- 10,876
- 423
After some additional thought, I think I have to return to my previous position, or rather a refined version of it. If I define specific theories by "steps 1-2" stuff, they won't be falsifiable, and that's unacceptable to me. I think the only good way out of this is to let terms like "special relativity" and "quantum mechanics" refer to classes of theories instead of specific theories. The members of each class are what I previously (in #97) referred to as "versions" of a specific theory.
A full definition of a specific theory includes all of the following: (Forget my previous steps 1-3. This list replaces the old one).
Step 2 will actually be short. The statement "a clock measures the proper time of the curve in spacetime that represents its motion" is a good example of the sort of thing we will see in step 2. This particular statement tells us (when combined with the rest of steps 1-2) how to use clocks to find out how accurate some of the theory's predictions are, but it doesn't tell us what a clock is. That's why steps 1-2 only defines a class of theories. A theory must be falsifiable, but we need step 3 to get falsifiability. Each definition of the term "clock" would give us a different theory in the class of theories defined by the list of step 2 statements.
Step 3 is anything but short. It tells us e.g. what measuring devices we should call "clocks". An instruction manual that describes how to build a cesium clock would of course be very long. To understand step 3, one must understand the refinement process I talked about in #97.
In spite of what I just said, I would still find it more than OK to call special relativity a "theory". This is to be understood as a sloppy way of referring to the specific member (of the class of theories) that's singled out by the best definitions of measuring devices that we have at the moment. This terminology isn't any more sloppy than e.g. what we're doing when we define a group as a pair (G,*) and then start referring to G as a "group".
A full definition of a specific theory includes all of the following: (Forget my previous steps 1-3. This list replaces the old one).
- Definitions of mathematical terms.
- A set of statements that tells us how to use a piece of mathematics, and a given set of definitions of terms for measuring devices, to make predictions about results of experiments.
- Definitions of terms for measuring devices.
Step 2 will actually be short. The statement "a clock measures the proper time of the curve in spacetime that represents its motion" is a good example of the sort of thing we will see in step 2. This particular statement tells us (when combined with the rest of steps 1-2) how to use clocks to find out how accurate some of the theory's predictions are, but it doesn't tell us what a clock is. That's why steps 1-2 only defines a class of theories. A theory must be falsifiable, but we need step 3 to get falsifiability. Each definition of the term "clock" would give us a different theory in the class of theories defined by the list of step 2 statements.
Step 3 is anything but short. It tells us e.g. what measuring devices we should call "clocks". An instruction manual that describes how to build a cesium clock would of course be very long. To understand step 3, one must understand the refinement process I talked about in #97.
In spite of what I just said, I would still find it more than OK to call special relativity a "theory". This is to be understood as a sloppy way of referring to the specific member (of the class of theories) that's singled out by the best definitions of measuring devices that we have at the moment. This terminology isn't any more sloppy than e.g. what we're doing when we define a group as a pair (G,*) and then start referring to G as a "group".
Last edited: