Medical What part of the brain is conscious?

  • Thread starter Thread starter Q_Goest
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Brain
AI Thread Summary
Anosognosia is a neurological condition where individuals are unaware of their own paralysis, often due to lesions in the right hemisphere of the brain. Research indicates that damage to specific frontal areas and the thalamocortical circuit is linked to this lack of awareness, suggesting a complex interplay of brain regions contributes to consciousness. The discussion raises questions about whether consciousness can be localized to specific brain areas or if it emerges from the interactions of many parts of the brain. It also highlights the distinction between neural correlates of consciousness and the broader context needed for conscious experience, emphasizing that understanding consciousness requires examining both specific neural activity and the overall functioning of the brain. Further research is necessary to map out these neural correlates and their relationship to conscious experience.
Q_Goest
Science Advisor
Messages
3,012
Reaction score
42
The 15 July 2005 issue of Science has an interesting article regarding something called anosognosia.

A strange and disturbing neurological condition, anosognosia, can cause obviously intelligent, awake and talking individuals to be unaware of paralysis on one side of their body. Berti et al. investigated patients with spatial neglect and found that about half of them were also anosognosic for their left hemiplegia because of lesions in the right brain hemisphere. Comparisons of the two groups with and without anosognosia revealed that damage to frontal areas (particularly brain areas 6 and 44, motor cortex BA4, and the somatosensory cortex) underpins the loss of awareness of motor impairment in these patients.

It seems very strange that one is unaware of their own paralysis while they are completely aware of the person they are being interviewed by asking them about it. The patient in this case would simply need to look down and realize that when consciously attempting to lift an arm, it would not move.

Similar problems might include the belief that limbs are still attached when in fact they've been amputated. That seems to be a similar phenomena wherein the brain is consciously aware of a limb that simply doesn't exist. Another problem I've seen is people with memory loss not realizing they even have a memory problem or constantly forgetting they have this problem.

If one were to model the brain as a mechanism of some sort with nerve inputs, it would seem that there is a borderline within the brain beyond which conscious awareness can not extend. In other words, if the input/output for the conscious portion of the brain simply goes silent and does not register anything, it would seem as if we can not be consciously aware of it or our consciousness is not impared by it except as that input/output may affect things such as memory.

We often view consciousness as being seated in the brain, but I wonder if there is any evidence which points to some limited location within the brain. The article in Science mentions specific locations, but unfortunately I'm not a neuroscientist and have no idea if this entire concept of there being a specific region of the brain responsible for consciousness has been examined. Any comments would be appreciated.
 
Biology news on Phys.org
The technical term for those parts of the brain whose activity is correlated with consciousness is "neural correlates of consciousness" (NCC for short). It is certainly the case that not all systems in the brain are NCCs, since the brain does a lot of information processing that can be shown to be unconsciousness, that is, not available to conscious awareness. Much more work needs to be done before the NCCs of the various features of consciousness can be exhausitively mapped out in detail, although the thalamocortical circuit seems to be a centrally important system as regards correlation with consciousness. (The thalamus is located roughly in the middle of the brain, and is often described as a 'relay station' to the cortex; all sensory input channels except smell feed into the thalamus. From the thalamus, there are dense neural connections to the cortex, where sensory information is processed further.)

Although it might seem intuitive and straightforward, the concept of what an NCC really is is somewhat subtle. A good discussion of what we should mean by an NCC can be found in David Chalmers' paper What is a Neural Correlate of Consciousness?. For some references on scientific research of NCCs, see http://consc.net/biblio/6.html#6.1a; for references on research of the NCCs of visual consciousness, see http://consc.net/biblio/6.html#6.1b.
 
Last edited:
Thanks for the info, I'll check those out shortly.
 
Consciousness is so complex and so little understood that I believe it is
not productive to try to localize "it" in a specific part of the brain.
 
How do you suppose we attempt to make it more understood if we do not try to locate it? Even failure is informative.
 
Consciousness is so complex and so little understood that I believe it is not productive to try to localize "it" in a specific part of the brain.

Yes, that's really my question, "is there a location, or more accurately, a given volume of the brain which is responsible for the phenomenon we call consciousness?"

It seems in the case of people with anosognosia, severed limbs and other maladies, there is a disconnect. Similarly, I suspect there are portions of the brain itself, such as those portions which might store memories, that don't contribute directly to the conscious experience.

I wonder what research has been done (especially on people that have undergone some brain damage) and what conclusions have been made. It seems the thalamus as mentioned by Hyp have been specifically mentioned in the literature.

I seem to remember a famous case of a man shot through the head with a steel spike who was working on a railroad over 100 years ago that survived and who's consciousness was relativly unaffected, but his personality was significantly affected. This is another case of consciousness not being affected, but only things that govern behaviour being altered.

So are there portions of the brain such as memory, or portions that govern behavior or other functions that DON'T contribute to the conscious experience?
 
On a separate note, there must also be portions of the brain which perhaps perform specific tasks related to the conscious experience. I seem also to remember hearing about a woman who could not distinguish how fast oncoming traffic was traveling. She could see a vehicle, but for some reason couldn't determine how fast it was coming. Other people have problems not consciously seeing something, but are able to react despite this.
 
El Hombre Invisible said:
How do you suppose we attempt to make it more understood if we do not try to locate it? Even failure is informative.


We should attempt to understand it as something that emerges from the
complex interplay of many different parts of the organ, not as something
that is spatially confined to one or another parts of it. K?
 
We should attempt to understand it as something that emerges from the complex interplay of many different parts of the organ, not as something
that is spatially confined to one or another parts of it.

When you say "parts of the organ" I presume you mean "brain" which has some boundry around it, as opposed to "parts of the organ" meaning body which includes the brain as a sub-part. Is this to presume that only neurons (or does this include glia?) are capable of consciousness then? Because if we rule out every other part of the body, including nerve cells such as the spinal chord, we are left with a group of neurons with an interesting interface. Somewhere it changes from neurons to not neurons. What is that interface, and where is it?

I tend to wonder though if this is a good assumption, that all the neurons in the brain are capable of consciousness, but no other cells are. Certainly not all the neurons in the brain are going to be used in the conscious experience at once, but many of them will. So there must be a switching on and off somehow. This switching on and off can also be affected by something as simple as xenon, used as an anesthetic for example. (Ref: Patent 5228434)
 
  • #10
El Hombre Invisible said:
How do you suppose we attempt to make it more understood if we do not try to locate it? Even failure is informative.

Let's say you are trying to figure out what part of a radio produces language. You don't know where language comes from, but you have already assumed the radio itself generates language because that's the only place you hear it. The technology you have doesn't allow you to detect radio waves, so the idea that language might originate outside the radio, as a signal, seems non-parsimonious.

What you do, because you are committed a priori to a radio explanation of language, is try to show exactly where in the radio that language emerges so you can say "THERE," that's the seat of language. In this analogy, it is obvious that just because language emerges from the radio's speaker doesn't mean the speaker created the language.

Yet that is exactly what a great many thinkers assume about the brain even though we can't find any evidence that physicalness (i.e., the brain) is capable of generating consciousness. Affecting it, shaping it, organizing it, giving it a means for manifesting itself in this universe . . . yes. But creating consciousness . . . no.
 
  • #11
Les is correct to point out that observing a correlation between brain activity and conscious experience is not, in itself, sufficient grounds to deduce the nature of the causal relationship between the two. Of course, that latter topic is itself the subject of much discussion and debate in the sciences and philosophy.

However, I think we can and should proceed with this discussion without delving too much into the deeper metaphysical issues; those are further questions that are best left to other threads. Along these lines, saying that the brain is conscious, or that the brain produces or is causally responsible for conscious experience might seem relatively harmless, but in reality these phrasings are theoretically loaded. However, if we restrict our discussion to the neural correlates of consciousness, we can still have a fruitful discussion here that is faithful to the thrust of this thread's topic, while remaining neutral on the more complicated metaphysical issues.
 
