Entanglement and teleportation

In summary: Entanglement is a very strong connection between particles, but it doesn't mean that information is always transmitted instantly. Information can take some time to propagate.
  • #71
kleinwolf said:
It's just because we don't understand QM.

I'd rather say: because the way you want do modify QM doesn't work :-)

But QM is omnipotent for everyone, just put : [tex]\chi=-\frac{\pi}{4}\Rightarrow p(diff)=1[/tex]

Yeah, that's the projection as is proposed in standard QM :-) So then it works...

But you claim that one should have a kind of "equal distribution" or so of outcomes (which clearly is NOT standard QM). And then you get silly results such as that the sum of the probabilities of all possibilities is not equal to 1.

In the other calculation, the sum add up to 1 in every case...

So what does it mean that the prob of the possible outcomes don't add up to 1 in everycase for the other calculation ?

It means that you have been cheating :-) You have in fact used normal quantum mechanics, except for the fact that you have been rotating the |-+> and the |+-> vectors in the "different" eigenspace. When you then calculate the total length (squared) of the original vector, projected on each of those and add it together, you obtain of course the correct QM prediction. Indeed, total length is invariant under a rotation of the basis (in the "different" eigenspace). But that's not what you were proposing in the first place. What you proposed was that the probability of having the "different" result should be the projection on ONE SINGLE arbitrary direction in the "different" eigenspace, not the sum of all the possibilities (which corresponds to finding the total length of the projection, as prescribed by standard QM). And then you're back to your first formula, where the sum of probabilities of all the possible outcomes is not equal to 1. THAT was the technique you used for the EPR stuff. You didn't sum over the different projections (because then you'd have found the same predictions as standard QM: you'd just have been rotating the basis vectors in the eigenspace to calculate the total projection length, something you are of course allowed to do).

cheers,
Patrick.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
Yes, basically I wrote you, it's just completely normal Copenhagen QM, there is nothing new in what I said...just trying to be more precise.

Anyway, for myself already gave the answer...but this, like always, is only my opinion...you have yours of course, but why say yours is the right one ??

Let's take the definition of the correlation : the following calculation is really old and well-known...but this maybe explains a bit more...I learn like you.

[tex] C(A,B)=<AB>-<A><B> [/tex]

then we have in fact a correlation operator given by the superposition of non-local and local opertators :

[tex] M_{non-local}=\sigma_z\otimes\sigma_z[/tex]
[tex] M_{local A}=\sigma_z\otimes\mathbb{I} [/tex]
[tex] M_{local B}=\mathbb{I}\otimes\sigma_z [/tex]

So that the correlation operator is :

[tex] C=M_{non-local}-M_{local_A}|\Psi\rangle\langle\Psi|M_{local_B} [/tex]

So that the correlation operator depends on the state we measure, hence this operator is non-linear.

We have also the correspondance : [tex]M_{non-local}=M_{local_A}M_{local_B}[/tex]

Now the fact is that the eigenstate of [tex]\mathhbb{I}[/tex] are degenerate. So if we look at the spectral decomposition of the identity operator, then we are lead to a more general equivalence that can be solved by doing some operations on the parametrization of the eigenstates describing the eigenspace, in other words : we should not only work with orthogonal bases. If we look nearer, then :

Let 2 eigenstates of 1 be :
[tex]|\phi\rangle=\left(\begin{array}{c}\cos(\phi)\\\sin(\phi)\end{array}\right)[/tex]
[tex]|\chi\rangle=\left(\begin{array}{c}\cos(\chi)\\\sin(\chi)\end{array}\right)[/tex]

Hence, this allows for non-orthogonal bases of R^2, the generalized spectral decomposition is :

[tex]\mathbb{I}_{decomp}=|\phi\rangle\langle\phi|+|\chi\rangle\langle\chi|=\left(\begin{array}{cc}\cos(\phi)^2+\cos(\chi)^2&\cos(\phi)\sin(\phi)+\cos(\chi)\sin(\chi)\\\cos(\phi)\sin(\phi)+\cos(\chi)\sin(\chi)&\sin(\phi)^2+\sin(\chi)^2\end{array}\right)[/tex]

Hence we have the relationships :

[tex] \mathbb{I}=\langle\mathbb{I}_{decomp}\rangle_{\phi,\chi} [/tex]

and the other precise decomposition that specifies the parameters :

[tex] \exists\phi_0,\chi_0|\mathbb{I}_{decomp}(\phi=\phi_0,\chi=\chi_0)=\mathbb{I} [/tex]

Now of course we can compute the complete correlation operator, that will give you expressions up to the 4th power in the cos and sin of the parameters...

What I basically want to know is if you consider this exchange about science as a game and you want to win...I feel a kind of something unhealthy in the air...because I don't really see what the game or the competition is...and you ?

Best regards.
 
Last edited:
  • #73
vanesch said:
Ok, that's the probability for the A+ detector to trigger. And what is the probability for the A- detector to trigger, then ? P = sin^2 |a - lambda| I'd say...

cheers,
Patrick.

EDIT:

I played around a bit with this, and in fact, it is not so easy to arrive at a CORRELATION function which is cos^2(a-b). Indeed, let's take your probability which is p(a+) = cos^2(lambda-a).
Assuming independent probabilities, we have then that the correlation, which is given by p(a+) p(b+) = cos^2(lambda-a) sin^2(lambda-b) for an individual event. (the b+ on the other side is the b- on "this" side)

Now, by the rotation symmetry of the problem, lambda has to be uniformly distributed between 0 and 2 Pi, so we have to weight this p(a+) p(b+) with this uniform distribution in lambda:

P(a+)P(b-) = 1/ (2 Pi) Integral (lambda=0 -> 2 Pi) cos^2(lambda-a) sin^2(lambda-b) d lambda.

If you do that, you find:

1/8 (2 - Cos(2 (a-b)) ) = 1/8 (3-2 Cos^2[a-b])

And NOT 1/2 sin^2(a-b) !

I checked this with a small Monte Carlo simulation in Mathematica and this comes out the same. Ok, in the MC I compared a+ with b+ (not with b-), and then the result is 1/8 (2+cos(2(a-b)))

So this specific model doesn't give us the correct, measured correlations...

cheers,
Patrick.

I attach the small Mathematica notebook with calculation...

I'm not sure what you're saying above.

The statement in question was that the cos^2 theta formula
is incompatible with hidden variables. It isn't. If you consider just
the individual results, then you can write the probability of
detection as P = cos^2 |a - lambda|, where a is the setting
of an individual polarizer and lambda is the emission polarization.
But of course you don't know the value of lambda ... ever. So,
the actual probability of individual detection is simply .5.
The reason it's .5 is because, presumably, lambda is varying
randomly -- and the data streams indicate that for any set
of n emissions you'll get, in the ideal, .5n detections.
Of course the actual number is modified enormously due
to efficiency considerations.

It can be shown, empirically, that there is a local hidden variable
determining individual detections.

However, while this local hidden variable exists, it does
not determine joint detection.

The combined context, when you're considering detection
at both ends during a given interval, is different in that, while
the local hidden variable is still determining individual results,
its *variability* isn't a factor in determining correlations.
The only thing about the emitted light that matters wrt
joint detection is that during any given detection interval
the light incident on the polarizers is the same at both
ends -- that any two opposite moving photons emitted
by the same atom are polarized identically. This is what
the *entanglement* is based on. If it wasn't assumed
that the two polarizers are analyzing light with the same
physical properties, then what would be the basis for the
projection along the detection axis?

So, during any given coincidence interval, the separated
polarizers are, in effect, analyzing the *same* light.
Hence, the applicability of the cos^2 theta formula in
the joint context involving crossed linear polarizers.
 
  • #74
DrChinese said:
Or Lambda=LHV does not exist, a possibility you consistently pass over. It is a simple matter to show that with a table of 8 permutations on A/B/C, there are no values that can be inserted that add to 100% without having negative values at certain angle settings.

A=___ (try 0 degrees)
B=___ (try 67.5 degrees)
C=___ (try 45 degrees)

Hypothetical hidden variable function: __________ (should be cos^2 or at least close)

1. A+ B+ C+: ___ %
2. A+ B+ C-: ___ %
3. A+ B- C+: ___ %
4. A+ B- C-: ___ %
5. A- B+ C+: ___ %
6. A- B+ C-: ___ %
7. A- B- C+: ___ %
8. A- B- C-: ___ %

It is the existence of C that relates to the hidden variable function. What you describe is just fine as long as we are talking about A and B only. (Well, there are still some problems but there is wiggle room for those determined to keep the hidden variables.) But with C added, everything falls apart as you can see.

