I Understanding Hilbert Subspace for Two-Particle Entangled Systems

  • I
  • Thread starter Thread starter bluecap
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Hilbert Subspace
  • #51
PeterDonis said:
Yes. But what is the "system" is a matter of choice. It can be one atom, or it can be some small group of atoms, or it can be one atom or a small group of atoms inside a larger object like an apple or a pencil, or it can be a whole apple or pencil. It depends on the scenario and on what questions you are trying to answer.

No. The pointer states are really states of the apparatus, not the system. Go back and read my previous posts again.

In this Maximilian paper which is condense of his book. He wrote in page 14 of https://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0312059.pdf which doesn't mention about apparatrus but directly the system and environment and the pointer states between S and E (pls. comment):

"(1) When the dynamics of the system are dominated
by b HSE, i.e., the interaction with the environment, the pointer states will be eigenstates of b HSE (and thus typically eigenstates of position). This case corresponds to the typical quantum measurement setting; see, for example, the model of Zurek (1981, 1982), which is outlined in Sec. III.D.2 above.
(2) When the interaction with the environment is weak and b HS dominates the evolution of the system (that is, when the environment is “slow” in the above sense), a case that frequently occurs in the microscopic domain, pointer states will arise that are energy eigenstates of b HS (Paz and Zurek, 1999).
(3) In the intermediate case, when the evolution of the system is governed by b HSE and b HS in roughly equal strength, the resulting preferred states will represent a “compromise” between the first two cases; for instance, the frequently studied model of quantum Brownian motion has shown the emergence of pointer states localized in phase space, i.e., in both position and momentum (Eisert, 2004; Joos et al., 2003; Unruh and Zurek, 1989; Zurek, 2003b; Zurek et al., 1993)."

Einselection can be applied--at least if you agree with Zurek's model--to any system, apparatus, and environment. It in no way requires that the system be microscopic.

In your last last message you mentioned about measuring every atom of the pencil to measure the pointer states. But let's say you just take one atom as the system. Can you measure the particular atom to get its pointer states? But how do you handle the other billions of atoms interacting with your particular atom?

No. When you interact with something, you automatically perturb it. But the size of the perturbation, relative to the size of the something, depends on the something and the perturbation. You can perturb a pencil by bouncing a photon off of it; but the perturbation will be negligible.

That's not what the no cloning principle says. The no cloning principle says that, if you have an unknown quantum state, there is no way to duplicate it--i.e., to take a system in an unknown quantum state and make a second copy of that exact quantum state in a second system. But measuring a system does not require copying its state, so the no cloning principle says nothing about what you can or can't do with measurement.

I didn't say measuring things wouldn't perturb them. I said measuring things isn't the same as just perturbing them. Measuring is much harder.

Basically the same way Zurek does, by assuming that you can't keep track of all the degrees of freedom in the environment. Zurek isn't disagreeing with the conventional model of decoherence; he's adding to it, by trying to explain, not just how decoherence happens, but how the states that are left after decoherence somehow always turn out to be the "classical" states that we observe, rather than "Schrodinger's cat" type states. The conventional account of decoherence doesn't really address that (at least, Zurek doesn't think it does). I think it's still an open question at this point how all this is going to turn out.

Kastner seems to be saying that even if you can't keep tract of all the degrees of freedom in the environment, that doesn't mean you can produce a subsystem out of it. You need genuine phase randomization. What do you think?

I don't have his book so I can't comment on it. I don't know how widespread the three-way split into system, apparatus, and environment is; Zurek is the only place I've seen it, but that doesn't mean he's the only one who uses it.

See Maximilian condensed paper above...

I don't know how widespread Zurek's concept of "pointer states" is either. Lots of other QM texts use that term, but that doesn't mean they mean the same thing by it that Zurek does.

Here's a good paper about it called "Understanding the Pointer States" https://arxiv.org/abs/1508.04101
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
bluecap said:
how do you handle the other billions of atoms interacting with your particular atom?

Exactly. You just pointed out why it's not practical to measure a single atom in a macroscopic object like a pencil--because you can't isolate it from all the other atoms, the way you have to to measure a single atom in the lab.
 
  • #53
bluecap said:
What do you think?

I think, as I said before, that this is an open area of research and nobody knows what the "right" answers are at this point. So I'm not sure how fruitful further discussion of the various viewpoints is going to be.
 
  • #54
PeterDonis said:
Exactly. You just pointed out why it's not practical to measure a single atom in a macroscopic object like a pencil--because you can't isolate it from all the other atoms, the way you have to to measure a single atom in the lab.

But is it correct to say that even if you only want to measure the pointer states of one atom, you need to measure the rest of the 10^30 atoms just to get accurate measurements how the rest affect the pointer states of that one atom? So if you solve for the pure state of the object.. you could in principle understand or get the state of that one atom. Or let's take actual example of a qubit. If you can't isolate the qubit and it is interacting with the rest of the molecules. What happens if you measure the entire molecules (atom by atom).. then the effect is like knowing the state of the single qubit?