  • #12
Antiphon said:
We should attempt to understand it as something that emerges from the
complex interplay of many different parts of the organ, not as something
that is spatially confined to one or another parts of it. K?

There is something to be said for this view. For instance, it is believed that various neural correlates of visual consciousness lie along the visual processing stream, beginning in area V1 of visual cortex in the occipital lobe and traversing the ventral processing stream to areas of the temporal lobe. Roughly stated, this means that certain activations of certain neural systems in these brain regions are correlated with certain features of experiential, visual consciousness. This might create the appearance of something of a modular view, on which the neural systems in the visual processing stream alone are enough to provide sufficient conditions for the existence of visual consciousness.

However, it is tacitly understood that for this correlation between neural systems in the visual processing stream and visual consciousness to hold, the relevant neural systems must be functioning in the wider context afforded by other neural systems. For instance, it is known that damage to the intralaminar nuclei in the thalamus leads to coma. If we assume for a moment that being in a coma implies the loss of unified, high level human consciousness, it follows that visual consciousness is lost as well. Thus, in order for neural systems in the visual processing stream to be correlated with visual consciousness, it seems that at least one background condition must be met: The intralaminar nuclei in the thalamus must be properly functioning. There are probably hosts of other such neural systems in the brain that must be functioning properly in order to provide the context in which certain neural systems are correlated with visual experience.

Nonetheless, the activity of the visual processing stream is related to visual experience in more direct and finer-grained ways than the activity of the intralaminar nuclei, so we would be missing something if we didn't distinguish between the two. Ideally what we want is to be able to draw as fine-grained a correlation between neural activity and subjective experience as possible, while still paying heed to the more global, background conditions that come into play. In the paper I referenced earlier, Chalmers succinctly incorporates these considerations (and others) into his general definition of a neural correlate of consciousness (NCC):

An NCC is a minimal neural system N such that there is a mapping from states of N to states of consciousness, where a given state of N is sufficient, under conditions C, for the corresponding state of consciousness.

For a good extended discussion on this topic (modularity of NCCs vs. global considerations), see the section of Chalmers' paper titled "Direct correlation."
 
Last edited:
  • #13
The previous three posts are very good.

Q_Goest said:
I seem to remember a famous case of a man shot through the head with a steel spike who was working on a railroad over 100 years ago that survived and who's consciousness was relativly unaffected, but his personality was significantly affected. This is another case of consciousness not being affected, but only things that govern behaviour being altered.

We need a more comprehensive working definition of consciousness.
Maybe this fellow's actual thought patterns changed. Or maybe they
didn't but his temper (an emotional-glandular interaction) was altered.

For humans anyway I would think that our emotional states should be
included in the description of consciousness.

And let's not forget that there is a subconscous layer that underpins this
which is only faintly understood if at all.
 
Last edited:
  • #14
isn't hte entire brain consciousness? If i remember correctly, you can lesion off any part of the brain but youi will lose certain capabilities that that part of the brain processed. perhaps memory, perhaps learning, physical motion.
 
  • #15
neurocomp2003 said:
isn't hte entire brain consciousness? If i remember correctly, you can lesion off any part of the brain but youi will lose certain capabilities that that part of the brain processed. perhaps memory, perhaps learning, physical motion.
The fact that you loose abilities when a certain part of the brain is lost does not imply that this part of the brain is concious. It may be that this part simply performs calculations and gives relevant results to the part of the brain that is concious.
 
  • #16
the right part of the bran is concence that's what i know. see this girl got her left brain replaced cause of a desies and she still had a concence and went to rehab and the docs say so to
 
  • #17
leonard: then what is your definition of consciousness? awareness like that of an animal?
 
  • #18
Being aware that you exist and having feelings.
 
  • #19
exactly your sences come from the left side of you brian :smile: :bugeye:
 
  • #20
neo-cortex
 
  • #21
the_truth said:
neo-cortex
How do you know that?
 
  • #22
neocortex isn't as developed in animals is it?
 
  • #23
on a similar topic, in certain extreme cases neurosurgeons can perform a hemispherectomy- essentially removing half of the brain- it's usually done in children who are at an early developmental stage. If done early enough, the remaining half of he brain compensates for the missing half, and they can lead an almost "normal" childhool. That is to say they can lead a fairly normal life versus no life at all. It's truly amazing.
 
  • #24
Zantra said:
on a similar topic, in certain extreme cases neurosurgeons can perform a hemispherectomy- essentially removing half of the brain- it's usually done in children who are at an early developmental stage. If done early enough, the remaining half of he brain compensates for the missing half, and they can lead an almost "normal" childhool. That is to say they can lead a fairly normal life versus no life at all. It's truly amazing.
:eek: How does that work exactly? How does that affect how the child thinks? like in regard to hand-eye coordination and such?
 
  • #25
Smurf said:
:eek: How does that work exactly? How does that affect how the child thinks? like in regard to hand-eye coordination and such?

Well I don't know the details of exactly how it works, but essentailly the brain compensates by directing left and right coordination to a part of the brain that still functions- much the way a blind man's hearing can become more attuned. As far as thinking, I believe the one subject read about never really developed beyond the mentality of a child, and he also had to see a physical therapist to learn to compensate. There's obviously going to be some difficulty when half of your brain is removed.
 
  • #26
The thalamo-cortical complex referred to by Hypnagogue is, in fact, somehow, the essential base of consciousness in the brain. As he mentioned, damage to the thalamus results in coma, which is not true of any other part of the brain, and merely physically disturbing the thalamus results in unconsciousness: neurosurgeons are careful to stay away from it when operating on epilepsy patients, a procedure done while they are awake so they can paticipate with localizing the seizure focus by giving verbal feedback to stimulation of different areas.

In addition, the thalamo-cortical complex is what is disturbed in attacks of petite-mal epilepsy, called absense seizures.

A person with this kind of epilepsy will experience very brief, but total, failures of consciousness, usually several times a day, but possibly even more.

Nothing but consciousness is affected in these seizures: the rest of the person's brain functions normally; there are no convulsions or other symptoms beyond the brief loss of consciousness.

To an outsider such a person appears to simply be standing still, unresponsive, and staring intently at nothing in particular. A few seconds later they resume a normal demeanor, but may seem mildy disconcerted, or surprised.

To the sufferer, time seems to suddenly jump ahead, like a film which has had a few seconds cut out of it. Things may have changed their position suddenly in the person's visual field, or the conversation they are in may seem to have inexplicably switched topic or speakers.

It's important to note that this is a completely different experience than "spacing out" i.e. becoming so lost in a train of thought that you stop paying attention to our surroundings. In an absense seizure conciousness ceases to function at all: there are no thoughts to get lost in.

The seizure activity in absense seizures runs somewhere in the circuits between the thalamus and the cortex of the frontal lobes, and is usually no problem to pick up on an EEG, exhibiting a tell-tale 3.5 hz spike and wave pattern that is the hallmark EEG tracing of the absence seizure.

So, during the absense seizure, the whole brain seems to continue to function, except those parts responsible for something essential about consciousness, which I don't even know what to call: perhaps basic consciousness or baseline consciousness or foundation consciousness.
 
  • #27
Q-Goest said:
Similar problems might include the belief that limbs are still attached when in fact they've been amputated. That seems to be a similar phenomena wherein the brain is consciously aware of a limb that simply doesn't exist.

V.S. Ramachandran, a well known neurologist, has done a lot of study of amputees, (as well as the half paralyzed stroke patients) and believes he has unlocked the mystery of the "phantom limb" phenomenon. Although a person's limb may be missing, the part of the brain that processes sensory input from that limb is still there, as well as the part that processes proprioceptive imput from that limb.