You can talk all day long about joint probabilities and lambda, but that continues to ignore the fact that you cannot make the above table work out. If you are testing something else, you are ignoring Bell. After you account for the above table, then your explanation might make sense. Meanwhile, the Copenhagen Interpretation (and MWI) accounts for the facts that LHV cannot.

I've considered the idea that the lhv
doesn't exist and rejected it.

There's a difference between the lhv not existing
and the lhv being irrelevant in a certain context.
I agree with you that the lhv is not determining
joint detection -- but, that doesn't mean that
it doesn't *exist*.

The above table is irrelevant to the
argument of whether or not the lhv *exists*.

The individual data streams are *direct*
evidence of the existence of the lhv.
 
  • #75
DrChinese said:
There are definitely TWO ways to look at that statement. Some of the vocal local realists argue that the cos^2 law isn't correct!

Then I think they're wrong about that.

DrChinese said:
They do that so the Bell Inequality can be respected; and then explain that experimental loopholes account for the difference between observation and their theory.

From what I know of the experiments, they're ok. However,
I think that Bell's analysis and the physical meaning of experimental
violations of the inequality are being misinterpreted.

DrChinese said:
Clearly, classical results sometimes match QM and sometimes don't; and when they don't, you really must side with the predictions of QM. Even Einstein saw that this was a steamroller he had to ride, and the best he could muster was that QM was incomplete.

I *am* siding with the predictions of qm. Where have I
said otherwise? But it's certainly not a complete description
of the physical reality. It's not designed to be.
 
  • #76
Sherlock said:
I'm not sure what you're saying above.

The statement in question was that the cos^2 theta formula
is incompatible with hidden variables. It isn't. If you consider just
the individual results, then you can write the probability of
detection as P = cos^2 |a - lambda|, where a is the setting
of an individual polarizer and lambda is the emission polarization.
But of course you don't know the value of lambda ... ever.

Well, yes, that's exactly what I did. But apparently now you assume EQUAL polarizations (lambda) at both sides, and not OPPOSITE polarizations. So be it.

For a GIVEN lambda (unknown, I agree), you say that, if we put up a polarizer at Alice in direction a, it has a probability equal to cos^2(a-lambda) of clicking (assuming it "100% efficient" ; we'll come to that later). This means then also, I would think, that we have a probability cos^2(a-lambda) of clicking at Bob's place if he also puts his polarizer in direction a, right ?
And if Bob puts his polarizer in direction b, I assume that his probability of clicking for the same lambda is cos^2(b-lambda), right ?
Of course, specifying individual probabilities doesn't give us the joint distribution, except if you say that these probabilities are independent. But normally, what happens at Bob is independent of what happens at Alice, once lambda is given. So the JOINT PROBABILITY that the detector (in direction a) at Alice clicks, and that within the same time interval, the detector (in direction b at Bob) clicks is then given by

P(a,b,lambda) = cos^2(a-lambda) cos^2(b-lambda)

If that is not the case, then give me your joint probability for a given lambda.

Now, you say that we don't know lambda (which is the random polarization direction of the light sent out to both detectors in any event).
But we know that the distribution, whatever it is, must be rotation-invariant if we consider many events. Indeed, this is the only way to have, on one side, a probability equal to 1/2 averaged over the entire sample for ALL values of a. This means that the DISTRIBUTION of the different lambda values must be uniform over the 0 - 2Pi interval. Otherwise, we'd have on average MORE clicks in one direction than in another (on one single side).

Now, if we know that lambda, over different trials, is distributed uniformly, then we can calculate, over this population, what will be the average correlation P(a,b):
It is simply given by:

P(a,b) = 1/2Pi integral(lambda=0 -> 2 Pi) of P(a,b,lambda) d lambda

And if you do that, well, then you find:

P(a,b) = 1/8 (2 + cos(2 (a-b)) )

What changes now when the detectors are "inefficient" ? Well, this changes normally only the probability of clicking: instead of your "cos^2(a - lambda), we have a scale factor: epsilon cos^2(a - lambda). BTW, that is exactly what you get out of the semi-classical approach for the photo-electric effect.

The only thing it changes for P(a,b) is that you multiply with epsilon^2 (assuming detectors of identical quality on both sides).

The combined context, when you're considering detection
at both ends during a given interval, is different in that, while
the local hidden variable is still determining individual results,
its *variability* isn't a factor in determining correlations.
The only thing about the emitted light that matters wrt
joint detection is that during any given detection interval
the light incident on the polarizers is the same at both
ends -- that any two opposite moving photons emitted
by the same atom are polarized identically. This is what
the *entanglement* is based on. If it wasn't assumed
that the two polarizers are analyzing light with the same
physical properties, then what would be the basis for the
projection along the detection axis?

Well, that's exactly what I do. You give me the individual probabilities for a given value of the hidden variable, and from that, and a symmetry argument, I calculate the joint probability over the entire population of the hidden variable.

And comes out... something that is different than what QM predicts ! Ok, the "right" form is there, namely cos^2, but the "modulation depth" is much lower: you do not reach high enough correlations, but more importantly, you do not reach LOW ENOUGH correlations for certain angles either.
You can intuitively see that too.

If the polarizers at Bob and Alice are perpendicular, then according to the photon picture, you will have perfect ANTICORRELATION. Namely whenever the photon gets through Bob's, it is blocked for sure at Alice's and vice versa. Now, with classical light that cannot happen, because certain light pulses will get in under 45 degrees. That means that there is a reduced, but finite probability at Alice's of clicking, and also at Bob's, so the correlation will not be 0. Nevertheless, experimentally, it is 0, and according to the photon picture, it should also be 0.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #77
Gosh...I should never have started with non-linear operators...anybody knows about the eigenvalues, or something like that...

For I get that the eigenvalues of the non-linear operator of the local part of the correlation of a bipartite system given by : [tex]M_{local}=(\sigma_z\otimes\mathbb{I})|\Psi><\Psi|(\mathbb{I}\otimes\sigma_z)[/tex]

are negative definite, continuous apparently, and need to solve a 4th order equation system of the style :

[tex] b^4+(2c-1)b^3-2c^2b^2-2c^2b+c^4=0 [/tex]
[tex] a^2=c^2-b^2[/tex]
[tex] d^2=-w[/tex]
[tex] a^2+b^2+c^2+d^2=1[/tex]

where the eigenstate is given by : [tex]|\Psi>=(a,b,c,d)[/tex]

In fact the notation [tex]M_{local}[/tex] is abusive, since the wavefunction is included, so that's why the average correlation is still non-local (I privately exchanged messages with RandallB before about why I came up with a non-perfect correlation for the singlet-state, giving CHSH=2.47 at maximum (hence non-local w.resp. to Bell's Ansatz, but still neare to experimental results 2.25)...

It's clear that if the total correlation operator is taken (with the local and the non-local parts), then, the eigenvalues should be in [-1;1]...but maybe the spectrum is a special one, with an infinite distribution, I cannot make any bet about that...What is your opinion ?
 
Last edited:
  • #78
Sherlock said:
I've considered the idea that the lhv
doesn't exist and rejected it.

There's a difference between the lhv not existing
and the lhv being irrelevant in a certain context.
I agree with you that the lhv is not determining
joint detection -- but, that doesn't mean that
it doesn't *exist*.

The above table is irrelevant to the
argument of whether or not the lhv *exists*.

The individual data streams are *direct*
evidence of the existence of the lhv.

That isn't so... it is just a question of seeing what you want to see.

Suppose the random value is inserted when the observation is made - supplied by some randomizer which we cannot access and never can. That is a reasonable explanation and completely consistent with the facts. You see the randomness as evidence that there is more to know. Well, maybe that is so. But... that random value DID NOT exist prior to the observation, as Bell clearly tells us.

Now suppose the "random" value is not random at all - it is completely determined by some complex stochastic process having to do with the state of the entire universe. Because it is non-local, the same information is available to the entangled photons. That could be a reasonable explanation and consistent with the facts. Bell would still apply! And thus we know that the observations were still fundamental to the process, and there is no locally hidden variable that explains the observed results.

The observer settings are fundamental to the results; and there are no local hidden variables that completely determine the outcome independent of the observer settings. As Bell states, the purpose of LHV theories is to restore locality and causality to the description, and this cannot be done.
 
