davidge said:
A manifold is an collection of open sets
More precisely, a topological space (a manifold is a particular kind of topological space) is a set ##X## together with a collection ##\tau## of subsets of ##X## that satisfies three axioms: (1) the empty set and ##X## itself belong to the collection ##\tau##; (2) any union (finite or infinite) of members of ##\tau## also belongs to ##\tau##; (3) any
finite intersection of members of ##\tau## also belongs to ##\tau##. The subsets in ##\tau## are then called the "open sets" of the topology.
(A closed set is then any set whose complement in the set ##X## is open. You can see from this definition that the empty set and ##X## are both closed
and open. Note also that the terms "open" and "closed" here are
different from the terms "open" and "closed" as I was using them to describe intervals on the real line! Terminology here can quickly get confusing since the same terms can have several different meanings depending on the context.)
A manifold is a topological space with the additional property that every point has an open neighborhood which is homeomorphic to ##\mathbb{R}^n##, i.e., to Euclidean space of the appropriate dimension. Note that this does
not mean the manifold as a whole must be homeomorphic to ##\mathbb{R}^n##; the n-dimensional sphere, for example, is not.
davidge said:
suppose ##T## is the manifold consisting of all points ##t##, such that ##d(t, x_o) < r## for some ##x_o \in T## and ##r > 0##,
This is not sufficient as you state it, because you have not defined which subsets of the set ##T## are the open sets. To be strictly correct, you either need to do that explicitly or say something like "with the standard topology on the real numbers", which means that the open sets are just the open intervals. (Note that with this topology, the open interval ##T## itself is also a closed set in the topology, but it is
not a closed interval--in other words, this is an illustration of the difference in meanings of terms that I referred to above.)
davidge said:
and that ##f: T \rightarrow \mathbb{R}## through ##t \mapsto \tan(t)##.
Just to be clear, this is not part of the definition of the manifold.
davidge said:
If we choose ##t \in (0, \pi / 2)##, the image of the map would be ##(0, \infty)##
Yes.
davidge said:
If we choose ##t \in [0, \pi / 2]##,
Then you are contradicting your definition of the manifold ##T##, since that definition specified ##d(t, x_o) < r##, and this closed interval only satisfies ##d(t, x_o) \le r##.
davidge said:
the image still would be ##(0, \infty)##
Even leaving aside the objection I just made, this is not correct. ##0## itself is included in the image, since ##\tan t = 0## if ##t = 0##, and ##t = 0## is now included in the domain. And for ##t = \pi / 2##, ##\tan t## is undefined, so ##f## is no longer defined on the entire domain, so it isn't a valid function on the closed interval.
The question it looks like you are trying to get at here is, can the closed interval, ##t \in [0, \pi / 2]##, be considered a manifold? The answer is no, but not for the reason you give. The reason is that every point in the manifold must have an
open neighborhood that is homeomorphic to ##\mathbb{R}^n## (which in this case is just ##\mathbb{R}##). ##f## still defines a homeomorphism from ##T## to ##\mathbb{R}## on every
open interval in ##T## if ##T## is the closed interval ##[0, \pi / 2]##; that's not the problem. The problem is that the endpoints, ##t = 0## and ##t = \pi / 2##,
do not have an open neighborhood in ##T## at all! Any open set on the reals that contains ##t = 0## or ##t = \pi / 2## must contain points that are
outside the set ##[0, \pi / 2]##. That is why that set cannot be considered a manifold.