Ramachandran believes that, with no imput from the missing limb, these areas become receptive to imput from the surrounding neural tissue and erroneously present that imput to consciousness as being from the missing limb.

Strangely enough, I saw a different neurologist on TV a few years ago arguing the same thing. (Does Ramachandran check the prior research?) He had a man with no arms there, and by touching the man's jawline he could produce a sensation in the man's "phantom thumb". This, the neurologist said, was due to the fact that the sense of touch or these two places are processed right next to each other on the sensory strip of the brain: stimulation to the sensory strip jaw area, via the jaw, could bleed right over into the deprived sensory strip area for the thumb.

This all makes a great deal of sense since phantom limb sensations aren't constant: they kick in and out, and are felt to different degrees at different times, and involve every sensation from touch to pain.

This, though, is really quite a different phenomenon than the half-paralzed stroke patients. The amputees are well aware a limb is missing, and the phantom senstions are appropriately inexplicable and incongruous to them. The stroke patients in question, on the other hand, have lost the capacity to apprehend they are half-paralyzed.
 
  • #28
Q_Goest said:
It seems very strange that one is unaware of their own paralysis while they are completely aware of the person they are being interviewed by asking them about it. The patient in this case would simply need to look down and realize that when consciously attempting to lift an arm, it would not move.
It's funny you should bring this up, because I recently linked to an article about the same kind of stroke patients in another forum to make a point about the limits of our ability to know if we are hallucinating or not.

From these patients along with several strange cases I've read about where something like the opposite occurs (that is: they "disown" a limb, and can't believe it is actually attached to their body, and is a part of them), as well as cases where people believe a limb that is neither missing nor paralyzed, is nevertheless in a position different from the one they can visually observe it to be in, and also from the common reports of the "out-of-body" experience, I was lead to some reading about the sense we all have, but are unaware of, called proprioception. This is a person's ability to sense what position they are in without having to look at themselves.

You may have supposed such a thing was the natural side-kick of the sense of touch, (and indeed, it is sometimes referred to as "internal touch") but is is actually a different dedicated system with it's own nerve receptors (proprioceptors) and it's own processing centers in the brain, (parietal lobes, somewhere, and angulate gyrus? - don't quote me, that's from memory).

Take the case of The Disembodied Lady reported in The Man Who Mistook His Wife For a Hat, by Oliver Sacks: a woman whose proprioceptive sense was destroyed by a freak illness now lives in a permanent "out-of-body" state. She no longer has any internal sense of where "she" is located. If she closes her eyes, she feels non-located. If she opens them, she can see from the perspective of her eyes, but doesn't "feel" located behind them. She can't move a limb without looking at it because she can't sense where it is to start with, where it is going, or aim it anywhere without visually tracking it the whole time. Sacks determined her parietal lobes were fine, and that it was the proprioceptors throughout her body that had been damaged: they could send her parietal lobes no information.

Somehow, simply having physical existence isn't enough to know we have a physical existence. To know we have physical existence, the brain must be informed by input from the sense of proprioception. The case reported by Sacks was, at that time, a freak: proprioception is usually so reliable that no such gross defects occur, and everyone remains blissfully unaware that we even need such a sense. (Since then, Sacks appends, many people have temporarily lost their sense of proprioception through a fad diet reccomending large amounts of vitamin B6)

The stroke patients are a different kettle of fish than amputees with phantom limb sensations. The stroke patients don't seem to be able to apprehend that half their body isn't working, not even by looking at the unmoving arm or leg. This means they must be in the throes of a full-blown, elaborate visual hallucination in which the paralyzed half is seen by them to be doing everything they feel it is doing.

Ramachandran believes this is old fashioned, psychological denial. However, when we look at all these misplaced, missing, and disowned limb cases, a pattern emerges concerning proprioception.

In his next story, The Man Who Fell Out Of Bed Sacks tells of a patient who came in for weakness in the leg. He woke up next morning to find a "horrible" leg in bed with him. Thinking some drunken hospital employee must have put an amputated limb in bed with him as a joke, he threw it out of bed, but he himself went with it, and ended up on the floor.

He couldn't apprehend that it was his own leg. He couldn't feel his own leg, and didn't know what had happened to it beyond the fact it seemed to have disappeared, but this terrible limb wasn't it, and didn't belong to him.

Our sense of proprioception, the sense we don't even realize we have, usually works so perfectly that we never doubt it, or think of doubting it. It turns out to be higher on the hierarchy of what senses we believe than even our vision, such that a man will disown his own leg, and try to throw it out of bed, if his sense of proprioception ceases to extend into that leg.

I think that what's happening with the stroke patients is much more complicated than mere denial. I think that, despite muscular paralysis, their ability to process proprioception for the paralysed half is intact, but now independent of the limbs in question, and that all the feelings of motion and resultant change in location that are appropriate to bilateral functionality are being experienced by these patients: they feel like they are moving the paralyzed half.

Why do I think that? Because amputees report thay can move their phantom limbs, feel them in different positions, and go through the motions of interacting with objects (unsuccessfully, of course). Additionally, some seizure patients with simple-partial seizure activity in the parietal lobes, experience the sensation that limbs which are neither amputated nor paralyzed, are never-the-less in positions which are different from what visual inspection tells them. One man, in particular, couldn't shake the "feeling" that his arm was being held up in the air beside his head. He could easily see it was down at his side, but the feeling was so convincing he asked his wife to pull it back down for him.

The stroke patients seem to be so convinced by the feeling the paralyzed half is still functioning and moving, that they resolve the cognitive dissonance between that overwhelmingly convincing feeling and the sight of the paralyzed limbs, by unconsciously chosing to believe the feeling and to ignore the actual visual imput, replacing it with an hallucination appropriate to the sensory experience of being able to move. I would look for the reason they are susceptible to such hallucinations, while amputees are usually not, in the fact that the stroke patients have had "insults" to the brain.

( Not all stroke patents are like this, by the way. This subset is actually a minority.)
 
  • #29
zoobyshoe said:
The thalamo-cortical complex referred to by Hypnagogue is, in fact, somehow, the essential base of consciousness in the brain. As he mentioned, damage to the thalamus results in coma, which is not true of any other part of the brain, and merely physically disturbing the thalamus results in unconsciousness: neurosurgeons are careful to stay away from it when operating on epilepsy patients, a procedure done while they are awake so they can paticipate with localizing the seizure focus by giving verbal feedback to stimulation of different areas.

Actually, the intralaminar nuclei in the thalami are not the only portions of the brain whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness:

"An astonishing amount of brain tissue can be lost from the great cerebral hemispheres without abolishing the state of consciousness, while tiny lesions in the slender axial core of the brain cause irreversible coma. We have known since the 1950s that a small area in the brain stem called the reticular formation is necessary for waking consciousness. When people with head injuries go into coma, it is often because tissue damage at the front of the head causes widespread swelling, choking off the blood supply even to the brain stem. When oxygen supply is lost to the reticular formation the result is coma; and because the nerve centers that control breathing and heart action are located very nearby, death often follows."

- from In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind by Bernard J. Baars, p. 25-26

While it's important to the NCC search to discover brain areas that are necessary for consciousness, such necessary conditions can't give us the final story. Ideally, we want to find those brain regions whose proper functioning present minimally sufficient conditions for consciousness, given some background conditions.

To give an exaggerated illustration of why this is the case, we can say with confidence that a functional heart is a necessary condition for consciousness. Still, elevating the heart to the status of a primary physical correlate of consciousness seems to be miss the point-- it's not faithful to what we really mean by "physical (neural) correlate of consciousness." I have no doubt that the thalamocortical complex is more intimately involved with consciousness than is the heart, but if it is, it is primarily by virtue of presenting some set of sufficient conditions for consciousness, rather than merely necessary conditions.
 