  • #79
I would like to point out, again, that when people (sherlock) say that classical optics gives us the probability of joint detection equal to cos^2(a-b), then this is NOT true. But as many people stated that, I believed it for a while myself. However, as I tried to show, if you assume the following:

1) Intensity of (classical) radiation when incident radiation has polarization direction lambda and the polarizer has direction a is given by the original intensity multiplied by cos^2(lambda-a).

2) Identical incident radiation (during one "pulse") at Alice's and Bob's, with identical (or opposite, pick your choice) polarization directions

3) photodetection probability (clicking probability) proportional to intensity, and, for a given intensity, statistically independent of any other photodetection somewhere else.

If we assume that the source sends out pulse trains, each with an (unknown) value of polarization, and equal intensity, then:

The probability at Alice (polarizer at angle a) of clicking is:
P(a,lambda) = eps cos^2(a - lambda)

The probability at Bob (polarizer at angle b) of clicking is:
P(b,lambda) = eps cos^2(b - lambda)

and the probability of clicking together, these probabilities being considered independent, is given by:

P(a,b,lambda) = eps^2 cos^2(a-lambda) cos^2(b-lambda)

From a symmetry argument, one can deduce that lambda must be drawn from a uniform distribution between 0 and 2 Pi, and so, the observed overall probabilities of clicking on N trials are:

[tex] P(a) = \frac{1}{2 \pi} \int_{\lambda = 0}^{2 \pi} \epsilon \cos^2(a - \lambda) d \lambda = 1/2 [/tex]

Same for P(b)

and for P(a,b):
[tex] P(a,b) = \frac{1}{2 \pi} \int_{\lambda = 0}^{2 \pi} \epsilon^2 \cos^2(a - \lambda)\cos^2(b - \lambda) d\lambda [/tex]

and this leads to:
[tex] P(a,b) = \frac{\epsilon^2 }{8} (2 + \cos 2 (a - b)) [/tex]

Of course we don't know the absolute number of trials (the true value of epsilon) if we don't consider the photon model, but we can do away with that by calculating:

[tex] \frac{P(a,b)}{P(a) P(b)} = \frac{1}{2} (2 + \cos 2(a-b))[/tex]

Note that this is NOT equal to the quantum prediction, especially for the fact that the above correlation function doesn't go down to 0, when the two polarizers are perpendicular.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #80
My previous message may give the impression that one cannot obtain a cos^2(a-b) curve with a hidden variable model. This is not true, and I just made one. It goes as follows:
Imagine that each pair of light pulses that is sent out has two hidden variables: one is lambda, the polarization direction (which will be uniformly distributed in 0-2Pi) and the other one is a one-bit random variable: if the Alice pulse receives the 1 bit, then the Bob pulse receives the 0 bit, and vice versa. This random variable is distributed 50/50, and we call it the tau variable.

Now, a polarizer could work in the following way, upon reception of a light pulse with hidden variables lambda and tau:
If tau = 1, then the intensity that gets through the polarizer under angle a equals the incoming intensity if |a - lambda|< delta (a small angle) and is blocked completely if not.
However, if tau = 0, then the intensity that gets through the polarizer is equal to the incoming intensity times cos^2(a - lambda).

Next, the probability of a detector click is proportional to the incoming intensity.

Applying this model yields a correlation about proportional to cos^2(a-b). Mind you, I say: proportional !

Indeed, for the individual polarizers, we get essentially 1/4 of the total number of trials (half of the time we get a bit 1, so then the probability of letting any intensity through is very rare, because lambda needs to be close to a, and the other half of the time, we get the cos^2 curve, which gives us 1/2 on average).
However, for the coincidence, in order for both to click, one of both will have a bit 1. So we KNOW that we are in one of the rare cases when lambda is close, or to a, or to b. In that case, the OTHER polarizer receives the 0 bit, and hence the probability for the OTHER one of clicking is given by the cos^2 rule. Only, we suppressed seriously the entire population and a very small fraction of the trials do give rise to a correlation. But if we add in arbitrary "efficiency" coefficients, we can say that we have a cos^2 relation.

This ad hoc model suffers of course from a lot of difficulties and is made up for the purpose. First of all, this is not classical optics either. The bit left or right mechanism is totally taken out of thin air. Next, although this model can explain certain aspects of the cos^2 curve, it would fail miserably on energy balances: we wouldn't have conservation of total radiant energy when taking the flux that gets through a polarizer, and that gets to the perpendicular polarizer.
But it is a technique to show that a curve, proportional to cos^2 can eventually be constructed.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #81
vanesch said:
I would like to point out, again, that when people (sherlock) say that classical optics gives us the probability of joint detection equal to cos^2(a-b), then this is NOT true. But as many people stated that, I believed it for a while myself. However, as I tried to show, if you assume the following:

1) Intensity of (classical) radiation when incident radiation has polarization direction lambda and the polarizer has direction a is given by the original intensity multiplied by cos^2(lambda-a).

2) Identical incident radiation (during one "pulse") at Alice's and Bob's, with identical (or opposite, pick your choice) polarization directions

3) photodetection probability (clicking probability) proportional to intensity, and, for a given intensity, statistically independent of any other photodetection somewhere else.

If we assume that the source sends out pulse trains, each with an (unknown) value of polarization, and equal intensity, then:

The probability at Alice (polarizer at angle a) of clicking is:
P(a,lambda) = eps cos^2(a - lambda)

The probability at Bob (polarizer at angle b) of clicking is:
P(b,lambda) = eps cos^2(b - lambda)

and the probability of clicking together, these probabilities being considered independent, is given by:

P(a,b,lambda) = eps^2 cos^2(a-lambda) cos^2(b-lambda)

From a symmetry argument, one can deduce that lambda must be drawn from a uniform distribution between 0 and 2 Pi, and so, the observed overall probabilities of clicking on N trials are:

[tex] P(a) = \frac{1}{2 \pi} \int_{\lambda = 0}^{2 \pi} \epsilon \cos^2(a - \lambda) d \lambda = 1/2 [/tex]

Same for P(b)

and for P(a,b):
[tex] P(a,b) = \frac{1}{2 \pi} \int_{\lambda = 0}^{2 \pi} \epsilon^2 \cos^2(a - \lambda)\cos^2(b - \lambda) d\lambda [/tex]

and this leads to:
[tex] P(a,b) = \frac{\epsilon^2 }{8} (2 + \cos 2 (a - b)) [/tex]

Of course we don't know the absolute number of trials (the true value of epsilon) if we don't consider the photon model, but we can do away with that by calculating:

[tex] \frac{P(a,b)}{P(a) P(b)} = \frac{1}{2} (2 + \cos 2(a-b))[/tex]

Note that this is NOT equal to the quantum prediction, especially for the fact that the above correlation function doesn't go down to 0, when the two polarizers are perpendicular.

cheers,
Patrick.


Excuse me for it is hard to read a long English texts for me. Because it is ordinary I read texts with mathematics only.
We can clear see that Bell's Inequalities it is possible to complete by curved and stationary geometry, which play role the non-local hidden variables. Why the geometry must be non-curved? Curved geometry is more suitable because it is the general case.
In that case Bell's Inequalities will be violet!
It is clear from
Correlation factor M of random variables [tex]\lambda ^{i}[/tex] are projections
onto directions [tex]A^{\nu }[/tex] and [tex]B^{n}[/tex] defined by polarizers (all these
vectors being unit) is

[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \left\langle AB\right\rangle \right| =\left|
\langle \lambda ^{i}A^{k}g_{ik}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}g_{mn}\rangle \right|[/tex]

The deferential geometry gives

[tex]\cos \Phi =\frac{g_{ik}\lambda ^{i}A^{k}}{\sqrt{\lambda ^{i}\lambda _{i}}\sqrt{A^{k}A_{k}}}[/tex],

[tex]\cos (\Phi +\theta )=\frac{g_{mn}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}}{\sqrt{\lambda
^{m}\lambda _{m}}\sqrt{B^{n}B_{n}}}[/tex].

Here i,k,m,n possesses 0,1,2,3; [tex]\theta [/tex] is angle between polarizers, then
[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \frac{1}{2\pi }\int_{0}^{2\pi }\rho (\Phi
)\cos \Phi \cos \left( \Phi +\theta \right) d\Phi \right| [/tex]

This the case when entanglement explained be by stationary gravitational fields (curved geometry) is perspective, I hope.
 