However, a more important point is that Zurek's equation (4) is highly schematic. He just waves his hands and assumes that there is some Hamiltonian ##H_{SE}## that entangles the system and the environment. But he can't write down any such Hamiltonian explicitly for any real object interacting with a real environment. Nobody can. Which means that neither he nor anyone else can write down the eigenstates of such a Hamiltonian--the states he labels with up and down arrows--explicitly either. This is very different from a controlled measurement in the lab, where we can in fact write down the explicit Hamiltonian and its eigenstates--for example, for a Stern-Gerlach apparatus for measuring spin.

About this environment very complex and difficult to write the Hamiltonian of real object interacting with a real environment.. Is it not like adding all the Hamiltonian together like Hse1 + Hse2 + Hse3 + Hse4 + Hse5 + Hse6 + Hse7 + Hse8 + Hse9 + Hse10 and so on? Is the reason we can't write or solve for it is due to insufficient computer processing power? Is it not like solving for the Schrodinger Equations of all the atoms of the molecules in quantum chemistry? But at least we have idea of how the dynamics or how solve for it. Just lack of computing powers. Why is the Hamiltonian of the environment and object any different?
 
  • #55
bluecap said:
is it correct to say that even if you only want to measure the pointer states of one atom, you need to measure the rest of the 10^30 atoms just to get accurate measurements how the rest affect the pointer states of that one atom?

If the atom is interacting with ##10^{30}## other atoms, because they're all part of the same macroscopic object, I'm not sure the concept of "pointer states" of that one atom even makes sense. (I'm not sure it makes sense for one atom even if the atom is isolated--that's why I said that to me, the pointer states really belong to the apparatus, not the system.)

bluecap said:
What happens if you measure the entire molecules (atom by atom).. then the effect is like knowing the state of the single qubit?

No.

bluecap said:
Is it not like adding all the Hamiltonian together

Hamiltonians don't just add that way. The Hamiltonian of a system of ##10^{30}## atoms is not just the sum of ##10^{30}## individual atom Hamiltonians. It also includes all the interactions, and we don't know what all those interactions are. We know the fundamentals--basically, interactions between atoms are based on electromagnetic forces--but that doesn't mean you can just put in, say, a Coulomb potential term for each pair of atoms. There are all kinds of collective effects involved, which even with quantum field theory we can only approximate.

bluecap said:
at least we have idea of how the dynamics

No, we don't. For that, we would have to know the Hamiltonian for the entire system, and we don't, not even conceptually. See above.
 
  • #56
PeterDonis said:
If the atom is interacting with ##10^{30}## other atoms, because they're all part of the same macroscopic object, I'm not sure the concept of "pointer states" of that one atom even makes sense. (I'm not sure it makes sense for one atom even if the atom is isolated--that's why I said that to me, the pointer states really belong to the apparatus, not the system.)

Ok. I believe you that the pointer states has to do with the apparatus. This paper is a valid source since it is summary of Zurek and others idea about Pointer States. https://arxiv.org/abs/1508.04101 But something puzzles me. The environment is not just entangled to the apparatus.. it is also entangled to the systems. So what is the side effect of this direct system-environment entanglement. In the paper in page 10:

"4.1 Example
In Sec. 3 we analysed the process of pre-measurement and, at this stage, we considered only the main system S and the measurement apparatus A. Let us now approach the complete process, from the initial evolution of the system until the measurement, step-by-step. Our analysis involves:

• the initial evolution of the system S and the measurement apparatus A, without interaction between them;
• the pre-measurement process, with the interaction between S and A;
• the beginning of the measurement process, with the introduction of the environment B, interacting with A;
• the determination of the evolution under the effects of the environment;
• the average of the environmental effects;
• the end of the measurement process, with analysis of the final S + A state after a long time."

and a few paragraphs prior, the author said:

"We will follow here the Zurek’s work [27]. If ˆ PA is the observable we wish to measure, an ideal apparatus will leave the system in one of the eigenstates of ˆ PA, not any relative state, but we have already seen this is not a simple task. In introducing the environment in the description, Zurek [27] imposed some conditions that had to be satisfied. In his original article, he admits these conditions are stronger than necessary, and for this reason here we will keep only two of them:
1. The environment does not interact with the system (i.e. ˆ HSB = 0). Otherwise, the state of the system would keep suffering environmental interference after the end of the measurement. (This could mean two repeated measurements of the same observable could give different results, which is against the tenets of quantum mechanics.)
2. The system-observer interaction is well-localized in time."

Or let's say you don't think the paper is correct.

What is the effect of this direct interaction between the environment and system? The trinity of system, apparatus, environment assumes the interaction is between system and apparatus.. then between apparatus and environment.. but surely the system is directly interacting with the environment too.. is it not? If you know of example of the apparatus being part of the objects or molecules.. please share it because I'm assuming the apparatus is separate from the object... but still environmental decoherence both engage the system and apparatus.. not just the apparatus.
No.
Hamiltonians don't just add that way. The Hamiltonian of a system of ##10^{30}## atoms is not just the sum of ##10^{30}## individual atom Hamiltonians. It also includes all the interactions, and we don't know what all those interactions are. We know the fundamentals--basically, interactions between atoms are based on electromagnetic forces--but that doesn't mean you can just put in, say, a Coulomb potential term for each pair of atoms. There are all kinds of collective effects involved, which even with quantum field theory we can only approximate.
No, we don't. For that, we would have to know the Hamiltonian for the entire system, and we don't, not even conceptually. See above.
 