  • #30
hypnagogue said:
Actually, the intralaminar nuclei in the thalami are not the only portions of the brain whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness:

"An astonishing amount of brain tissue can be lost from the great cerebral hemispheres without abolishing the state of consciousness, while tiny lesions in the slender axial core of the brain cause irreversible coma. We have known since the 1950s that a small area in the brain stem called the reticular formation is necessary for waking consciousness. When people with head injuries go into coma, it is often because tissue damage at the front of the head causes widespread swelling, choking off the blood supply even to the brain stem. When oxygen supply is lost to the reticular formation the result is coma; and because the nerve centers that control breathing and heart action are located very nearby, death often follows."

- from In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind by Bernard J. Baars, p. 25-26
Well, no. The reason the reticular formation is important to consciousness is because it moderates the functioning of the intralaminar nuclei in the thalamus:

The Reticular Formation
Address:http://www.geocities.com/medinotes/reticular_formation.htm

Scroll to bottom:

"Control of Consciousness

Ascending projections from the reticular formation terminate in the thalamus, subthalamus, hypothalamus, and basal ganglia.

The functions of most of these are poorly understood, but those to the thalamus seem to be particularly important.

They terminate in the intralaminar nuclei, which in turn project to widespread areas of the cortex.

Activity in this pathway is essential for the maintenance of a normal state of consciousness.
Bilateral damage to these fibres as they traverse or originate in the midbrain reticular formation results in prolonged coma."


In other words, the reticular formation, itself, is neither here nor there, except that it controls the level of activity of the thalamus (specifically, the intralaminar nuclei), which is vital to consciousness.

I'm going to guess that if you or I do more digging into this, we'll find the reason this, sort of. rheostat for the thalamus is located removed from that organ in the brainstem, it is because many other important functions having to do with sleep are also located in the brainstem.

(That whole page on the reticular formation is worth reading, if you can slog through the medical language: it does many, many things. I was particularly interested by the note that, in some cases, a single neuron in the formation may be doing all the work of a particular specific function it performs.)

While it's important to the NCC search to discover brain areas that are necessary for consciousness, such necessary conditions can't give us the final story.
I am sure no one has read to the end of the book yet, but I'm not sure I would characterize myself as looking for the neural correlates of consciousness. (That sounds like it may have subtle philosophical implications that I might not want to endorse if I knew what they were.)

My point was/is: the thalamo-cortical complex is vital to consciousness in a way nothing else in the brain is. I think the most vivid way to get that across is the descriptions of what happens when it is disturbed. Gross, probably clumsy analogy: it's as vital to consciousness as an engine is to a working car. No engine: you go nowhere.
------
The notion of "minimally sufficient conditions for consciousness" assumes a cut off point that I doubt exists. Each thing you subtract diminishes consciousness by removing a stimulus or function. I can't see any termination point (except obvious unconsciousness) as being anything but arbitrary. But maybe you have better insight into what they're looking for.
 
  • #31
zoobyshoe said:
Well, no. The reason the reticular formation is important to consciousness is because it moderates the functioning of the intralaminar nuclei in the thalamus:

That may well be, but that doesn't contradict anything I said. I was mainly responding to your comment that "damage to the thalamus results in coma, which is not true of any other part of the brain." Essentially, this amounts to saying that the thalamus is the only brain region whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness. This is false, since the reticular formation is part of the brain, and its proper functioning is also necessary for consciousness.

I think you object because you are taking 'necessary' to mean more than it should be taken to mean, e.g. when you say:

zoobyshoe said:
In other words, the reticular formation, itself, is neither here nor there, except that it controls the level of activity of the thalamus (specifically, the intralaminar nuclei), which is vital to consciousness.

I assume when you say the thalamus is "vital" for consciousness, you mean that proper functioning of the thalamus presents sufficient conditions for consciousness-- i.e., whenever the thalamus is doing whatever it does during periods of wakefulness, we are conscious.

Claiming that a brain region is necessary for consciousness is not so strong a claim. If X is necessary for Y, that just means that if there is no X, then there cannot be any Y, or more formally, ~X -> ~Y. On the other hand, if X is sufficient for Y, that means that whenever X is present Y is also present, or X -> Y. Note that if X is a necessary condition for Y, it does not follow that X is a sufficient condition for Y. (The converse is also true; if X is sufficient for Y, it does not follow that X is necessary for Y.)

Applying this to the discussion at hand, it seems we have good evidence that the reticular formation is necessary, but not sufficient, for consciousness. We know the reticular formation is necessary for consciousness, because whenever it is damaged, coma follows. We know that it is not sufficient for consciousness, however, because coma can also follow if we damage the intralaminar nuclei but leave the reticular formation intact.

zoobyshoe said:
I am sure no one has read to the end of the book yet, but I'm not sure I would characterize myself as looking for the neural correlates of consciousness. (That sounds like it may have subtle philosophical implications that I might not want to endorse if I knew what they were.)

"Neural correlates of consciousness" is the standard terminology used for this subject, in scientific as well as philosophical circles. The term is in fact not theoretically loaded, but quite neutral. When we speak of neural correlates of consciousness, we refer only to correlations between neural activity and features of consciousness, while remaining neutral on the nature of the causative link that underlies that correlation.

zoobyshoe said:
The notion of "minimally sufficient conditions for consciousness" assumes a cut off point that I doubt exists. Each thing you subtract diminishes consciousness by removing a stimulus or function. I can't see any termination point (except obvious unconsciousness) as being anything but arbitrary. But maybe you have better insight into what they're looking for.

Looking for minimally sufficient conditions for consciousness amounts to narrowing down the search so that we can zero in on what neural systems are truly essential for consciousness or features thereof, while not counting neural systems whose activity is superfluous to consciousness or its various features. This consideration is basically just a refinement of the more general term "sufficient."

To illustrate why such a refinement is needed, consider the following. Eating a large meal is sufficient to alleviate hunger. It is also true that eating a large meal while watching TV is sufficient to alleviate hunger. It is also true that eating a large meal while watching TV and sitting in a lotus position in Nepal is sufficient for alleviating hunger. And so on. But if we are interested in zeroing in on what exactly it is that is critically related to hunger satiation, we will not want to consider superfluous phenomena like watching TV, etc. That is, we will want to find the minimally sufficient conditions for hunger satiation.

In general, if X is sufficient for Y (X -> Y), then any number of conditions in conjunction with X are also sufficient for Y ([X & A & B & C & ...] -> Y). Finding the minimally sufficient conditions for Y amounts to separating the wheat from the chaff, subtracting various superfluous conditions until we are left with some essential core sufficiency conditions.

This is important to the NCC search because we are interested in the finding the specific neural systems whose activity is sufficient for consciousness, or features thereof. If we were satisfied with merely finding a sufficient NCC for consciousness, we could count the brain as a whole as one such NCC and be done with it-- a healthily functioning brain, taken as a whole, presents a sufficient condition for consciousness and all its various features. But if we don't want to count as NCCs all those neural systems whose activity is essentially superfluous to presenting sufficient conditions for consciousness as a whole or its specific contents, then we will have to look for minimally sufficient conditions.

If you haven't yet, I recommend reading Chalmers' paper on NCCs. It does a good job of clarifying all these surface issues that we're getting caught up in.
 
Last edited:
  • #32
I'd like to thank everyone for all the comments on this thread. Right now I'm out of town on business trying to help get a rocket up in the air, and next week doesn't look much better for my free time, so I appologize for not being more active on my own post here. Anyway, I just wanted to acknowledge and thank you all for the terrific feedback so far.

Zantra: It sounds like that hemispherectomy must not touch certain common areas of the brain such as the thalamus which is deep in the center somewhere above the brain stem. It must take out a whole lot computational power away from the brain, if you will, but none that prevents the phenomenon of consciousness from existing. That in itself seems to be crucial to understanding the central question of what parts of the brain do not directly impact consciousness, but may only impact it in a secondary way.
 
