Peano axioms for natural numbers - prove 0.5 ∉ N

AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers around the Peano axioms and the proof that 0.5 is not a natural number. Participants clarify the definition of property P and its implications regarding natural numbers, emphasizing that if a number does not satisfy the axioms, it cannot be considered a natural number. The conversation highlights the equivalence of statements regarding the unprovability of P(x) and the relationship to the set of natural numbers. A key point is that the axioms imply that 0.5 does not meet the criteria for natural numbers, thus confirming its exclusion. The discussion concludes with an acknowledgment of the complexities surrounding provability in mathematical statements.
ato
Messages
30
Reaction score
0
i am studying real analysis from terence tao lecture notes for analysis I. http://www.math.ucla.edu/~tao/resource/general/131ah.1.03w/

from what i understand , property is just like any other statement. for example P(0.5) is P(0) with the 0s replaced with 0.5 . so the notes says (assumes ?),

##P(0.5)\textrm{ is unprovable}\Rightarrow0.5\notin N##

i mean its alright to assume something like but i just want to make sure that what i understood is correct. if it is why not just assume something like this,
##0.5\in N\textrm{ is unprovable}\Rightarrow0.5\notin N##

but i might be wrong, so in that case could you prove 0.5 ∉ N.

thank you
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Since you did not give a page number, I cannot tell what property P you are referring to, but I would presume that P(x) is something like x =0 \vee\existsy (y\inN \wedge x=y+1).

Before I answer the question further, please tell me what P(.) is.
 
OK, all clear: P is simply the variable in the axiom of induction, which can be seen formally here: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mathematical_induction#Axiom_of_induction. (Note that this does not require the domain of P to be N; it can only prove P for non-negative integers.) He omits a statement (or leaves it implicit) that "this is all the natural numbers": that is, if a number does not satisfy all the axioms, then it is not a natural number. (Here I follow the convention that 0 is included in the set of natural numbers. Some places don't, and just call N the set of non-negative integers.) So the author's reasoning is basically that 0.5 does not satisfy the axioms, hence is not a natural number. Therefore, the statements you listed are equivalent if you take P(x) being "x\inN".
 
nomadreid said:
Therefore, the statements you listed are equivalent if you take P(x) being "x∈N".

i was following alright until this. do you mean this is correct,
##P(x)\textrm{ is unprovable for }x\in N\Rightarrow x\notin N##
but then P(x) would never be unprovable (hence redundant) because ##P(x)## is true for ##x\in N##.
why would x∈N assumed as condition ? would not this require N to be known.

please clarify.
 
Remember my parenthetical remark that x does not have to be in N. You have introduced "\in"N where it wasn't before. That is, you had two statements
(1)
P(0.5) is unprovable⇒0.5∉N
and
(2)
0.5∈N is unprovable⇒0.5∉N
This latter quote is an instance of the addition that I mentioned was implicit,
(3)
"this is all the natural numbers".
and hence not surprising.
I suggested
(4)
take P(x) being "x∈N".
Applying (4) to (2), (2) morphs into (1). (And, of course, the contrary.) That's what I meant by the equivalence.
Applying (4) to your new statement
P(x) is unprovable for x∈N⇒x∉N
would give
(x∈N is unprovable for x∈N)⇒x∉N
which is a completely different statement, and would take us into that interesting area about true but unprovable statements... to quote from The Never-Ending Story (a good title for mathematics), "But that is another story and shall be told another time."
 
got it, thanks
 
Back
Top