  • #57
bluecap said:
The environment is not just entangled to the apparatus.. it is also entangled to the systems.

It's entangled with the system because of its entanglement with the apparatus. The environment and the system don't interact directly--at least not in a typical "lab" measurement where we take care to isolate the system. The quote you give appears to agree with that; it says the environment B interacts with A (the apparatus). It doesn't say B interacts with S (the system); only A does.

bluecap said:
What is the effect of this direct interaction between the environment and system?

There doesn't seem to be any such thing in any of the quotes you give.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #58
PeterDonis said:
It's entangled with the system because of its entanglement with the apparatus. The environment and the system don't interact directly--at least not in a typical "lab" measurement where we take care to isolate the system. The quote you give appears to agree with that; it says the environment B interacts with A (the apparatus). It doesn't say B interacts with S (the system); only A does.
There doesn't seem to be any such thing in any of the quotes you give.

I'm referring to decoherence and open systems where the system is not isolated or not the typical lab measurement. Zurek concept of Pointer States occur for macroscopic object where it is not isolated.. So think of the environment causing loss of coherence in the pointer states of the apparatus that prevents the cat alive and dead superposition (or other superpositions), the same environment can also cause loss of superpositions of the system so the system can no longer have dead and alive cats.. but won't this be redundant the environment affect both system and apparatus at same time?
 
  • #59
bluecap said:
think of the environment causing loss of coherence in the pointer states of the apparatus that prevents the cat alive and dead superposition (or other superpositions), the same environment can also cause loss of superpositions of the system so the system can no longer have dead and alive cats

Once again, I don't see anything in what you've quoted from the papers that says the environment interacts with the system directly; it interacts with the apparatus, and that interaction with the apparatus, since the apparatus is already entangled with the system, entangles the environment with the system.
 
  • #60
PeterDonis said:
Once again, I don't see anything in what you've quoted from the papers that says the environment interacts with the system directly; it interacts with the apparatus, and that interaction with the apparatus, since the apparatus is already entangled with the system, entangles the environment with the system.

or see directly this Zurek paper: https://arxiv.org/pdf/0903.5082.pdf

"Interactions that depend on a certain observable correlate it with the environment, so its eigenstates are singled out, and phase relations between such pointer states are lost [6]. "
"Negative selection due to decoherence is the essence of environment-induced superselection, or einselection [7]: Under scrutiny of the environment, only pointer states remain unchanged. Other states decohere into mixtures of stable pointer states that can persist, and, in this sense, exist: They are einselected."

Think of this setup. You have an apple on the table and an apparatus to measure it's position. The environment is exposed to both the system and apparatus. In decoherence, the system is open.. it is not isolated. so it's exposed to the environment same as the apparatus.
 
  • #61
PeterDonis said:
Once again, I don't see anything in what you've quoted from the papers that says the environment interacts with the system directly; it interacts with the apparatus, and that interaction with the apparatus, since the apparatus is already entangled with the system, entangles the environment with the system.

I think when system is directly exposed to the environment. We can bypass apparatus which is only used if system is isolated to environment so apparatus acts as interface between them. In the same Zurek paper, the following is clear that he only deals with system and environment and omits any apparatus:

"These ideas can be made precise. The basic tool is the reduced density matrix ρS. It represents the state of the system that obtains from the composite state ΨSE of S and E by tracing out the environment E: ρS = TrE|ΨSEihΨSE| . (1) Evolution of ρS reveals preferred states: It is most predictable when the system starts in a pointer state. To quantify this one can use (von Neumann) entropy, HS = H(ρS) = −TrρS lgρS, as a function of time. Pointer states result in smallest entropy increase. By contrast, their superpositions produce entropy rapidly, at decoherence rates, especially when S is macroscopic."

So "when S is macroscopic" and directly exposed to environment. We can use pointer states directly on the system.. right?
 
  • #62
bluecap said:
So "when S is macroscopic" and directly exposed to environment. We can use pointer states directly on the system.. right?

I'm not sure. For example, if you "measure" an apple's position by looking at it (and perhaps comparing it with a ruler or a grid of coordinates marked on the table it's sitting on), the "apparatus" is photons bouncing off the apple (and the ruler/grid/table, etc.) and coming into your eyes (and perhaps your eyes themselves). The "system" is the apple, and the "environment" is everything else. You are correct that both the system and the apparatus interact with the environment, but the environment interaction that counts is with the apparatus. Basically, multiple people can look at photons bouncing off the apple and agree on its position, because there are so many photons. But there are so many photons because the environment is basically an inexhaustible source of them, and the information that each person receives through their eyes gets stored in other environment degrees of freedom like their brains, the sound waves they emit when they describe what they see, etc. None of this involves any interaction with the system--the only interaction with the system that made any difference was the photons bouncing off the apple.

Zurek's formulation in the paper you link to here, which doesn't include an "apparatus", is unclear to me in an example like the above. Would he include the photons bouncing off the apple in the "system" or the "environment"? Neither one seems right to me; the photons seem like an "apparatus", which isn't the same as the system (since the photons don't stay localized at the apple), but isn't the same as the environment either (because other degrees of freedom don't interact with the apple, at least not in a way that makes any difference in the scenario above).