  • #33
zoobyshoe, I enjoyed your comments. Many thanks.
The stroke patients in question, on the other hand, have lost the capacity to apprehend they are half-paralyzed.
Yes, I think this is exactly right. I found this regarding the article in the July 15 issue of Science. It's from a NY Times article:
Dr. Anna Berti sits facing a patient whose paralyzed left arm rests in her lap next to her good right arm. "Can you raise your left arm?" Dr. Berti asks.

"Yes," the patient says.

The arm remains motionless. Dr. Berti tries again. "Are you raising your left arm?" she asks.

"Yes," the patient says. But the arm still does not move.

Dr. Berti, a neuroscientist at University of Turin in Italy, has had many such conversations with stroke patients who suffer from denial syndrome, a strange disorder in which paralyzed patients vehemently insist that they are not paralyzed.

This denial, Dr. Berti said, was long thought to be purely a psychological problem. "It was a reaction to a stroke: I am paralyzed, it is so horrible, I will deny it," she said.

But in a new study, Dr. Berti and her colleagues have shown that denial is not a problem of the mind. Rather, it is a neurological condition that occurs when specific brain regions are knocked out by a stroke.

Patients deny the paralysis because a closely related region of the brain that is still intact appears to tell them that their bodies are responding normally.
The article is really about "denial" versus "neglect". Further, it says:
Denial, Dr. Berti said, is usually considered to be a subfeature of a more common neurological syndrome called neglect. In neglect, patients suffer a stroke in the right side of the brain that results in paralysis of the left side of the body. Damage is pronounced in a region toward the back of the brain where personal space around the body is literally mapped and encoded by cells.

Neglect patients ignore everything, including their paralyzed limbs, in the left side of space, Dr. Berti said. But if their attention is purposefully drawn to that space, they recognize that their arm is paralyzed. They do not deny their situation.

But because denial and neglect can occur independently, Dr. Berti said she decided to see if patients who exhibited denial showed different underlying brain pathology.

For the study, 30 stroke patients underwent anatomical brain scans to pinpoint the source of their brain damage. All were paralyzed on the left side. Twelve patients exhibited neglect. Another 17 showed neglect and denial. One patient displayed only denial.

By comparing brain images, the researchers hoped to subtract denial from neglect, to see where the disorder resides in brain circuitry. As expected, neglect frequently involved damage to a region toward the back of the brain called the parietal lobe, as well as to nearby structures. Damage was also seen below the brain's mantle, or cortex, in tissue called white matter.

But to the researchers' surprise, brain damage in the patients who displayed denial tended to occur in the front part of the brain, particularly in the circuits that control movements and the planning of movements and in a region that helps produce feelings about the body.

Dr. Berti said these regions appeared to work together to generate, plan and perceive actions. They also generate self-awareness of actions.

Denial seems to arise from the fact that in patients who display the disorder, a related brain area is less affected or unaffected, Dr. Berti said. Called the supplementary motor area, it is involved in the mental simulation of movements. When athletes close their eyes and imagine a golf swing or skiing motion, this part of the brain is activated.

When patients who display denial are asked to raise an arm or clap their hands, the region that imagines these movements produces a familiar pattern of brain activation, showing normal or close to normal function, Dr. Berti said.

But the regions that maintain awareness of movements and carry them out are not working. The conflict between these regions, she said, becomes overwhelming.

The sense of having moved is powerful but awareness is absent.
So it would seem that "denial" and "neglect" are outward indications of what certain portions of the brain is doing, or how it is functioning. I'm interpreting this as if the conscious portions of the brain are working properly but receiving improper inputs or are unable to properly connect to the body. Although the portions of the brain responsible for performing those functions are not working properly, the lack of those functional areas does not directly impact the ability of the brain to be conscious or aware. It is still experiencing unity for example, but the experience seems to have a disconnection with reality because of these chunks of brain which are not properly functioning and not providing feedback to the portions of the brain responsible for awareness. I also gather the same impression from other things zoobyshoe mentions such as the discussion on phantom limbs, "The man who fell out of bed" and others. I hope I'm understanding this right, its all fairly new to me.
 
  • #34
Q_Goest said:
Zantra: It sounds like that hemispherectomy must not touch certain common areas of the brain such as the thalamus which is deep in the center somewhere above the brain stem. It must take out a whole lot computational power away from the brain, if you will, but none that prevents the phenomenon of consciousness from existing. That in itself seems to be crucial to understanding the central question of what parts of the brain do not directly impact consciousness, but may only impact it in a secondary way.

Functional Hemispherectomies, are a procedure used in extreme epileptic cases where the specific region of the brain causing the seizures cannot be isolated.

http://www.neuro.wustl.edu/epilepsy/pediatric/articleHemispherectomy.html

Hemispherectomy is the surgical removal or disconnection of one side of the brain from the other. This procedure is performed on a subset of epilepsy patients - those with medically intractable epilepsy arising from one side of the brain that lacks normal function. Typically they have long-standing hemiparesis of the contralateral body, which causes them to walk by circumducting the hip rather than with a normal leg swing. If the injury to one side of the brain occurs during infancy, patients can develop infantile hemiplegia-hemiatrophy with the contralateral side being smaller and weaker than the normal side. Hemispherectomy also is performed on patients who have hemimegalencephaly, Sturge-Weber or Rasmussen's encephalitis
Twenty to 30 years ago, hemispherectomy involved removing half of the brain completely. However, early enthusiasm for this operation was replaced by skepticism due to progressive neurologic deficits caused by superficial cerebral hemosiderosis. This complication most likely was due to small recurrent hemorrhages into the large surgical cavity associated with minor trauma and from lack of support for the remaining hemisphere. To limit the area of removal, multi-lobar resections, subtotal hemispherectomies and hemisphercortisectomies were performed instead. Although these procedures reduced the superficial hemosiderosis, they resulted in less seizure control, probably because seizures continue to arise from residual portions of the damaged hemisphere. To duplicate the good results of the complete hemispherectomy while avoiding cerebral hemosiderosis, several modifications have been devised. Currently the most common operation performed is the functional hemispherectomy. In this operation, the temporal lobe is removed, corpus callosotomy is performed, and the frontal and occipital lobes are disconnected. The blood supply to the remaining brain is left intact; hence, the skull remains filled on the side of the operation rather than being left with a large cavity.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #35
hypnagogue said:
That may well be, but that doesn't contradict anything I said.
Without explaining that damage to the reticular formation, or its communication to the intralaminar nuclei, causes coma by interrupting the functioning of the thalamo-cortical complex there is an implication that at least two separate areas exist where consciousness is developed, analagous, perhaps to the two language areas. That needed clearing up because the quote you posted didn't point out that the reason damage to the reticular formation can cause coma is not because it constitutes a full-blown separate consciousness area, but because damage there is de facto an interruption of the proper function of the thalamus.
I was mainly responding to your comment that "damage to the thalamus results in coma, which is not true of any other part of the brain." Essentially, this amounts to saying that the thalamus is the only brain region whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness.
Maybe and/or no, depending. I'm trying to convey my sense of the importance of the thalamus to consciousness without making any choices about what else might also be necessary. A thalamus in a vat would, almost certainly, not constitute a proper consciousness. What else, though, do you need? I don't know, but you have to start off with a thalamus, and build from there.