Last edited:
  • #82
vanesch said:
I would like to point out, again, that when people (sherlock) say that classical optics gives us the probability of joint detection equal to cos^2(a-b), then this is NOT true. But as many people stated that, I believed it for a while myself. However, as I tried to show, if you assume the following:

Patrick,

I don't mean to pick apart words. But there are two ways to interpret the situation you describe. You are of course correct that the application of Malus' Law in the "classical" manner you describe yields a different prediction for joint detection.

But that is not the only way to apply Malus' Law to this case. Since it describes the results only when initial polarizeration is KNOWN, you should wait to apply it until an observation is performed on one or the other of the entangled photons...similar to how it is done in classical application (in which the first polarizer tells us the initial polarization). Then the joint results will match QM exactly.

In other words, if you apply Malus' Law ASSUMING hidden variables, you get a different result (for joint detection) than if you apply it using (what I think of as) a "traditional" application which does not specifically assume HV. Presumably, Malus never thought of hidden variables one way or the other.

So to summarize: if you push a "classical" application of Malus' Law as you describe, you immediately run into problems because the results disagree with experiment (as you pointed out). If you push the hidden variable version and apply as I described, you immediately run into problems with Bell's Theorem. So you know that there is something wrong with the "classical" or "traditional" views (which are just labels as I have used them here) either way you choose to look at it.
 
  • #83
DrChinese said:
But that is not the only way to apply Malus' Law to this case. Since it describes the results only when initial polarizeration is KNOWN, you should wait to apply it until an observation is performed on one or the other of the entangled photons...similar to how it is done in classical application (in which the first polarizer tells us the initial polarization). Then the joint results will match QM exactly.

Because people told this already a few times, intuitively I thought that that was very acceptable, and that's why for a long time I thought that "classical optics" predicted the same correlations as quantum theory.
When you apply it as you state, when you say: ah, one detector clicked, so the light MUST BE in the same polarization direction as that polarizer, YOU ARE IN FACT APPLYING QUANTUM THEORY ! You projected and normalized the ENTIRE state on the direction of the first polarizer, as is typically done in QM (in the Copenhagen view, let's be clear).
But that is NOT what is done in classical optics. In classical optics a polarizer ONLY SELECTS THE COMPONENT of the light in the direction of the polarizer FOR THE LIGHT AT THAT POLARIZER. When you send light polarized under 45 degrees with the polarizer, only HALF of the intensity gets through ; and if you have two "identical copies of light" (as entanglement is seen in classical optics), it is not because on one side, you selected only half of the intensity (because your polarizer made an angle of 45 degrees) that suddenly the light will jump over 45 degrees on the other side to match the detection. That is a typical pure quantum phenomenon.

And that's why I wanted to point out, that, in the case Alice and Bob put their polarizers at 90 degrees, in the classical picture, THERE IS STILL LIGHT COMING THROUGH at both sides: namely all that light that is not exactly polarized at 0 or at 90 degrees. If light is incident under 45 degrees, at both sides, they get half the intensity, so there is a real chance of having coincident clicks.

In other words, if you apply Malus' Law ASSUMING hidden variables, you get a different result (for joint detection) than if you apply it using (what I think of as) a "traditional" application which does not specifically assume HV. Presumably, Malus never thought of hidden variables one way or the other.

I was not really using "hidden variables" ; the "hidden variable" was the random polarization of classical light. We know that the source sent out light pulses which have identical polarization for bob and alice, wavetrain per wavetrain. But this common polarization can fluctuate randomly (as the phase of light can fluctuate randomly outside of the coherence time). There is nothing surprising about that in classical optics.
Then I calculated the light intensity that got through each polarizer individually, using Malus' law, and then I applied a probability law for each photodetector, that gives us a probability of clicking per unit of time which is proportional to the incident intensity (after the polarizer).
I would think that that is exactly what one is supposed to do in classical optics, no ? I didn't "push" anything.

So to summarize: if you push a "classical" application of Malus' Law as you describe, you immediately run into problems because the results disagree with experiment (as you pointed out). If you push the hidden variable version and apply as I described, you immediately run into problems with Bell's Theorem. So you know that there is something wrong with the "classical" or "traditional" views (which are just labels as I have used them here) either way you choose to look at it.

Yes, of course. But it just appeared to me that what I had been taking for granted because so many people said it, namely that in PURELY CLASSICAL OPTICS, you get out the same correlations as in quantum theory, is absolutely not true ! And the most striking aspect is again the pure ANTI correlation when Alice and bob have perpendicular polarizers, which is impossible to obtain in classical optics. (but for which you can build an ad hoc hidden variable model, as I did - without physical plausibility).

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #84
cartuz said:
Excuse me for it is hard to read a long English texts for me. Because it is ordinary I read texts with mathematics only.
We can clear see that Bell's Inequalities it is possible to complete by curved and stationary geometry, which play role the non-local hidden variables. Why the geometry must be non-curved? Curved geometry is more suitable because it is the general case.
In that case Bell's Inequalities will be violet!
It is clear from
Correlation factor M of random variables [tex]\lambda ^{i}[/tex] are projections
onto directions [tex]A^{\nu }[/tex] and [tex]B^{n}[/tex] defined by polarizers (all these
vectors being unit) is

[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \left\langle AB\right\rangle \right| =\left|
\langle \lambda ^{i}A^{k}g_{ik}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}g_{mn}\rangle \right|[/tex]

The deferential geometry gives

[tex]\cos \Phi =\frac{g_{ik}\lambda ^{i}A^{k}}{\sqrt{\lambda ^{i}\lambda _{i}}\sqrt{A^{k}A_{k}}}[/tex],

[tex]\cos (\Phi +\theta )=\frac{g_{mn}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}}{\sqrt{\lambda
^{m}\lambda _{m}}\sqrt{B^{n}B_{n}}}[/tex].

Here i,k,m,n possesses 0,1,2,3; [tex]\theta [/tex] is angle between polarizers, then
[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \frac{1}{2\pi }\int_{0}^{2\pi }\rho (\Phi
)\cos \Phi \cos \left( \Phi +\theta \right) d\Phi \right| [/tex]

This the case when entanglement explained be by stationary gravitational fields (curved geometry) is perspective, I hope.

Well, in fact in this case, then Bell's idea is not really reached because you have something like :

[tex] M_{AB}=\frac{1}{2\pi}\int_0^{2\pi}\cos(\theta_A-\phi)\cos(\theta_B-\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]
[tex]=\int_0^{2\pi}A(\theta_A,\phi)B(\theta_B,\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]

But your functions A and B ARE NOT THE RESULTS OF MEASUREMENT (because the results can be only 1 and -1)...That's why Bell could deduce a difference between hidden variable and QM...Remind that the results of measurement of the quantum-mechanical operator [tex](\sigma\cdot n_A)\otimes(\sigma\cdot n_B)[/tex] are +1 or -1 (the eigenvalues)...but nothing is allowed inbetween.

What you could say is that in your case :[tex] A(\theta_A,\phi)=\int a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)u(\lamda)d\lambda[/tex]

where [tex]a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)=+1,-1[/tex]

So that then you can apply Bell's theorem on a,b...so that your proposition doesn't violate the inequqality (CHSH for example).
 
  • #85
cartuz said:
Excuse me for it is hard to read a long English texts for me. Because it is ordinary I read texts with mathematics only.
We can clear see that Bell's Inequalities it is possible to complete by curved and stationary geometry, which play role the non-local hidden variables. Why the geometry must be non-curved? Curved geometry is more suitable because it is the general case.
In that case Bell's Inequalities will be violet!
It is clear from
Correlation factor M of random variables [tex]\lambda ^{i}[/tex] are projections
onto directions [tex]A^{\nu }[/tex] and [tex]B^{n}[/tex] defined by polarizers (all these
vectors being unit) is

[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \left\langle AB\right\rangle \right| =\left|
\langle \lambda ^{i}A^{k}g_{ik}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}g_{mn}\rangle \right|[/tex]

The deferential geometry gives

[tex]\cos \Phi =\frac{g_{ik}\lambda ^{i}A^{k}}{\sqrt{\lambda ^{i}\lambda _{i}}\sqrt{A^{k}A_{k}}}[/tex],

[tex]\cos (\Phi +\theta )=\frac{g_{mn}\lambda ^{m}B^{n}}{\sqrt{\lambda
^{m}\lambda _{m}}\sqrt{B^{n}B_{n}}}[/tex].