But as I said before, all this is an open area of research, so I'm not sure how much weight to put on any particular description of it.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #63
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure. For example, if you "measure" an apple's position by looking at it (and perhaps comparing it with a ruler or a grid of coordinates marked on the table it's sitting on), the "apparatus" is photons bouncing off the apple (and the ruler/grid/table, etc.) and coming into your eyes (and perhaps your eyes themselves). The "system" is the apple, and the "environment" is everything else. You are correct that both the system and the apparatus interact with the environment, but the environment interaction that counts is with the apparatus. Basically, multiple people can look at photons bouncing off the apple and agree on its position, because there are so many photons. But there are so many photons because the environment is basically an inexhaustible source of them, and the information that each person receives through their eyes gets stored in other environment degrees of freedom like their brains, the sound waves they emit when they describe what they see, etc. None of this involves any interaction with the system--the only interaction with the system that made any difference was the photons bouncing off the apple.

Zurek's formulation in the paper you link to here, which doesn't include an "apparatus", is unclear to me in an example like the above. Would he include the photons bouncing off the apple in the "system" or the "environment"? Neither one seems right to me; the photons seem like an "apparatus", which isn't the same as the system (since the photons don't stay localized at the apple), but isn't the same as the environment either (because other degrees of freedom don't interact with the apple, at least not in a way that makes any difference in the scenario above).

But as I said before, all this is an open area of research, so I'm not sure how much weight to put on any particular description of it.

I'm trying to relate what you mentioned above about the scattering photons being apparatus to what this Maximilian book is saying. In page 74:
"For the simple example of the system-environment interaction given by (2.78), we immediately see that a system that starts out in either one of the states |psi1> and |psi2> will not get entangled with the environment: The final composite system-environment state will at all times remain in the separable product forms|psi1>|E1> and |psi2>|E2> respectively. Thus the environment can be regarded as carrying out a quantum nondemolition measurement on the system. i.e. a measurement that does not disturb the state of the system. In the case of the scattering of environment particles discussed above, |psi1> and |psi2> represent spatially well-localized states, and accordingly the environment-superselected preferred observable is the position of the system. Conversely, if the system is described by the superposition (2.70) of |psi1> and |psi2> , it will become maximally entangled with the environment, leading to decoherence in the {|psi1> , psi2> } basis. The system observable corresponding to the measurement of a superposition of positions would there be "difficult" to measure, in the sense that the spatial interference terms in the reduced matrix corresponding to a measurement of this observable decay rapidly due to the interaction with the environment."

How do you use the concept of maximal entanglement here (monogamy?). How come if the system is described by the superposition (2.70) of |psi1> and |psi2> will they be maximally entangled with the environment while if |psi1> and |psi2> are separated, it will remain in the separable product forms |psi1>|E1> and |psi2>|E2> respectively (the comment in page 71 described this "We motivated this form of the interaction by referring to the fact that the states |psi1> and |psi2> correspond to sufficiently distinct physical states of the system (such as different spatial positions and orientations of a body), and this difference is resolved by the environment continuously monitoring the system.".. and this refers to page 67 "Supposed the system is described by a coherent superposition of two quantum states |psi1> and |psi2> representing localization around two different positions x1 and x2 (in the case of the double-slit experiment, the corresponding position space wave functions psi1(x) and psi2(x) would represent the partial waves at the slits)."

Thanks!
 
  • #64
bluecap said:
How do you use the concept of maximal entanglement here (monogamy?)

Maximal entanglement isn't the same thing as monogamy of entanglement, though they are related. Monogamy of entanglement basically says that a subsystem can't be maximally entangled with more than one other subsystem.

I'm not sure what you mean by "how do you use the concept".

bluecap said:
How come if the system is described by the superposition (2.70) of |psi1> and |psi2> will they be maximally entangled with the environment while if |psi1> and |psi2> are separated, it will remain in the separable product forms |psi1>|E1> and |psi2>|E2> respectively

Because that's how the interaction with the environment works. It's just unitary evolution. It's no different in principle from putting a spin up or spin down electron through a vertically oriented Stern Gerlach device, vs. putting a spin left electron (equal superposition of spin up and spin down) through it. At least, that's the type of model that it looks like Maximilian is using. The only difference is that here the "system" (as well as the apparatus) is made up of many quantum particles, not just one.
 
  • #65
PeterDonis said:
Maximal entanglement isn't the same thing as monogamy of entanglement, though they are related. Monogamy of entanglement basically says that a subsystem can't be maximally entangled with more than one other subsystem.

I'm not sure what you mean by "how do you use the concept".
Because that's how the interaction with the environment works. It's just unitary evolution. It's no different in principle from putting a spin up or spin down electron through a vertically oriented Stern Gerlach device, vs. putting a spin left electron (equal superposition of spin up and spin down) through it. At least, that's the type of model that it looks like Maximilian is using. The only difference is that here the "system" (as well as the apparatus) is made up of many quantum particles, not just one.

