mike1000 said:
It is wave collapse that I do not think happens.
This is a permissible interpretation, yes. But there are also permissible interpretations in which collapse does happen. As I said before, we don't currently have any way of testing this experimentally, since both kinds of interpretations make the same predictions. Even if you favor a no collapse interpretation, it's still good to be aware that collapse interpretations exist and can't currently be ruled out by experiment.
mike1000 said:
the wave function is really giving us the apriori probabilities
If you favor a no collapse interpretation, you might run into problems trying to interpret the wave function this way. The most common no collapse interpretation, the many worlds interpretation, views the wave function as the actual physical state of the system. When a measurement happens, the state of the measuring device becomes entangled with the state of the measured system, so that there are multiple branches of the overall wave function, one branch for each possible result. For example, in the case of a spin-z measurement on an electron that is in a superposition of spin-z eigenstates, the evolution of the state through the measurement would look like this:
$$
\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \left( \vert \uparrow \rangle + \vert \downarrow \rangle \right) \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \left( \vert \uparrow \rangle \vert U \rangle + \vert \downarrow \rangle \vert D \rangle \right)
$$
where ##\uparrow## is the spin-z up eigenstate of the electron, ##\downarrow## is the spin-z down eigenstate of the electron, ##R## is the "ready to measure" state of the measuring device, ##U## is the "measured spin-z up" state of the measuring device, and ##D## is the "measured spin-z down" state of the measuring device. So the state after the measurement has two branches, one in which the electron is spin-z up and the measuring device has measured spin-z up, and the other in which the electron is spin-z down and the measuring device has measured spin-z down.
It is important to understand that the above expression, taken by itself, is
not actually interpretation dependent; it is just the straight math of QM, unitary evolution, applied to the initial state, under the assumption that the measuring device is a valid measuring device for spin-z. (That assumption is what ensures that the ##U## state gets entangled with the ##\uparrow## state, and the ##D## state with the ##\downarrow## state.) The interpretation comes in when you ask, what happens next? The two possibilities, broadly speaking, are:
(1) Collapse: The state of the entire system collapses to one or the other of the above branches. This is probably most lay people's intuitive interpretation of what happens, since intuitively we observe a single measurement result, not a superposition. (For how the MWI explains that, see below.) The problem with it is the collapse: how does it happen? It would have to be a non-unitary process, since unitary evolution can't make either branch just disappear. It would also be very difficult to see how it could be relativistically covariant, since the two branches could be spatially separated. There is a huge literature about this, but no resolution, it is an open question.
(2) No Collapse: Both branches continue to exist. This is the straightforward interpretation of the actual math, based on unitary evolution always being correct. At first it was thought that there was an obvious problem of us not observing a superposition but a single measurement result; but Hugh Everett resolved that when he published his Ph.D. thesis in 1957. He pointed out that, to be completely consistent, we would have to treat ourselves as quantum systems, so that our own quantum states, when we observed the results of a measuring device, would become entangled with the state of the device. So really, in the above evolution, the ##U## and ##D## states should mean, not just "measuring device measured spin-z up (or down)", but "all observers observe and agree that the measuring device measured spin-z up (or down)". In other words, you, I, and all other observers branch just like the measuring device branches: there are multiple copies of all of us, and each copy observes a single measurement result, and our own conscious experience is the conscious experience of a single copy.
The open problem with the MWI is actually how it can explain probabilities: how do you get the Born rule (that the probabilities of the possible results are proportional to the squares of their amplitudes in the wave function) out of the straight math of QM unitary evolution? Nobody has come up with a resolution to this, although there is a lot of literature on it. (Note that in collapse interpretations, the Born rule is not derived: it's just added as an extra postulate.) This is why I said you need to be careful about interpreting the wave function as giving probabilities, if you prefer a no collapse interpretation.