My statements in that post are highly qualified:

zoobyshoe said:
The thalamo-cortical complex referred to by Hypnagogue is, in fact, somehow[/color], the essential base of consciousness in the brain.
zoobyshoe said:
So, during the absense seizure, the whole brain seems to continue to function, except those parts responsible for something essential about consciousness, which I don't even know what to call[/color]: perhaps basic consciousness or baseline consciousness or foundation consciousness.

hypnagogue said:
This is false, since the reticular formation is part of the brain, and its proper functioning is also necessary for consciousness.
Because it moderates the functioning of the thalamus.
I assume when you say the thalamus is "vital" for consciousness, you mean that proper functioning of the thalamus presents sufficient conditions for consciousness:
It is necessary, vital that we have a thalamus presenting sufficient conditions for consciousness.
If X is necessary for Y...
You are employing the formalized reasoning discipline of logic here, a formal discipline with which I am only very vaguely familiar.
We know the reticular formation is necessary for consciousness...
By extenuating circumstances only. It's role is to moderate the activity of the thalamus. The analogy to a rheostat is not too bad, I think. Some patients with brainstem bleeds that impinge on the reticular formation don't go into a coma at all, rather, the opposite happens: they can't fall asleep. The reticular formation is being prevented from turning the volume down on their thalamus, so to speak.
-------
The term is in fact not theoretically loaded, but quite neutral. When we speak of neural correlates of consciousness, we refer only to correlations between neural activity and features of consciousness, while remaining neutral on the nature of the causative link that underlies that correlation.
(sotto voce: This, though, already bothers me. Speaking of the connection as a "correlate" suggests that the coiner of the term is operating with a "ghost in the machine" notion in the background.)
This consideration is basically just a refinement of the more general term "sufficient."
Chalmers must obviously have laid out a working definition of consciousness such that he can determine when sufficent conditions have been met. I've been trying to avoid getting into this can of worms, because I can't imagine there would be no challenges to his working definition.

Eating a large meal is sufficient to alleviate hunger. It is also true...
The whole large meal thing is pretty much baffling to me, because shouldn't the quest be to find the minimum amount of food that will be sufficient for the hungry person to say "I am no longer hungry?" The kinds of things you used in your example as "superfluous" don't strike me as on the mark for a good analogy. Wouldn't "superfluous" be any amount of food in excess of that which satisfies his hunger, rather than things like trays and trips to tibet?
-----
Ay any rate, my overall point in that post was to illustrate the kind of importance the thalamus has to consciousness with specific, real life examples of what happens when it is disturbed. Brain function and anatomy is all new to Q-Goest, but he's obviously actively curious about it.
 
  • #36
zoobyshoe said:
Without explaining that damage to the reticular formation, or its communication to the intralaminar nuclei, causes coma by interrupting the functioning of the thalamo-cortical complex there is an implication that at least two separate areas exist where consciousness is developed, analagous, perhaps to the two language areas.

There is no such implication so long as we understand the word "necessary" properly. In the same post where I copied that quote from Baars, I also pointed out that necessary conditions are not the most important thing to consider in the search for NCCs. I pointed out that a functional heart is a necessary condition for consciousness too, even though the heart should not be taken to be a correlate of consciousness-- there is certainly no implication that the heart is an area where consciousness is "developed" or anything like that, even though it is necessary for consciousness.

To state it again, this time without using formal logic: Necessary conditions can be thought of as enabling conditions. If X is necessary for Y, then Y cannot exist without X, but that doesn't entail that X is crucial for Y in any way beyond providing some sort of enabling role. For instance, in order to create a painting, it is necessary to have some sort of surface on which to paint. (I'll use the word 'canvas' to refer to any such surface.) Without a canvas, there can be no painting-- the canvas presents a kind of condition that enables the possibility of creating a painting. Still, it doesn't follow that merely being in possession of a canvas entails the existence of a painting.

Furthermore, if we say something like "a canvas is a necessary condition for the existence of a painting," we do not have to qualify this statement by saying something like "however, a canvas is only important insofar as it absorbs brush strokes, which is when the painting is really created." Such a qualification amounts to saying "the canvas is necessary, but not sufficient, for the existence of a painting." But we've already established that the canvas is necessary for the painting, and have not stated or implied anywhere that it is sufficient-- the question of its sufficiency is left open. So while it is helpful to specify that it is indeed not sufficient, it's not as if we need to come out and specify this in order to correct an error inherent in the original claim. Necessity does not imply sufficiency in any way at all.

If X is sufficient for Y, then the existence of X guarantees the concomitant existence of Y. It should be clear, then, that in the search for NCCs, we are interested in those neural systems whose activity is sufficient for consciousness-- we want to find those neural systems such that, whenever they function in a certain way, it is guaranteed that some feature of consciousness exists. In the painting example, certain kinds of brush strokes on a canvas would present sufficient conditions for the existence of a painting. So when we talk about what brings a painting into existence, what we're really interested in is the brush strokes. At the same time, we recognize the necessity of the canvas in order to enable those brush strokes to occur. We can say that, assuming we are given a canvas on which to paint, certain brush strokes are sufficient for the creation of a painting.

This squares pretty straightforwardly with Chalmers' definition of an NCC:

An NCC is a minimal neural system N such that there is a mapping from states of N to states of consciousness, where a given state of N is sufficient, under conditions C, for the corresponding state of consciousness.

The NCC is what presents sufficient conditions for consciousness, so that's what we're really interested in. At the same time, we recognize the necessity of certain other conditions to hold in order to enable these NCCs to be sufficient for consciousness. These necessary conditions are the background conditions C. The reticular formation and intralaminar nuclei are probably two neural systems included in C.

zoobyshoe said:
hypnagogue said:
I was mainly responding to your comment that "damage to the thalamus results in coma, which is not true of any other part of the brain." Essentially, this amounts to saying that the thalamus is the only brain region whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness.

Maybe and/or no, depending. I'm trying to convey my sense of the importance of the thalamus to consciousness without making any choices about what else might also be necessary.

You already did make such an implicit choice in the statement I quoted. If N is necessary for consciousness, then without N, consciousness cannot exist (by definition of "necessary"). In other words, if N is necessary for consciousness, then if N is substantially damaged, coma follows. The converse is also true: If N is substantially damaged and coma follows, then N must be necessary for consciousness. Thus, if the thalamus is the only brain region whose damage entails coma, then it follows that the thalamus is the only brain region that is necessary for consciousness. You claimed that the thalamus is indeed the only brain region whose damage entails coma, which is equivalent to saying that the thalamus is the only brain region that is necessary for consciousness. (Of course, we know there is at least one other neural system that is necessary for consciousness, the reticular formation.)

zoobyshoe said:
A thalamus in a vat would, almost certainly, not constitute a proper consciousness.

I agree. But if this is true, it follows that damaging every part of the brain but the thalamus would lead to coma (assuming the body is put on life support to prevent outright death). This contradicts the claim that the thalamus is the only part of the brain whose proper functioning is necessary for consciousness.

zoobyshoe said:
(sotto voce: This, though, already bothers me. Speaking of the connection as a "correlate" suggests that the coiner of the term is operating with a "ghost in the machine" notion in the background.)

I see absolutely no reason why this should bother you. It seems that the neutrality of the term "correlate" bothers you because it merely admits of the possibility of certain views on consciousness, and that in turn should only bother you if you think you already know the nature of the causal relationship between brain and consciousness with certainty. I hope that's not the case, because frankly, no one does right now.

The neutrality of the term itself certainly doesn't suggest one view or another-- how could it? It's neutral! The whole point is that we should be able to focus on the (relatively!) straightforward, empirical issue of what brain regions are related to what features of consciousness without getting bogged down in complicated, contentious, and ongoing theoretical arguments about the causal nature of that relation. The idea is to treat the data purely, as data, and leave the heavier theoretical stuff for other discussions. This can only be a good thing, as it clarifies and simplifies the empirical program.