Here i,k,m,n possesses 0,1,2,3; [tex]\theta [/tex] is angle between polarizers, then
[tex]\left| M_{AB}\right| =\left| \frac{1}{2\pi }\int_{0}^{2\pi }\rho (\Phi
)\cos \Phi \cos \left( \Phi +\theta \right) d\Phi \right| [/tex]

This the case when entanglement explained be by stationary gravitational fields (curved geometry) is perspective, I hope.

Well, in fact in this case, then Bell's idea is not really reached because you have something like :

[tex] M_{AB}=\frac{1}{2\pi}\int_0^{2\pi}\cos(\theta_A-\phi)\cos(\theta_B-\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]
[tex]=\int_0^{2\pi}A(\theta_A,\phi)B(\theta_B,\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]

But your functions A and B are not the results of measurement (because the results can be only 1 and -1)...That's why Bell could deduce a difference between hidden variable and QM...Remind that the results of measurement of the quantum-mechanical operator [tex](\sigma\cdot n_A)\otimes(\sigma\cdot n_B)[/tex] are +1 or -1 (the eigenvalues)...but nothing is allowed inbetween.

What you could say is that in your case :[tex] A(\theta_A,\phi)=\int a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)u(\lambda)d\lambda[/tex]

where [tex]a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)=+1,-1[/tex]

So that then you can apply Bell's theorem on a,b...so that it seems your proposition doesn't violate the inequality (CHSH for example).

The point is that if the correlation is expressed as hidden variables only :

[tex] C(A,B)=\int_a^b a(\vec{n}_A,\vec{\lambda})b(\vec{n}_A,\vec{\lambda})\rho(\vec{\lambda})d\lambda_1...d\lambda_n[/tex]

Then Bell's inequality is respected..(where a,b are constant (e.g. infinity or 0->2pi)...

however, if the correlation contains a visible variable :

[tex] C(A,B,\mu)=\int_{f(\mu)}^{g(\mu)}A(n_A,\lambda,\mu)B(n_B,\lambda,\mu)\rho(\lambda,\mu)d\lambda[/tex]

Then you can violate the inequality, in the sense you choose [tex]\mu[/tex] so that you cannot factorize the results like in Bell's theorem.
 
Last edited:
  • #86
kleinwolf said:
Well, in fact in this case, then Bell's idea is not really reached because you have something like :

[tex] M_{AB}=\frac{1}{2\pi}\int_0^{2\pi}\cos(\theta_A-\phi)\cos(\theta_B-\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]
[tex]=\int_0^{2\pi}A(\theta_A,\phi)B(\theta_B,\phi)\rho(\phi)d\phi [/tex]

But your functions A and B are not the results of measurement (because the results can be only 1 and -1)...That's why Bell could deduce a difference between hidden variable and QM...Remind that the results of measurement of the quantum-mechanical operator [tex](\sigma\cdot n_A)\otimes(\sigma\cdot n_B)[/tex] are +1 or -1 (the eigenvalues)...but nothing is allowed inbetween.

What you could say is that in your case :[tex] A(\theta_A,\phi)=\int a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)u(\lambda)d\lambda[/tex]

where [tex]a(\theta_A,\phi,\lambda)=+1,-1[/tex]

So that then you can apply Bell's theorem on a,b...so that it seems your proposition doesn't violate the inequality (CHSH for example).

The point is that if the correlation is expressed as hidden variables only :

[tex] C(A,B)=\int_a^b a(\vec{n}_A,\vec{\lambda})b(\vec{n}_A,\vec{\lambda})\rho(\vec{\lambda})d\lambda_1...d\lambda_n[/tex]

Then Bell's inequality is respected..(where a,b are constant (e.g. infinity or 0->2pi)...

however, if the correlation contains a visible variable :

[tex] C(A,B,\mu)=\int_{f(\mu)}^{g(\mu)}A(n_A,\lambda,\mu)B(n_B,\lambda,\mu)\rho(\lambda,\mu)d\lambda[/tex]

Then you can violate the inequality, in the sense you choose [tex]\mu[/tex] so that you cannot factorize the results like in Bell's theorem.
Thank you for reply and excuse me for delay.Are this mean that I
must to add here [tex]\mu[/tex] which have the sense of distribution of metric [tex]g_{ik}[/tex]?
Yes, I understand that metric allow correlated different quantatives in the space.
 
  • #87
Sherlock said:
The statement in question was that the cos^2 theta formula
is incompatible with hidden variables. It isn't. If you consider just
the individual results, then you can write the probability of
detection as P = cos^2 |a - lambda|, where a is the setting
of an individual polarizer and lambda is the emission polarization.

vanesch said:
Well, yes, that's exactly what I did. But apparently now you
assume EQUAL polarizations (lambda) at both sides, and not
OPPOSITE polarizations. So be it.

For a GIVEN lambda (unknown, I agree), you say that, if we put up a polarizer at Alice in direction a, it has a probability equal to cos^2(a-lambda) of clicking (assuming it "100% efficient" ; we'll come to that later). This means then also, I would think, that we have a probability cos^2(a-lambda) of clicking at Bob's place if he also puts his polarizer in direction a, right ?
And if Bob puts his polarizer in direction b, I assume that his probability of clicking for the same lambda is cos^2(b-lambda), right ?
Of course, specifying individual probabilities doesn't give us the joint distribution, except if you say that these probabilities are independent. But normally, what happens at Bob is independent of what happens at Alice, once lambda is given. So the JOINT PROBABILITY that the detector (in direction a) at Alice clicks, and that within the same time interval, the detector (in direction b at Bob) clicks is then given by

P(a,b,lambda) = cos^2(a-lambda) cos^2(b-lambda)

If that is not the case, then give me your joint probability for a given lambda.

First, the statement I was replying to was that local hidden
variables don't *exist*. I disagreed. They do exist, and
it can be demonstrated by looking at *individual* results.
Lambda is what's being analyzed in the individual context.

Regarding the *joint* probability, it doesn't depend
on a given lambda. That is, lambda isn't what's being
analyzed. What's being analyzed in the combined
context is a global constant. Lambda isn't the
global *constant*, so a description of joint
probability (such as what you evaluated) based on
lambda might give the correct functional form, but a
reduced spread (as you pointed out).

Ok, so, in the joint context, the polarizers, taken
together, are analyzing the degree to which photon_1
and photon_2 of any given pair are polarized identically.

So, if A records a photon detection, then the
probability of detection at B with the polarizers
aligned is 1 -- and the probability of detection
at B varies as cos^2 |a - b|. Isn't this
just standard quantum optics?

But where is the identical polarization produced?
As far as we *know* it *could* be produced at
the polarizers or detectors. But there's
an explanation that fits the observations,
and doesn't require the existence of undetectable
superluminal 'influences'.

Does quantum theory have an answer for the
question of where the identical polarization
is produced?

As far as I can tell, you could
interpret the projection as being due to local
or nonlocal transitions. That is, you *can*
assume that the identical polarization of
photon_1 and photon_2 is produced via the
emission process, and this assumption isn't
contradicted by the data. It also isn't, imo,
contradicted by Bell's analysis which deals
with the variable lambda. It also fits the
original idea of entanglement being due
to past interaction or common source.

Since interpretations of Bell's analysis
seem to be the only thing that superluminality
(wrt to associated experiments) has going
for it, it doesn't seem to me to be the
most reasonable option.

Regarding your statement that, using a wave
picture for light, a detector sitting behind
perpendicularly crossed linear polarizers has a >0
probability of registering a detection:
I don't think that's so. Anyway, I'm not
sure what that has to do with what we're
talking about -- which is, I thought, the
nature of entanglement in general, and in Bell/EPR
experiments in particular.
 
  • #88
Sherlock said:
Regarding the *joint* probability, it doesn't depend
on a given lambda. That is, lambda isn't what's being
analyzed. What's being analyzed in the combined
context is a global constant. Lambda isn't the
global *constant*, so a description of joint
probability (such as what you evaluated) based on
lambda might give the correct functional form, but a
reduced spread (as you pointed out).

But it isn't doing that ! It is doing that only in my second,
ad hoc, model.

Ok, so, in the joint context, the polarizers, taken
together, are analyzing the degree to which photon_1
and photon_2 of any given pair are polarized identically.

So, if A records a photon detection, then the
probability of detection at B with the polarizers
aligned is 1 -- and the probability of detection
at B varies as cos^2 |a - b|. Isn't this
just standard quantum optics?

No, not at all. That's standard optics IF IT IS THE SAME BEAM:

beam in ==> (pol 1) =(beam1)==> (pol2) ==> beam 2.