My question really was. If the system is described by the superposition of |psi1> and |psi2> , and it will become maximally entangled with the environment, and lead to decoherence in the {|psi1> , psi2> } basis. How come the system observable corresponding to the measurement of a superposition of positions would there be "difficult" to measure (in the sense that the spatial interference terms in the reduced matrix corresponding to a measurement of this observable decay rapidly due to the interaction with the environment). You earlier just described the photons reflecting off the object. But now we have to consider it directly interacting with the system. Do you have example of system being maximally entangled with the environment and the setup difficulty getting the preferred observable or basis? Contrast this with the case where the final composite system-environment state will at all times remain in the separable product forms|psi1>|E1> and |psi2>|E2>respectively. Here how come "the environment can be regarded as carrying out a quantum nondemolition measurement on the system. i.e. a measurement that does not disturb the state of the system.". In this message we are.not just describing photons reflecting from object but interacting with the object. Thanks!
 
  • #66
bluecap said:
My question really was

Instead of trying to answer this as you ask it, I'm going to try to rephrase it to simplify things.

The environment's interaction with the system picks out a "preferred" basis of states, which in this example are position eigenstates. (Technically those aren't actually states since they aren't normalizable, and you have to do a fair bit of mathematical work to make all this rigorous, but we'll ignore that here.)

If we use that basis, it is obvious that if the system is in a position eigenstate, measuring its position doesn't change its state; that is what he is talking about when he describes this case as a "quantum nondemolition" measurement.

If we use the position basis, it is also obvious that if the system is in a superposition of two position eigenstates, measuring its position, which is what the environment is doing (that's why the environment picks out the position basis), will entangle the system with the measuring device (which in this case is the environment), so you will end up with two branches, each corresponding to one of the position eigenstates and the corresponding "measured that position" state of the environment (i.e., the environment state that stores the information that that particular position was measured). The branches will then decohere.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #67
PeterDonis said:
Instead of trying to answer this as you ask it, I'm going to try to rephrase it to simplify things.

The environment's interaction with the system picks out a "preferred" basis of states, which in this example are position eigenstates. (Technically those aren't actually states since they aren't normalizable, and you have to do a fair bit of mathematical work to make all this rigorous, but we'll ignore that here.)

If we use that basis, it is obvious that if the system is in a position eigenstate, measuring its position doesn't change its state; that is what he is talking about when he describes this case as a "quantum nondemolition" measurement.

If we use the position basis, it is also obvious that if the system is in a superposition of two position eigenstates, measuring its position, which is what the environment is doing (that's why the environment picks out the position basis), will entangle the system with the measuring device (which in this case is the environment), so you will end up with two branches, each corresponding to one of the position eigenstates and the corresponding "measured that position" state of the environment (i.e., the environment state that stores the information that that particular position was measured). The branches will then decohere.
Thanks..in an apple, how many percentage of the particles are in approx eigenstates of position and how many percentage are in superposition of approx position eigenstates? (I mentioned approx bec I'm aware that HUP disallows exact position of eigenstates). What must you do to the apple to change the percentage of each of the above (between approx eigenstates of position vs superpositions of approx eigenstates of position)?

Anyway I believe you now that the pointer states (or preferred states) are a result of joint system environment (or even apparatus) processes so observer can't perturb the pointer states directly. After 5 years. I finally understood it (thanks to you).. but it's bittersweet knowing the limitation of the model of Einselection and even quantum darwinism.
 
  • #68
PeterDonis said:
If we use the position basis, it is also obvious that if the system is in a superposition of two position eigenstates, measuring its position, which is what the environment is doing (that's why the environment picks out the position basis), will entangle the system with the measuring device (which in this case is the environment), so you will end up with two branches, each corresponding to one of the position eigenstates and the corresponding "measured that position" state of the environment (i.e., the environment state that stores the information that that particular position was measured). The branches will then decohere.
I thought you discuss about photons. How can you have a "position basis" then? Photons don't have a position. You cannot define a position operator for massless quanta with spin ##\geq 1##!
 
  • #69
bluecap said:
in an apple, how many percentage of the particles are in approx eigenstates of position and how many percentage are in superposition of approx position eigenstates?

The atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. There isn't really any difference from one atom to another, so it doesn't really make sense to ask "what percentage" are in one state (or one kind of entanglement) vs. another.
 
  • #70
vanhees71 said:
I thought you discuss about photons.

We've been bouncing around among different examples. You're correct that there is no "position basis" for photons, but there is for, e.g, atoms in an apple (with the caveats I mentioned earlier).
 
  • #71
PeterDonis said:
The atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. There isn't really any difference from one atom to another, so it doesn't really make sense to ask "what percentage" are in one state (or one kind of entanglement) vs. another.

I know that a macroscopic object like an apple has an enormous number of internal degrees of freedom and therefore an enormous number interactions inside it, so there is decoherence right inside the apple hence many states inside are constantly decohering. In other words, the environments and systems are right inside the apple. Therefore it seems a macroscopic object is not ideal thing for quantum darwinism? I mean.. Zurek focuses on fragments and invariance of the fragments and even deriving the born rule from it. But is it not the fragments that we see are only from the surface of the apple. How does quantum darwinism handle the fragments right inside the apple inside. In the book example of approx eigenstates of position and superposition of approx eigenstates of position. They are just simple system. In an apple, the states have so many interactions inside.. but you can't see the fragments inside the apple.. so does it mean for big object like an apple, it is useless for quantum darwism analysis?