And if you still don't trust the term on the unfortunate suspicion that it's being used for malicious philosophical purposes, consider the http://www.absoluteastronomy.com/encyclopedia/n/ne/neural_correlate_of_consciousness.htm : "The neural correlate of consciousness (NCC) is a term made popular by Francis Crick and Christof Koch in the early 1990s." Unless you think the inimitable scientist Crick has a volume of "ghost in the machine" literature to be published posthumously (perhaps currently in press), I think your concern here can be put to rest.

zoobyshoe said:
Chalmers must obviously have laid out a working definition of consciousness such that he can determine when sufficent conditions have been met. I've been trying to avoid getting into this can of worms, because I can't imagine there would be no challenges to his working definition.

Chalmers' paper merely clarifies what is meant by "NCC" (drawing heavily from how the term has been used in the scientific literature) and discusses some issues related to the scientific search for NCCs. The determination of what conditions are sufficient for consciousness is not some a priori matter of which Chalmers has constructed his own idiosynchratic version-- that is something that obviously must be discovered empirically.

To be honest, I am somewhat frustrated that you refuse to read the paper because of a preconceived notion of what the paper must be like, apparently based on the author. As I've said, the topic of NCCs is largely theory-neutral by definition, so it should stand to reason that Chalmers' own theories on the nature of the causal relation between the brain and consciousness do not figure into his discussion of NCCs. It is precisely because we are talking about the neural correlates of consciousness that the can of worms you fear does not rear its head.

To drive this point home, here again is the general definition of an NCC at which Chalmers arrives:

An NCC is a minimal neural system N such that there is a mapping from states of N to states of consciousness, where a given state of N is sufficient, under conditions C, for the corresponding state of consciousness.

He also offers a more specific definition for neural correlates of contents of consciousness:

An NCC (for content) is a minimal neural representational system N such that representation of a content in N is sufficient, under conditions C, for representation of that content in consciousness.

Now consider http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/Elsevier-NCC.html . Some selected quotes from the Crick and Koch paper:

"It is important to distinguish the general, enabling factors in the brain that are needed for any form of consciousness to occur from modulating ones that can up- or down-regulate the level of arousal, attention and awareness and from the specific factors responsible for a particular content of consciousness." (the enabling factors are the 'conditions C' in Chalmers' definition)

"The question motivating much of the current research into the neuronal basis of consciousness is the notion of the minimal neural activity that is sufficient to cause a specific conscious percept or memory."

"The specific processes that correlate with the current content of consciousness are referred to as the neuronal correlate of consciousness, or as the NCC. Whenever some information is represented in the NCC it is represented in consciousness." (note how this squares with Chalmers' definition of an NCC for contents of consciousness)

"The NCC is the minimal (minimal, since it is known that the entire brain is sufficient to give rise to consciousness) set of neurons, most likely distributed throughout certain cortical and subcortical areas, whose firing directly correlates with the perception of the subject at the time. Conversely, stimulating these neurons in the right manner with some yet unheard of technology should give rise to the same perception as before." ('direct correlation' and 'stimulating NCC neurons leads to some conscious percept' are different ways of talking about sufficiency)

zoobyshoe said:
The whole large meal thing is pretty much baffling to me, because shouldn't the quest be to find the minimum amount of food that will be sufficient for the hungry person to say "I am no longer hungry?" The kinds of things you used in your example as "superfluous" don't strike me as on the mark for a good analogy. Wouldn't "superfluous" be any amount of food in excess of that which satisfies his hunger, rather than things like trays and trips to tibet?

The degree to which one's hunger is satiated is a function of how much food one eats. If I would have constructed the analogy as you suggested, that would imply that all neural systems can present sufficient conditions for consciousness, if only they are somehow activated enough, or in the right manner. But as far as we know, that is not the case. There are plenty of unconscious neural mechanisms whose activity is never represented in consciousness under any circumstances.

For instance, consider the neural mechanism that guides the fine, complex, low level motor movements we make when we walk. We never have direct conscious access to the internal workings of this mechanism, and its functioning is never directly represented in all its gory detail in conscious awareness. If eating is to hunger satiation as (say) activity in the thalamus is to consciousness, then the brain's 'walking mechanism' is like watching TV. Its functioning is completely irrelevant to consciousness. Nonetheless, if it is true that the thalamus presents sufficient conditions for the existence of consciousness, it is also true that the thalamus and the 'walking mechanism,' taken together, are also sufficient for consciousness. But since the 'walking mechanism' is basically irrelevant to consciousness, we are not interested in it and want to strike it from the NCC records. We do this by looking for the minimally sufficient conditions for consciousness, those sufficient conditions for consciousness that do not include anything superfluous.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #37
hypnagogue said:
To be honest, I am somewhat frustrated...
I sense this in your whole post, and I think the conflict is one of method of approach. You are deeply immersed in a very structured, formal approach, and are not understanding why I'm not quick to adopt the same.

The formal discipline of logic is important for you because you are young, and planning to continue your formal education in this field. You are going to need to be able to speak about just about everything in logic terms. I am 50, and might only run into situations where it would be of use here and there, and only at PF. It's too much work to learn just to be able to engage in certain kinds of, for me, isolated discussions. Plus, I know you're fully capable of talking about all this at my level. I read a book here, a study there, talk to mentally ill people, people with brain damage, people with seizures. people with MS, and so forth, and, I believe, end up understanding quite a bit about the brain without also being able to state things in formal logic terms.

The majority of people I post to about the brain aren't trained in formal logic, and would lose interest in what I had to say if I translated things into those terms. It's hard enough, sometimes, maintaining their interest once you start using unfamiliar words like hippocampus, amygdala, parahippocampal gyrus, and such.

Also, I'm not resisting reading the Chalmers for any other reason than that it sounds like complex reading: new terms and new concepts to grasp and get used to. I don't recall ever hearing of him before this thread, and also don't know who Crick is, or any other name you've mentioned. I admit I may be wrong about the implications I read into the word "correlate" but that isn't why I haven't read it yet at all.
 
  • #38
Sorry if I read too much into your reply. I do think it's important to maintain some level of logical rigor when talking about somewhat complex subjects like this, though. For the purposes of this thread, formal logic isn't needed-- I just brought it up to try to illustrate a point with more clarity. However, it is important to distinguish between necessary and sufficient conditions, but I don't think that's too demanding.

btw, surely you know Francis Crick? Of Watson and Crick fame, discoverers of the structure of DNA. Crick redirected his scientific attention to consciousness in the latter stages of his career before his death.
 
  • #39
hypnagogue said:
I do think it's important to maintain some level of logical rigor when talking about somewhat complex subjects like this, though.
Well, I posted quite a bit, and if that was the only transgression you discovered to be worth highlighting, then there's hope.
btw, surely you know Francis Crick? Of Watson and Crick fame, discoverers of the structure of DNA. Crick redirected his scientific attention to consciousness in the latter stages of his career before his death.
I'm sure I've encountered the names before in connection with the DNA discovery, but I guess there was never any reason for it to stick in my memory. I know precious little about DNA.
 
  • #40
I was reading the first link from hypnagogue, and found this interesting:

"Then these neurons are monitored in the binocular rivalry situation, to see how well they correlate with what the monkey seems to be seeing. It turns out that cells in primary visual cortex (V1) don't correlate well: when the monkey is stimulated with horizontal and vertical gratings but "sees" horizontal, a large number of "vertical" cells in V1 fire, as well as "horizontal" cells. At this point, most cells seem to correlate with retinal stimulus, not with visual percept."

Your brain knows more than you do, huh?
 
  • #41
El Hombre Invisible said:
Your brain knows more than you do, huh?

There is tons of information in the brain that is not represented in consciousness at any given time. Computationally speaking, consciousness actually has quite limited capacity with respect to the brain as a whole. We run into these limitations all the time: We can only hold a paltry 6 or 7 units of information in working memory at a time, it's impossible for us to effectively attend to two sensory modalities (e.g., seeing and hearing) at once, etc.