If pol1 and pol2 are aligned, of course beam 1 is reduced in intensity from beam in, but beam 2 is not reduced anymore, it is equal to beam1. And if pol1 and pol2 are perpendicular, beam2 equals 0. BUT THAT IS BECAUSE POL2 WORKS ON THE BEAM THAT GOT THROUGH POL1, which selected the component of beamin in the pol1 direction. If you then select AGAIN that component, of course everything gets through. It is as if you have a vector in the xy plane, and you project on the x-axis, and then you project the projection AGAIN on the x-axis. You work the second time with the projection.

But if you have:
beam2 <== (pol2) == (beamin) ====(pol1)==> beam1

then beam1 is simply the component of beamin in the pol1 direction, and beam2 is simply the component of beamin in the pol2 direction, and in classical optics these projections are done on the original beam. In the xy analogy, if pol1 and pol2 are resp. on the x and the y axis, beam1 gives you the x-component, and beam2 gives you the y component of the arbitrary vector coming from beamin. It is the special quantum context which makes that the measurement of the component x at pol1 makes that suddenly the beam at pol2 is projected out together in that x-direction (to take up the Copenhagen picture). But that's not what is done in classical optics.

In fact, in classical optics, there is no difference between this setup, and simply an incoming beam that is split on a (non-polarizing) beamsplitter, the transmitted beam arriving at pol1 and the reflected beam arriving at pol2.

That is, you *can*
assume that the identical polarization of
photon_1 and photon_2 is produced via the
emission process, and this assumption isn't
contradicted by the data. It also isn't, imo,
contradicted by Bell's analysis which deals
with the variable lambda. It also fits the
original idea of entanglement being due
to past interaction or common source.

Well, of course I assume that the two beams have identical polarization (lambda)!

Let us assume, for fun, that the source is polarized: it is sending out light always under 45 degrees, at both sides. Now assume that pol1 is set parallel to the x-axis, and pol2 is set parallel to the y axis. What do you think are the intensities at both sides in classical optics ?


Regarding your statement that, using a wave
picture for light, a detector sitting behind
perpendicularly crossed linear polarizers has a >0
probability of registering a detection:
I don't think that's so.

Eh, a detector behind CROSSED linear polarizers doesn't see any light, of course ! I never said that. I said that a detector behind ONE polarizer sees some light, and if ANOTHER BEAM (with identical polarization) falls upon ANOTHER POLARIZER (which is crossed to the first), it will ALSO SEE SOME LIGHT (in classical optics).

Anyway, I'm not
sure what that has to do with what we're
talking about -- which is, I thought, the
nature of entanglement in general, and in Bell/EPR
experiments in particular.

?

cheers,
Patrick.
 
Last edited:
  • #89
vanesch said:
But it isn't doing that ! It is doing
that only in my second, ad hoc, model.

I'm not sure what you're referring to here.
 
  • #90
vanesch said:
I would like to point out, again, that when people (sherlock) say that classical optics gives us the probability of joint detection equal to cos^2(a-b), then this is NOT true.

Actually, I wasn't arguing that -- but
rather just offering a perspective on why the
qm formulation works. A view of some possible
physical reasons for the correlations in optical Bell/EPR
experiments. These setups *do* have some
important features in common with the classical
setups that first produced the cos^2 theta formula.

The thing about photon detections is that there's
no way to tell whether all or some portion of the
light incident on a polarizer has been transmitted
by the polarizer when a detection occurs.

I suspect that you and I might have somewhat different
conceptions of what the word "photon" might refer to,
aside from it's existence as a theoretical entity and
a recorded detection.

Regarding anticoincidence experiments using
beamsplitters -- it's the same problem. There's
no way to tell if the light incident on a beamsplitter
and subsequently producing a photon detection at
one detector or the other (but never both)
was unevenly split or traveled only one path or
the other.

Do the uncertainty relations associated with these
types of experiments forbid ever knowing the
answers to these questions (given the current
fundamental quantum of action)?
 
  • #91
Sherlock said:
The thing about photon detections is that there's
no way to tell whether all or some portion of the
light incident on a polarizer has been transmitted
by the polarizer when a detection occurs.

I suspect that you and I might have somewhat different
conceptions of what the word "photon" might refer to,
aside from it's existence as a theoretical entity and
a recorded detection.

Well, there is of course one true concept of a photon, and that's the theory that defines it, namely QED. But if you insist on classical optics (which is Maxwell's equations), then a way to try to explain photo-electric clicking is by assuming that the EM wave amplitude is strongly pulsed: you don't have the intro textbook sine wave, but you have essentially most of the time, very low amplitudes and then you have sudden pulses (wave packets). When you look at the monochromaticity required (the delta lambda / lambda) and the time scale of detection (a few ns) versus the period of EM field oscillation (order fs), then there is all the room in the world to make these wave packets which are peaked in amplitude on the ns scale and appear still essentially monochromatic. Adding a semiclassical model of the source (where atoms radiate pulses of light during short time intervals) you have a natural setting for claiming that the EM wave is pulsed that way.
So *IF YOU INSIST ON THIS SEMICLASSICAL MODEL* (which, I recall, can explain quite a lot of optical phenomena), with individual light pulses which are EM wave trains according to Maxwell, then I don't see how you can arrive at any other prediction for the correlations than what I calculated, namely eps^2/8 (2 - cos 2(a-b) ).

Mind you that the workings of a beam splitter, a polarizing filter and a photodetector, in this semi-classical model do not have many liberties. Especially the beam splitter: if you ever hope to get interference using this pulsed light, a beam splitter has to send HALF of the EM energy (1/sqrt(2) of the E-field amplitude) very accurately to both sides. If it sends a whole pulse to the left, and then a whole pulse to the right, upon recombination, you wouldn't have any interference. Now, beamsplitters do give rise to interference. So that limits strongly how they can handle the classical EM wave.
In the same way, a photodetector can be checked against bolometric energy flux measurements: there is a very strict relation between the total number of counts during a certain time, and the total incident EM radiation. If you assume that the photodetector doesn't have any memory mechanism beyond the few ns scale then the probability of detection can only depend upon the incident EM energy (the flux of the Pointing vector). You can then also check its dependence, or not, of any polarization state.

Again, interference experiments with light getting through two polarizers show, in a similar way as done with a beam splitter, that classical EM wave pulses do not sometimes get through entirely, and sometimes don't get through, but that their intensities are lowered according to Malus's law, per pulse.

All this in the hypothesis of *classical EM radiation*.

You can think of many experiments that way, people have done them for more than a century, the classical behaviour of these components is completely constrained, and allows one to make precise predictions, based upon classical optics.

And for certain experiments, these predictions are in contradiction:
a) with QED predictions
b) with experimental results
but this only happens in the case of non-classical states of light (according to QED), such as 1-photon and 2-photon states in superposition (entangled photons).

Regarding anticoincidence experiments using
beamsplitters -- it's the same problem. There's
no way to tell if the light incident on a beamsplitter
and subsequently producing a photon detection at
one detector or the other (but never both)
was unevenly split or traveled only one path or
the other.

There is a way: interference of the resulting beams. If they interfere, they have to be present at the same time, and not one after the other.
You have to be able to do E1(t) + E2(t) at the screen. If at one time, you have a full E1 but no E2, and at another time, you have a full E2 but no E1, then you won't see interference.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #92
vanesch said:
Well, there is of course one true concept of a photon, and that's the theory that defines it, namely QED. But if you insist on classical optics (which is Maxwell's equations), then a way to try to explain photo-electric clicking is by assuming that the EM wave amplitude is strongly pulsed: you don't have the intro textbook sine wave, but you have essentially most of the time, very low amplitudes and then you have sudden pulses (wave packets). When you look at the monochromaticity required (the delta lambda / lambda) and the time scale of detection (a few ns) versus the period of EM field oscillation (order fs), then there is all the room in the world to make these wave packets which are peaked in amplitude on the ns scale and appear still essentially monochromatic. Adding a semiclassical model of the source (where atoms radiate pulses of light during short time intervals) you have a natural setting for claiming that the EM wave is pulsed that way.
So *IF YOU INSIST ON THIS SEMICLASSICAL MODEL* (which, I recall, can explain quite a lot of optical phenomena), with individual light pulses which are EM wave trains according to Maxwell, then I don't see how you can arrive at any other prediction for the correlations than what I calculated, namely eps^2/8 (2 - cos 2(a-b) ).