Also when you said the atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. This is only completely true for diamond or crystals as they form one energy band.. is it not? The apple has holes inside them microscopically where some liquid moves.. therefore is it right to think they are not completely entangled as solid band.. but multiple entanglement areas or domains or portion inside the apple?

Also the surface cover membrane of the apple (red) is different from the inside (dirty white color meat). So they are not really fully entangled? Now about the photons hitting the apple surface.. I think it's more like it entangled with the approx eigenstates of position hence nothing happening instead of the photons entangling with the apple surface superposition of approx eigenstates position.. although it's possible we only have many mixed states from the superposition that has decohered already from the Cosmic Microwave Background Radiation or thermal phonons hitting the surface of the apple? If you are saying the entire surface of the apple is entangled.. then how do the photons or CMBR interacted with the single entangled apple surface?

Thank you!
 
  • #72
bluecap said:
it seems a macroscopic object is not ideal thing for quantum darwinism?

Why not? The fact that we always observe macroscopic objects in classical states is exactly what quantum darwinism is trying to explain.

If you mean, it's hard to see all the details working in a macroscopic object, yes, that's true. Welcome to physics, where the interesting problems are not easy. :wink:

bluecap said:
when you said the atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. This is only completely true for diamond or crystals as they form one energy band.. is it not?

No. Any macroscopic object will have its individual atoms entangled in all sorts of ways.

bluecap said:
The apple has holes inside them microscopically where some liquid moves.. therefore is it right to think they are not completely entangled as solid band.. but multiple entanglement areas or domains or portion inside the apple?

No. The liquid moving inside the apple is still interacting strongly with the rest of the apple, so it's entangled with the rest of the apple.

bluecap said:
the surface cover membrane of the apple (red) is different from the inside (dirty white color meat). So they are not really fully entangled?

What do you mean by "fully entangled"? If you mean maximally entangled, probably very few of the atoms anywhere in the apple are maximally entangled with other ones. Maximal entanglement usually requires a very precise preparation procedure.

The skin of the apple might be somewhat less entangled with the inside than either the skin or the inside are with themselves. But they're still interacting strongly, so they're still entangled. If they weren't entangled, the apple would not stay together; it would just fall apart (or the skin would just fall off, instead of having to be peeled).

bluecap said:
how do the photons or CMBR interacted with the single entangled apple surface?

Um, by interacting with them? I don't understand why you would see a problem here. Photons interact with atoms in objects all the time; that's how we see the objects.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #73
PeterDonis said:
We've been bouncing around among different examples. You're correct that there is no "position basis" for photons, but there is for, e.g, atoms in an apple (with the caveats I mentioned earlier).

According to Maximilian:

"System-environment interaction Hamiltonian frequently describe a scattering process of surrounding particles (photons, air molecules, etc.) interacting with the system under study. Since the force laws describing such processes typically depend on some power of distance (such as alpha r^-2) in Newton's or Coulombs' force law) the interaction Hamiltonian will usually commute with the position operator. According to the commutativity requirement (2.89), the pointer states will therefore be approximate eigenstates of position. The fact that position is typically the determinate property of our experience can thus be explained by referring to the dependency of most interactions on distance."

I'm trying to relate this to Vanheez71 statement: "I thought you discuss about photons. How can you have a "position basis" then? Photons don't have a position. You cannot define a position operator for massless quanta with spin ≥ 1 !"

Now consider first the Schrodinger equation. The position basis is implicit in the normal form of the Schrodinger equation. When expressed in that basis virtually all interactions turn out to be radial ie the V(x) in the Schrodinger equation.

Is it true that this is because the universe originally has chosen position preferred basis in the initial decomposition of the everettian universe. Let me summarize it (or elaborate):

There are 2 kinds of preferred basis. First is the original preferred basis that originally created the universe first subsystems (or decomposing systems and environment) in the everettian universe (without basis). The second preferred basis is from the pointer states (or preferred states) you get from present system-environment Einselection. So Demystifier once said that without the initial preferred basis decomposition, the radial thing interaction choosing position basis won't even work. Therefore can it be that even if the photon doesn't have position basis, the mere existence of photons already assume the universe has initially chosen the position basis as preferred (think of the Nothing Happens in Many Worlds discussions way back).

Or to make it more illustrative.. what if you suddenly remove the initial prefer basis that cause the initial system-environment (subsystem) decomposition in the everettian universe (originally without any basis), would distance suddenly disappear in our universe that our Earth would become a mere point? is the initial prefer basis choosing position the reason why particles are separate and there are photons in the surrounding? This means even if the photon doesn't have position, the fact we can see it have dynamics is because of the initial decomposition of the everettian universe which uses position as preferred?
 
  • #74
bluecap said:
I'm trying to relate this to Vanheez71 statement:

The position eigenstates Maximilian is talking about are for the atoms in the object, not for the photons that bounce off the object.

bluecap said:
consider first the Schrodinger equation

The Schrodinger equation can't be used to describe photons. It only works for non-relativistic particles (i.e., particles moving much slower than light).

The rest of your post just appears to build on the mistaken assumption that it is possible to give photons a position basis. It isn't. @vanhees71 is correct about that.
 
  • #75
PeterDonis said:
Why not? The fact that we always observe macroscopic objects in classical states is exactly what quantum darwinism is trying to explain.