Consciousness's functional utility isn't so much what it knows as much as it is 'who' it knows and how it contacts them. Consciousness has widespread access to a huge number of specialized neural subsystems, each of which is very good at performing highly specific tasks. Those subsystems help shape the things we actually are conscious of-- for instance, as you read this sentence, quite complex syntactic and semantic operations on the words are being performed in your brain. You are not aware of all this low-level activity, however. What is ultimately sent to your conscious awareness is a high-level understanding of the sentence that appears to 'come' to you quite automatically and effortlessly. Once a piece of information reaches conscious awareness, it is automatically 'broadcast' widely across the brain to numerous subconscious subsystems, which can then use that information to guide further perception and behavior, etc. So, functionally speaking, consciousness acts as a sort of integrator and disseminator of information in the brain, transmitting important global messages to specialized, local subsystems that otherwise function pretty 'blindly' and independently.
 
  • #42
BTW, Crick's last paper before his death, http://www.pubs.royalsoc.ac.uk/finalcrickpaper.shtml, was recently published. The claustrum is a thin sheet of neural tissue lying beneath the cortex on either hemisphere, receiving input from and projecting to most areas of cortex. In the paper, Crick and Koch speculate that the claustrum might play a crucial role in binding and coordinating various sensory percepts within and across most sensory and motor modalities, i.e. it might be the 'conductor' that organizes all the disparate information in the various regions of cortex into one coherent and synchronized whole in consciousness. As of yet this remains speculation, since the claustrum is situated in such a way that it is extremely rare that it becomes damaged while other brain regions remain intact, and it is particularly difficult to stimulate it using invasive measures, etc.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #43
Q_Goest said:
zoobyshoe, I enjoyed your comments. Many thanks.
You're very welcome.

Here is a link to an essay that contains the Ramachandran story in which I first heard about these patients:
Address:http://consc.net/misc/wired.html

You have to scroll way, way down to the section entitled One Hand Clapping.

Ramachandran's stories about these patients are interesting, but you should be able to see why I find his psychological explanation of the problem unconvincing.

Neurologist Berti in your article is much more to my liking in that she questions the validity of ascribing this exceptionally elaborate phenomenon to a cause as flimsy as denial: refusal to face the fact you have a problem.
I'm interpreting this as if the conscious portions of the brain are working properly but receiving improper inputs or are unable to properly connect to the body.
I think this is right. More: in addition to being "out of touch" with the paralyzed half, consciousness is receiving false information from within the brain due to the various mechanisms mentioned by me, and the neurologist in the article you posted, such that it feels like the planning and execution of movements are being carried out as usual.

Berti, the doctor in your article, doesn't go as far as I did to the next step, which was to say that, completely convinced by the sensations of movement, the brain "heals" any gap there may be between that sensation and the obvious sight of a paralyzed arm or leg, by hallucinating all the proper visuals to accompany the feeling. These people, by their own testimony, "see" their arms moving, and their hands clapping. I don't think they're lying, and I think they mean it literally.

I don't know the exact mechanism by which people have visual hallucinations whose content is directed by their own will and desires, but I can speculate it is accomplished by doing something similar to what the brain does during dreaming. In addition, I think these people can fall into this easily because the stroke damage throws everything somewhat off.

Although the portions of the brain responsible for performing those functions are not working properly, the lack of those functional areas does not directly impact the ability of the brain to be conscious or aware.
In general, yes. My view on this, though, is that everything you subtract diminishes consciousness: it has less imput.

I'm sure you'd enjoy The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat and An Anthropologist on Mars by Oliver Sacks. Learning what the brain does can be done in negativa, by learning what happens when parts of it go wrong. Sacks is a good writer, comes off as a warm person, and the stories are fascinating.
 
  • #44
Q_Goest said:
Zantra: It sounds like that hemispherectomy must not touch certain common areas of the brain such as the thalamus which is deep in the center somewhere above the brain stem.

The thalamus is actually composed of two symmetrical parts on either side of the brain, and the two sides of the thalamus seem to perform much the same functions. For instance, we've already talked about how damage to the intralaminar nuclei in the thalamus leads to coma. However, for coma to occur, both intralaminar nuclei need to be damaged. If only one is damaged, one can still maintain consciousness. If the original hemispherectomy procedures did indeed remove an entire half of the brain, then half of the thalamus was also removed. However, the remaining half of the thalamus would have been enough to maintain consciousness. From the description Zantra posted, it seems like modern hemispherectomies do not get deep enough to affect the thalamus.

http://ahsmail.uwaterloo.ca/kin356/ltm/thalamus_hypothalamus.html is a pictorial representation of a thalamus highlighting some of its anatomical features, and again you can see its symmetry.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #45
Hypnagogue, have you ever looked into the "defect of consciousness" that occurs in complex-partial seizures? With all this concentration on the thalamus, I just realized I'd lost sight of the non-thalamic defects of consciousness that give clues to how everything else contributes.
 
Last edited:
  • #46
hypnagogue

hypnagogue, thanks much for the clarification regarding the two halves of the thalamus. I'd be curious to know just how much of the thalamus could be destroyed before consciousness no longer could be maintained. If two symetrical but small fractions of the thalamus lost function for example, would that have an effect?

Second, would similar losses from both sides of the brain that did not include the thalamus result in some loss? In other words, assuming the brain is essentially symetrical like the thalamus, does either side perform some kind of back up to the other akin to a single failure tolerant system? The suggestion is that the thalamus is symetrical with two halves of possibly equal capability (ie: in regards to the support of consiousness). Do other parts of the brain organize themselves in similar ways? (Ex: If the brain is "single failure tolerant" with two halves of roughly equal capability, that might imply that neurons supporting the visual signals of say, the left eye, could be destroyed or otherwise rendered inoperable, without loss of vision, if (a BIG if) the opposite side of the brain was able to support those signals.)

Note that here I'm assuming a very mechanistic view of the brain in which portions of the brain crunch data and provide that output as input to a central portion of the brain which supports the conscious experience.

Note 2, it is understood that the thalamus may not contain the only NCC's, so the above can be rewritten by replacing "thalamus" with "NCC's".
 
  • #47
A general question

If there are portions of the brain which support consciousness, (NCC's) then one might assume a second question regards the difference between neurons, especially neurons within the thalamus and other NCC's and the nervous system in general. If there are sections of the nervous system which support consciousness, what is physically unique about them?

From what I've read, it would appear that nerve cells in general are very similar, and some with strictly dimensional differences, some with extremely long axons for example. I think I read somewhere that axons can extend essentially the length of one's leg, and axons from the thalamus can extend throughout the brain. But the clue IMHO would be to look inside to see what differences there are.

I seem to remember reading somewhere that there are neurons unique to the thalamus, with thalamus sounding names, so one must conclude there is a uniqueness within them which does not corrolate to their dimensions or other outward appearances.

Perhaps I'm only offering "easy" questions as Chalmers would say, but I have to believe these questions have already been answered.
 
  • #48
zoobyshoe

Thanks once more for, this time for the link. Andrew Brown writes with a brilliant flair one can't help but notice. There's so much to read on this subject and so little time, but moments of focus such as this one are worth their weight.
 
  • #50
Q_Goest said:
Thanks once more for, this time for the link. Andrew Brown writes with a brilliant flair one can't help but notice. There's so much to read on this subject and so little time, but moments of focus such as this one are worth their weight.
Andrew Brown is...the author of that article? I didn't sample much of his "flair". I just googled "Ramachandran" and when I got there, typed his name into my find on page button. So much to read, so little time.

Ramachandran is a flashy showman, and I was wondering what you might make of his discovery that squirting water in the ears of the "denial" stroke patients seemed to cause their awareness of their condition to come into full focus. This seems to belie his whole proposition that their "denial" is psychological confabulation.
 

Similar threads

Replies
9
Views
5K
Replies
52
Views
10K
Replies
2
Views
5K
Replies
15
Views
18K
Replies
5
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
7K
Back
Top