Mind you that the workings of a beam splitter, a polarizing filter and a photodetector, in this semi-classical model do not have many liberties. Especially the beam splitter: if you ever hope to get interference using this pulsed light, a beam splitter has to send HALF of the EM energy (1/sqrt(2) of the E-field amplitude) very accurately to both sides. If it sends a whole pulse to the left, and then a whole pulse to the right, upon recombination, you wouldn't have any interference. Now, beamsplitters do give rise to interference. So that limits strongly how they can handle the classical EM wave.
In the same way, a photodetector can be checked against bolometric energy flux measurements: there is a very strict relation between the total number of counts during a certain time, and the total incident EM radiation. If you assume that the photodetector doesn't have any memory mechanism beyond the few ns scale then the probability of detection can only depend upon the incident EM energy (the flux of the Pointing vector). You can then also check its dependence, or not, of any polarization state.

Again, interference experiments with light getting through two polarizers show, in a similar way as done with a beam splitter, that classical EM wave pulses do not sometimes get through entirely, and sometimes don't get through, but that their intensities are lowered according to Malus's law, per pulse.

All this in the hypothesis of *classical EM radiation*.

You can think of many experiments that way, people have done them for more than a century, the classical behaviour of these components is completely constrained, and allows one to make precise predictions, based upon classical optics.

And for certain experiments, these predictions are in contradiction:
a) with QED predictions
b) with experimental results
but this only happens in the case of non-classical states of light (according to QED), such as 1-photon and 2-photon states in superposition (entangled photons).

There is a way: interference of the resulting beams. If they interfere, they have to be present at the same time, and not one after the other.
You have to be able to do E1(t) + E2(t) at the screen. If at one time, you have a full E1 but no E2, and at another time, you have a full E2 but no E1, then you won't see interference.

So, my assessment of what entanglement *is* (offered many
messages ago) would seem to be incomplete. I can't argue with
the fact that the idea that it's due to common emission polarization
results in mathematical representations that are contradicted
by experiments. Yet, the common emission polarization would
seem to be a necessary condition for producing entangled results.

I suppose I should look at the details of the MWI stuff that you
seem to like. :) Thanks for the thoughtful comments from you and
DrChinese, et al.

There's a paperclip symbol by this thread -- what does that
mean? Also, what do the "warnings" mean? I couldn't find
an explanation of this in the faq.
 
  • #93
Sherlock said:
So, my assessment of what entanglement *is* (offered many
messages ago) would seem to be incomplete. I can't argue with
the fact that the idea that it's due to common emission polarization
results in mathematical representations that are contradicted
by experiments. Yet, the common emission polarization would
seem to be a necessary condition for producing entangled results.

Yes, entanglement is "more" than common emission polarization.

You can have, say, 4 different "polarization relations" between two photons.

One is: identical polarization, all the time the same. That's represented in QM by, say, |theta> |theta> (a pure product state), and classically by two beams with identical, fixed polarization theta.

The second is: identical polarization, but randomly distributed from event to event. That is represented in QM by a mixture: half |0>|0> and half |90>|90> (a density matrix). This is the "correlated polarization" situation. In classical EM, it is represented by two identical beams with polarization theta, but this time theta is drawn from a population.
THIS is the situation that can be described by the semiclassical model I talked about.

The third one is: uncorrelated polarizations. This is represented in QM by a statistical mixture:
1/4 |0>|0> ; 1/4 |0>|90> ; 1/4 |90>|0> and 1/4 |90>|90>.
Classically, we have uncorrelated beams with individual random polarizations.

The final one is entanglement ; a pure state |0>|0> + |90>|90>.
There is no classical equivalent here...
Of course it implies "identical polarization with random distribution" in a certain way, but it is a STRONGER form of correlation than with ONLY this link (which is perfectly well described by the mixture in our second case above).
It has in it, this "magical link at a distance". If you want to describe it "semiclassically" you have to introduce strange things, namely that upon observation of the polarization at one side in direction A+ (which could have been the result of a partial intensity of another polarisation getting through the polarizer), suddenly the polarization at the other side has to jump into exactly that direction ; at which point it can be analysed by another polarizer in another direction, and Malus' law applies then. But that's not how Maxwell tells us that EM waves behave ! They don't "jump" because at a distance, something was detected or not. Hence the puzzling aspects of entangled states when you want to force them into classical concepts.
Again, entanglement has no classical equivalence. It's a new state which exists only within the quantum framework.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
Last edited:
  • #94
I would like to point out a recent paper in the European Journal of Physics, especially for those who are still trying to grasp what is meant by "entanglement". This is especially true if you think it can be understood without bothering to look into the mathematics.

G.B. Roston et al., "Quantum entanglement, spin 1/2 and the Stern-Gerlach experiment", Eur. J. Phys. v.26, p.657 (2005).

You have no excuse if you say you don't have access to it. As I've pointed out many times on here and in my journals, this is one of IoP journals, and ALL articles appearing on IoP journals are available FREE (via registration) for the first 30 days that paper appears online.

Zz.
 
  • #95
ZapperZ said:
G.B. Roston et al., "Quantum entanglement, spin 1/2 and the Stern-Gerlach experiment", Eur. J. Phys. v.26, p.657 (2005).

You have no excuse if you say you don't have access to it. As I've pointed out many times on here and in my journals, this is one of IoP journals, and ALL articles appearing on IoP journals are available FREE (via registration) for the first 30 days that paper appears online.

Zz.

Here is the link to the page that takes you there (just to make it even easier):

http://www.iop.org/EJ/ejs_extra - Select "This Month's Papers"

The article was put out around May 22 +/- so should be there through much of June. This site is nice, you may want to bookmark this page.
 
  • #96
vanesch said:
... entanglement has no classical equivalence. It's a new state which exists only within the quantum framework.

I feel somewhat confident in saying that an eventual qualitative understanding of quantum entanglement will be in terms of concepts developed via our ordinary sensory perception of things (ie., a wave mechanical picture) -- nothing *essentially* new or exotic, but
perhaps a lot more complicated than what's been developed so
far (eg., via quantum or classical or semiclassical descriptions).

The basic idea is that entanglement has to do with
analyzing common physical properties. There are a number
of ways that this can be produced in a universe with a
signal transmission speed limit of c. I don't think that's
been contradicted. The experimental results contradict
some simplistic ways of describing this mathematically,
that's all. If you've got a better idea wrt the essence of
entanglement, then let's hear it. :)

Now I'm going to read the Roston et al. paper referenced by
Zapperz and see if it has anything new in it.
 
  • #97
Sherlock said:
The basic idea is that entanglement has to do with
analyzing common physical properties. There are a number
of ways that this can be produced in a universe with a
signal transmission speed limit of c. I don't think that's
been contradicted. The experimental results contradict
some simplistic ways of describing this mathematically,
that's all. If you've got a better idea wrt the essence of
entanglement, then let's hear it. :)

You have it backwards, as I see it. The experimental results rule out local reality. If you have a local hidden variable solution - either simplistic OR complicated - that matches experiment, let's hear it. :)

Instead of trying to restore local reality, we should try to understand local non-reality. Or non-local reality. Or non-local non-reality. :rofl:
 
  • #98
DrChinese said:
You have it backwards, as I see it. The experimental results rule out local reality.

That's an unwarranted conclusion. The experimental results
rule out quantitative descriptions of a certain form. As yet,
nobody's quite sure what that means as far as nature is
concerned.

DrChinese said:
If you have a local hidden variable solution - either simplistic OR complicated - that matches experiment, let's hear it. :)

I did provide, some messages back, a sort of semi-classical
approach in terms of local interactions and common source
which even vanesch allowed was ok for the usual EPR-Bell type
setups of an emitter, two polarizers and two detectors, but can't
as yet be extended to eg. beamsplitter setups.
The problem is that details of the physical characteristics of the
emitted light are lacking.

DrChinese said:
Instead of trying to restore local reality, we should try to
understand local non-reality. Or non-local reality. Or non-local
non-reality. :rofl:

Local reality is still with us afaik. :) The question is whether we
need to posit superluminal signals to account for experimental
results. Some people don't think so. Some people do think so.
So, these are just two different ways to approach the
problem of explaining the correlations -- which remain
unexplained so far.
 
  • #99
Sherlock said:
I did provide, some messages back, a sort of semi-classical
approach in terms of local interactions and common source
which even vanesch allowed was ok for the usual EPR-Bell type
setups of an emitter, two polarizers and two detectors, but can't
as yet be extended to eg. beamsplitter setups.
The problem is that details of the physical characteristics of the
emitted light are lacking.

