Sherlock said:
Or the traveller could keep heading away from Earth or whatever. But the question I was responding to involved the round trip scenario.
JesseM said:
If they pass each other at a single point in space, that is a round trip scenario, because there can only be a single objective answer to what their clocks read at the moment they pass, it can't be different for different reference frames.
Sherlock said:
Ok, but wrt my reply to the original questioner, we were talking about the scenario where clock A is eventually returned to it's starting position next to clock B.
What you're not understanding is that "passing at a single point in space" is the same as "returning to its original starting location" (at least, it would be the 'original starting location' in the Earth's frame). Whether the traveler changes velocity and comes to rest relative to the earthbound observer at that location, or simply passes by the earthbound observer instantaneously, makes no difference to the problem, because we're only interested in what their clocks read at the moment they first reunite.
Sherlock said:
The questioner was apparently of the opinion that the landing approach would cancel the effects of the takeoff, not realizing that even on slowing down wrt the earth, though the timekeeping rates of the traveller's clocks (biological or artificial) are becoming ever closer to what they were while on the earth, the periods of the oscillators are still larger than what they were on earth.
JesseM said:
Or the period of the oscillators are smaller than what they were on earth, it depends what frame you use.
Sherlock said:
If the period was smaller than on earth, then clock A would record *more* time during it's trip than clock B.
All you can say is that the
average period of clock A's ticks throughout the trip is larger than period of clock B's ticks. But since clock A changes velocities, the period of its ticks will not be constant in most frames. You referred specifically to what would happen during the return portion of the trip as clock A changed velocity to come to rest relative to clock B; there are certainly frames where clock A's ticks during the inbound leg of the trip are shorter than those of clock B, but this is balanced by the fact that in these frames, clock A's ticks during the outbound leg are longer than those of clock B. So at the end of the inbound leg when clock A changes velocity to come to rest relative to clock B (assuming this actually happens, as I said earlier you could also just have them pass each other instantaneously and compare clocks then), in these frames clock A's ticks are
shorter than those of clock B but are getting longer as it gets closer to B's velocity.
JesseM said:
Since accelerating the Earth isn't too plausible, let's change the earth-twin to a twin on a space station, but otherwise the situation is the same--the ship and the station are initially at rest relative to each other at a single location, then they begin to move apart, then the ship fires its rockets and turns around, and finally they reunite and compare clocks. Now, note that when I described this scenario, I just said they "begin to move apart", I didn't say whether this was because the ship fired its rockets to move away from the space station or because the space station fired its rockets to move away from the ship. Do you agree that I don't need that piece of information (assuming the initial acceleration was near-instantaneous), that either way the ship's clock will be the one that's behind when they reunite? If so, how can the answer to the question possibly have any relevance as a "physical explanation" to why the ship's clock is behind when they reunite?
Sherlock said:
The way you describe this we don't have the information about whether the ship or the station, or both, accelerated to produce the initial separation. So, if we want to make some inferences about the affects of acceleration, then we would have to describe the reference state as being the state of the system at the instant the ship fired its rockets to return to the station.
I still don't know what you mean by "reference state", this is a term that you have made up without defining, and which makes no sense to me.
Why would we have to describe the reference state as the one where ship fired its rockets to return to the station? Do you agree or disagree that if we know their initial relative velocity as they begin to move apart on the outbound leg, and we know when the ship fired its rockets to turn around, and we know the relative velocity of the ship and the station on the inbound leg after the rocket has been fired (assume the acceleration due to the rocket firing was arbitrarily brief), then this is enough information to tell us which clock will be behind when they reunite, and by how much? Do you agree, in other words, that the answer to the question of whether it was the ship or the station that initially accelerated to get them moving apart has
no effect whatsoever on the final time difference when they reunite? Please answer this question yes or no, because it's not clear to me whether you understand this.
Sherlock said:
But I don't know how that would work, because we want to first compare the clocks while they are in the same state of motion
Why is it important compare them when they are in the same state of motion? All that's important is that you compare them when they are at the same spatial location, that way there will be no disagreement between different reference frames as to the time on each clock at that moment (in contrast to when the clocks are at different locations, and the question of what the two clocks read 'at a single moment' depends on your definition of simultaneity).
Sherlock said:
and the easiest way to do this is to have them sitting next to each other. Then we accelerate *one* clock and note any differences in timekeeping between the two.
I agree that if you start them out sitting next to each other and then accelerate one, then you can have an objective answer to which one has aged less when they reunite. But again,
which one you accelerate initially will have no effect on the final outcome.
JesseM said:
As for physical explanations, a pretty simple one is that the laws of physics are Lorentz-symmetric. Lorentz-symmetry is just a mathematical property of a given equation--it can be defined with no reference to physics whatsoever--and it so happens that the equations describing the laws of electromagnetism have this property, which guarantees that any clocks based on electromagnetic phenomena must appear to slow down when they are moving in your frame, regardless of which frame you're in.
Sherlock said:
Yes, but as is demonstrated by the phenomenon of differential aging or timekeeping, the affects of acceleration aren't just matters of appearance or perspective due to a finite c.