If you mean, it's hard to see all the details working in a macroscopic object, yes, that's true. Welcome to physics, where the interesting problems are not easy. :wink:

No. Any macroscopic object will have its individual atoms entangled in all sorts of ways.

We always heard that for entanglement experiment like Aspect experiment. It is very hard because you have to isolate it to avoid decoherence. Is the reason because you are trying to isolate the information? Contrast this with decoherence with object where entanglement occurs anywhere without isolation. Is this because you are not isolating or manipulating any single information. Just want to verify if this is correct thinking. So it means even if there are two apples 1 foot apart.. the apples are still entangled?? What is the minimum distance between any object is entangled?
No. The liquid moving inside the apple is still interacting strongly with the rest of the apple, so it's entangled with the rest of the apple.

Have you heard about this so called Decoherence Free Subspaces. Is there a way to do this inside the apple or other objects by manipulating with laser to cause a domain free from decoherence?

What do you mean by "fully entangled"? If you mean maximally entangled, probably very few of the atoms anywhere in the apple are maximally entangled with other ones. Maximal entanglement usually requires a very precise preparation procedure.

The skin of the apple might be somewhat less entangled with the inside than either the skin or the inside are with themselves. But they're still interacting strongly, so they're still entangled. If they weren't entangled, the apple would not stay together; it would just fall apart (or the skin would just fall off, instead of having to be peeled).

Just want to know why entanglement monogamy doesn't stop all the entanglement of the apple. You said "Monogamy of entanglement basically says that a subsystem can't be maximally entangled with more than one other subsystem." But yet all the apple is entangled with billions of entanglement.. what does it mean for the apple to be maximally entangled? Can you give example of how to cause two particles of the apple to be maximally entangled?

Um, by interacting with them? I don't understand why you would see a problem here. Photons interact with atoms in objects all the time; that's how we see the objects.

Thanks so much.
 
  • #76
PeterDonis said:
The position eigenstates Maximilian is talking about are for the atoms in the object, not for the photons that bounce off the object.
The Schrodinger equation can't be used to describe photons. It only works for non-relativistic particles (i.e., particles moving much slower than light).

The rest of your post just appears to build on the mistaken assumption that it is possible to give photons a position basis. It isn't. @vanhees71 is correct about that.

But in the example we were talking about or in the book too. It is photons from the environment that either entangled with the approx. eigenstates of position that "doesn't do anything to the system" or entangling with the superposition of approx. eigenstates of positions causing decoherence. If it is not photons from environment. then what is? If it's photons and photons don't have positions.. perhaps the reason the position eigenstates is chosen is because the atoms or particles in the system can define a position operator and this is what caused the pointer states to be eigenstates of position instead of momentum or the self Hamiltonian (energy of the system)?
 
  • #77
PeterDonis said:
The atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. There isn't really any difference from one atom to another, so it doesn't really make sense to ask "what percentage" are in one state (or one kind of entanglement) vs. another.

This is the vital part. You said above the atoms are all entangled so they don't have definite states by themselves. So does this mean the photons or whatever in the environment shouldn't interact with an atom only or a few because these don't have definite state? That's why I asked "how do the photons or CMBR interacted with the single entangled apple surface?" where you replied: "Um, by interacting with them? I don't understand why you would see a problem here. Photons interact with atoms in objects all the time; that's how we see the objects.". So do you mean when photons or others interact with an object where all the atoms are entangled. The photons or something interacts with the whole molecules as entangled object as same time (not with any of the atoms because the entangled parts don't have definite state)?

In short.. are you saying it's a Quantum Field Theory situation where the entire apple and photon need to be considered together.. meaning no photon interacts with any of the atom since any atom has no definite state?

Also this means you as Peter has all your atoms entangled in your body so they don't have definite state. But when I shake your hands.. how come I'm shaking the atoms and molecules of your hands only and not the entire entangled QFT thing in your whole body at once?
 
  • #78
bluecap said:
It is very hard because you have to isolate it to avoid decoherence. Is the reason because you are trying to isolate the information?

No, it's because you are trying to isolate the system you want to measure from any interactions other than the specific interaction you are using to measure it.

bluecap said:
So it means even if there are two apples 1 foot apart.. the apples are still entangled?

To some extent, because there are photons, air molecules, etc. bouncing between both apples; but the apples are entangled with each other to a much lesser extent than each apple is entangled with itself. That's why we can view the two apples as separate classical objects.

Btw, I feel like this answer should have been obvious. You might want to spend more time thinking these things through before you ask questions.

bluecap said:
Have you heard about this so called Decoherence Free Subspaces

No. Do you have a reference?

bluecap said:
Just want to know why entanglement monogamy doesn't stop all the entanglement of the apple.

Because the apple isn't maximally entangled with anyone thing.

I feel like this answer should also have been obvious. See my comment above about thinking things through.

bluecap said:
Can you give example of how to cause two particles of the apple to be maximally entangled?

You should be able to get this from a modern QM textbook.

bluecap said:
If it's photons and photons don't have positions.. perhaps the reason the position eigenstates is chosen is because the atoms or particles in the system can define a position operator

I already answered this. See the first sentence I wrote in post #74.

bluecap said:
does this mean the photons or whatever in the environment shouldn't interact with an atom only or a few because these don't have definite state?

No. This answer should also be obvious; there are plenty of quantum experiments where one particle of an entangled pair is measured. That could not be done if it wasn't possible to interact with a particle that doesn't have a definite state by itself (because it's entangled with something else).
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #79
PeterDonis said:
No, it's because you are trying to isolate the system you want to measure from any interactions other than the specific interaction you are using to measure it.

To some extent, because there are photons, air molecules, etc. bouncing between both apples; but the apples are entangled with each other to a much lesser extent than each apple is entangled with itself. That's why we can view the two apples as separate classical objects.

Btw, I feel like this answer should have been obvious. You might want to spend more time thinking these things through before you ask questions.

No. Do you have a reference?

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Decoherence-free_subspaces

But I think it's useless for apples.. it can only happen in let's say Bose-Einsten condensates...

I wonder if Penrose can apply it to his microtubules in the brain.. will read his stuff next week with all this basic background... anyway Maximilian book says:

"Pointer subspaces, or DFS, have attracted much interest over the past decade because of their relevance in quantum computing. These the basic idea is to encode the fragile quantum information stored in the quantum computer in such subspaces so as to naturally protect it from decoherence. We will describe this approach in more detail in Sec. 7.5 (see also the review article by Lidar and Whaley [101]. The ideas behind pointer subspaces have also been used to propose methods for taming decoherence in other areas of interest, for example, in the context of superposition states of macroscopically distinguishable states in Bose-Einstein condensates [102] (see Sect. 6.4.1).

Because the apple isn't maximally entangled with anyone thing.

I feel like this answer should also have been obvious. See my comment above about thinking things through.
You should be able to get this from a modern QM textbook.
I already answered this. See the first sentence I wrote in post #74.
No. This answer should also be obvious; there are plenty of quantum experiments where one particle of an entangled pair is measured. That could not be done if it wasn't possible to interact with a particle that doesn't have a definite state by itself (because it's entangled with something else).
Consider ##
\vert \Psi' \rangle \vert E \rangle = \left( a \vert + \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \vert D \rangle \right) \vert E \rangle
\rightarrow
a \vert + \rangle \vert U \rangle \vert E_U \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \vert D \rangle \vert E_D \rangle##

I thought when something in the environment entangled with the system... it's the entire quantum state.. not just one term of it.. you are saying above that one term can be entangled with? I thought you that when something is entangled with a new thing.. it's new terms added.. for example:

##\Psi_0 = \left( a_1 \vert u_1 \rangle + b_1 \vert d_1 \rangle \right) \left( a_2 \vert u_2 \rangle + b_2 \vert d_2 \rangle \right) \vert R_1, R_2 \rangle \vert O_{R1}, O_{R2} \rangle##
##
\rightarrow \Psi_1 = \left( a_2 \vert u_2 \rangle + b_2 \vert d_2 \rangle \right) \left( a_1 \vert u_1 \rangle \vert U_1, R_2 \rangle \vert O_{U1}, O_{R2} \rangle + b_1 \vert d_1 \rangle \vert D_1, R_2 \rangle \vert O_{D1}, O_{R2} \rangle \right)##
##
\rightarrow \Psi_2 = a_1 a_2 \vert u_1 \rangle \vert u_2 \rangle \vert U_1, U_2 \rangle \vert O_{U1}, O_{U2} \rangle + a_1 b_2 \vert u_1 \rangle \vert d_2 \rangle \vert U_1, D_2 \rangle \vert O_{U1}, O_{D2} \rangle \\ + b_1 a_2 \vert d_1 \rangle \vert u_2 \rangle \vert D_1, U_2 \rangle \vert O_{D1}, O_{U2} \rangle + b_1 b_2 \vert d_1 \rangle \vert d_2 \rangle \vert D_1, D_2 \rangle \vert O_{D1}, O_{D2} \rangle##

Each time a measurement happens, it creates another entanglement. So after two measurements, we have an entangled state containing four terms, one corresponding to each possible combination of the results of the two measurements.

How is this compatible with what you just said above that only one particle of an entangled pair is measured? How would the math of what you described looks like. You mean putting the system into mixed state? Then making new entanglement? But how would the photon know whether it should be entangled with the entire system or only one part of it (which doesn't even have any state)?
 
  • #80
bluecap said:
you are saying above that one term can be entangled with?

No.

bluecap said:
How is this compatible with what you just said above that only one particle of an entangled pair is measured?

The math you wrote down is for measurement of a single particle that's not entangled with anything before the measurement. You need to look up the math for a measurement of one particle of an entangled pair; this is a common case in quantum computing so it should be easy to find examples.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #81
PeterDonis said:
No.
The math you wrote down is for measurement of a single particle that's not entangled with anything before the measurement. You need to look up the math for a measurement of one particle of an entangled pair; this is a common case in quantum computing so it should be easy to find examples.

Is it the math of reduced density matrix and improper mixed states? I'm familiar with the math of these. If it's not. Please just mention me what is the math called when one particle of an entangled pair can be measured without any collapse or born rule applied or breaking the entanglement so I can look for the particular math or concept. Thanks.
 
  • #82
bluecap said:
Is it the math of reduced density matrix and improper mixed states?

No. Look up, for example, Bell state measurements for quantum "teleportation".
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap

Similar threads

Back
Top