I didn't say anything about it being a matter of appearance or perspective. Again, if you figure out what the correct equations of physics are in a single frame, and then you check the equation you found and see that it has the mathematical property of Lorentz-symmetry, this means you know that observers in different coordinate systems related to yours by the Lorentz transform would see the laws of physics obeying the exact same equations, and this guarantees that clocks based on these laws must be measured by each coordinate system to slow down as their velocity in that frame increases. It is not logically possible to have a universe where the equations representing the laws of physics as seen by an inertial observer have the mathematical property of Lorentz-symmetry but where the physical phenomenon of differential aging seen in the twin paradox would
not be observed. Do you agree with this? If you like I can give a little more explanation about what I mean when I talk about "Lorentz-symmetry" in a purely mathematical sense, as a property of certain equations, as opposed to a more physical sense.
Sherlock said:
I'm not sure what you mean by "valid".
JesseM said:
I mean saying that one frame's perspective on which clock slows down should be preferred in some way over any other's, as you seem to be arguing with your "anomalous motion" vs. "natural motion" distinction.
Sherlock said:
We're asking whether acceleration to a different state of motion (eg., a different velocity wrt some reference state) produces physical changes in the accelerated body.
Maybe that's what you're asking, but I still am not clear on what you mean by "reference state", you have never really defined this term. All I'm saying is that if two clocks start at the same location so that there is a single objective answer to what each one reads "at the same moment", then move apart, then reunite so their readings are compared again and we can see which clock elapsed more time, it will always be whichever clock had to accelerate to turn around that elapsed less time.
Sherlock said:
Apparently it does. But in order to see this we have to know which body is accelerating wrt some reference state, don't we? Otherwise, if we just have two clocks with different readings and no other information, then either, or both, could have been accelerated wrt the reference state.
As long as we know the accelerations and velocities throughout the period when they are apart, that's all you need to figure out what the readings will be when they reunite. Knowing which accelerated initially to begin to move them apart in the first place is irrelevant.
Sherlock said:
So, we make some assumptions about the experimental situation. In the case of clock A moving around the solar system while clock B remains on earth, we're assuming that clock A's motion is the anomalous motion wrt the regular motion of the solar system and not the earth's.
"Anomalous motion" is another term you made up and didn't define. And again, in the ship/space station example, if the question of whose motion is "anomalous" depends on whether the ship or the station accelerated initially, then obviously this question is irrelevant to the problem, since either way you'll get the same answer to which clock is behind when they reunite, and by how much (it'll be the ship's clock that's behind, because the ship was the one that accelerated to turn around at the midpoint of the journey).
Sherlock said:
And we *can* say with a pretty high degree of certainty that it's clock A that has accelerated and not clock B.
But it does make a difference. If it was clock B rather than clock A that traveled around the solar system, then clock B would show less time for the trip interval than clock A. Which clock we choose to accelerate is an arbitrary decision of course, since they're identical clocks, keeping time at exactly the same rate while next to each other on earth. But once we've made the choice, and accelerated one or the other, then it makes a difference, wrt our experimental hypothesis, which one was accelerated and which one wasn't.
It makes a difference which clock accelerated to turn around at the midpoint of the trip, it doesn't make a difference which clock accelerated initially to get the two clocks moving apart after they had been at rest relative to each other in a single location. Agreed?
Sherlock said:
The point of a 'reference state' is simply to be able to make some objective statements about differential timekeeping.
JesseM said:
And any such "objective statement" would totally violate the spirit of relativity.
Sherlock said:
I don't think so. Especially since we're using Relativity to predict the results. And the results do seem to agree very well with the predictions of Relativity.
Yes, and the predictions of relativity about objective physical questions like what two clocks read at the moment they reunite will be the same
regardless of what reference frame you use to analyze the problem. But these frames will disagree on other less "objective" issues, like which clock was ticking slower during the inbound leg of the trip. From what I understand, you're using the concept of a "reference state" to pick a particular reference frame's answers to these sorts of questions (the Earth's frame, say) and label them more "objectively true" then the answers in other frames--that's what I meant when I said it would totally violate the spirit of relativity. Am I misunderstanding what you are saying about reference states here?
Sherlock said:
So, I'm just exploring what sort of inferences about the physical causes of differential timekeeping can be made. The conjecture is that acceleration produces physical changes in accelerated bodies -- eg., the periods of oscillators are altered, due to physical changes in the oscillators, as they move from one state of motion to another. If you don't think that the results of relativistic experiments lead to this idea, then you still haven't explained satisfactorily why? Aren't length contraction and mass increase as prescribed by Relativity real physical changes?
Something is only a "real physical change" if it is the same in every frame. Length contraction and time dilation depend on the frame you choose--they're more analogous to the slope of a curve drawn on a piece of paper at a particular point, which depends on what angle you place your x and y axes. Nevertheless, you can calculate the length of the curve in different coordinate systems by integrating a function of the slope in that coordinate system, and you'll get the same answer regardless of how you orient your axes. Similarly, you can integrate a function of the time dilation in different frames in relativity to get the total time elapsed on a clock which follows a given path between two points in spacetime, and you'll get the same answer in every frame.
Sherlock said:
We're using a *reference state* (earth-clock A-clock B) which we disassemble and then reassemble by accelerating *one* component (clock A) of that state.
Who's "we"? Physicists don't use "reference states" when analyzing these problems. Perhaps we could look at a numerical example of a twin-paradox-like situation, and I could show you how physicists would analyze it, then you could try to explain how it could be analyzed in terms of your own concepts?