I first thought that indeed a semiclassical approach allowed for the reconstruction of Malus' law because that was repeated so many times here. But then I did a calculation and according to me, this semiclassical model gives you eps^2 /8 (2 - cos(2(a-b))) as a correlation function, which is NOT the prediction of QM, nor can explain the experimental results, especially in the case of perpendicular polarizers.

So could you specify again your semiclassical model ? Give us, for each "measurement interval" (a few nanoseconds):

a) what common parameters does the light have on both sides (classical polarization ; maybe also something else) which went with it thanks to a common creation ; and how these parameters are statistically distributed over the entire sample.
b) how, from these parameters, the individual detection probabilities at Alice and Bob are given if their angles of polarizers are a and b respectively
c) how you calculate from this the joint probability of detection assuming statistical independence of the probabilities cited in b).

Local reality is still with us afaik. :) The question is whether we
need to posit superluminal signals to account for experimental
results.

?

Locality implies of course the absense of superluminal signals by definition! Well, unless you are willing to sacrifice causality or special relativity...

cheers,
Patrick.
 
  • #100
Sherlock said:
That's an unwarranted conclusion. The experimental results rule out quantitative descriptions of a certain form. As yet,
nobody's quite sure what that means as far as nature is
concerned.

The form that is ruled out is the one in which the photon polarization has definite values for any other angles other than the ones actually observed. If you do not choose to call that the local realistic position, that is your choice. However, that is definitely what EPR envisioned and this is what everyone else calls it.

Sherlock said:
I did provide, some messages back, a sort of semi-classical
approach in terms of local interactions and common source
which even vanesch allowed was ok for the usual EPR-Bell type
setups of an emitter, two polarizers and two detectors, but can't
as yet be extended to eg. beamsplitter setups.
The problem is that details of the physical characteristics of the
emitted light are lacking.

I don't think Vanesch said that you advanced a local realistic position he agreed with. (Of course, he can speak for himself on the matter - edit: he does in the post above.)

However, the quantum mechanical description is as physical as any theory. How about F=ma? Is that a physical description? Why would that make more sense than the HUP, for example? Just because QM uses a different mathematical language doesn't make it less of a description.

Sherlock said:
Local reality is still with us afaik. :) The question is whether we need to posit superluminal signals to account for experimental
results. Some people don't think so. Some people do think so.
So, these are just two different ways to approach the
problem of explaining the correlations -- which remain
unexplained so far.

Local reality is generally ruled out (unless you think of MWI as local reality). I agree with your question, though. Which is: are superluminal effects present?
 
  • #101
vanesch said:
I first thought that indeed a semiclassical approach allowed for the reconstruction of Malus' law because that was repeated so many times here. But then I did a calculation and according to me, this semiclassical model gives you eps^2 /8 (2 - cos(2(a-b))) as a correlation function, which is NOT the prediction of QM, nor can explain the experimental results, especially in the case of perpendicular polarizers.

So could you specify again your semiclassical model ? Give us, for each "measurement interval" (a few nanoseconds):

a) what common parameters does the light have on both sides (classical polarization ; maybe also something else) which went with it thanks to a common creation ; and how these parameters are statistically distributed over the entire sample.
b) how, from these parameters, the individual detection probabilities at Alice and Bob are given if their angles of polarizers are a and b respectively
c) how you calculate from this the joint probability of detection assuming statistical independence of the probabilities cited in b).

Locality implies of course the absense of superluminal signals by definition! Well, unless you are willing to sacrifice causality or special relativity...

cheers,
Patrick.

The equation that you set up as a semi-classical model doesn't
describe the approach that I outlined. And it was *just* an
outline. :) I, presently, have no idea how to continue, to
'flesh it out', so to speak. And anyway I don't have time.

In saying that "local reality is still with us, afaik" ... I meant just
that. :) Since I don't think there's any need to posit the
existence of superluminal signals, as far as I'm concerned,
and certainly as far as anyone *knows*, they don't exist.
 
  • #102
DrChinese said:
The form that is ruled out is the one in which the photon polarization has definite values for any other angles other than the ones actually observed. If you do not choose to call that the local realistic position, that is your choice. However, that is definitely what EPR envisioned and this is what everyone else calls it.

I don't think Vanesch said that you advanced a local realistic position he agreed with. (Of course, he can speak for himself on the matter - edit: he does in the post above.)

However, the quantum mechanical description is as physical as any theory. How about F=ma? Is that a physical description? Why would that make more sense than the HUP, for example? Just because QM uses a different mathematical language doesn't make it less of a description.

Local reality is generally ruled out (unless you think of MWI as local reality). I agree with your question, though. Which is: are superluminal effects present?

We're talking about the essence of entanglement.
Here's what Schroedinger had to say about it:

"If two separated bodies, each by itself known maximally,
enter a situation in which they influence each other,
and separate again, then there occurs regularly that
which I have called entanglement of our knowledge of
the two bodies."

Iow, the subsequent motion of the disturbances as they move
away from a point of interaction (or a common emission source)
contains a property or properties imparted to each as a result of
the interaction (or common origin). These shared properties are what 'entangle' subsequent instrumental records of the
disturbances, as long as it is the shared properties that are
being analysed. (So, you can let the entangled disturbances
move as far away from each other as you want, and as
long as the shared properties are undisturbed, then they'll
remain entangled.)

Now, doesn't this make more sense that positing the existence
of superluminal signals to account for the correlations.
(The lower bound on such signals increases as the entangled
disturbances move away from each other. At some scale of
separation, say opposite ends of the universe, the transmission
would have to be virtually instantaneous. Not a likely
scenario, imo.)

The formal treatment of entanglement by QM is the
embodiment of Schroedinger's original idea, afaik -- and
not some notion of superluminality. The problem is
simply that it can't be qualitatively descriptive enough
(wrt the *details* of the shared physical property or
properties) to dismiss the *possibility* that the entangled
instrumental results are due to superluminal signalling.
(But, as Einstein might say, it's a silly idea anyway :) )

So the program, as I see it, is to get creative and
develop some more descriptive local models that agree
with the experimental results.
 
  • #103
Sherlock said:
The formal treatment of entanglement by QM is the
embodiment of Schroedinger's original idea, afaik -- and
not some notion of superluminality. The problem is
simply that it can't be qualitatively descriptive enough
(wrt the *details* of the shared physical property or
properties) to dismiss the *possibility* that the entangled
instrumental results are due to superluminal signalling.
(But, as Einstein might say, it's a silly idea anyway :) )

So the program, as I see it, is to get creative and
develop some more descriptive local models that agree
with the experimental results.

You are covering a lot of ground in one post... :smile:

1. Schroedinger's quote is not at all the same as the formal treatment by QM, and I don't see why you would think it is. They do NOT share any physical properties until they are observed and this is the essence of any quantum particle's state - which is always limited by the HUP. Certainty about one quantum property (as a result of an observation) creates uncertainty in another.

2. As to the superluminal signal idea... I don't accept that particularly either (maybe it is the case, I don't know) and yet I reject local reality. Bell's Theorem addresses the notion of simultaneous reality of non-commuting observables, and concludes this is incompatible with experiment. It does not REQUIRE superluminal transmission of anything.

3. As already indicated, no local realistic model can agree with experimental results.
 
  • #104
DrChinese said:
... They do NOT share any physical properties until they are observed ...

If by "they" you mean the opposite-moving disturbances ...
well, nobody knows what they share or don't share. But,
the assumption is that they do share some physical property
or properties. That's what entanglement is all about.
Great care is taken to produce the shared properties
experimentally.

Keep in mind that QM is about the measurement results, not
the opposite-moving disturbances.

DrChinese said:
... As to the superluminal signal idea... I don't accept that particularly either (maybe it is the case, I don't know) and yet I reject local reality.

This seems like a rather confusing way to talk about it. :)
 
  • #105
Sherlock said:
Iow, the subsequent motion of the disturbances as they move
away from a point of interaction (or a common emission source)
contains a property or properties imparted to each as a result of
the interaction (or common origin). These shared properties are what 'entangle' subsequent instrumental records of the
disturbances, as long as it is the shared properties that are
being analysed. (So, you can let the entangled disturbances
move as far away from each other as you want, and as
long as the shared properties are undisturbed, then they'll
remain entangled.)

I wonder (really no offense intended) if you understood the implications of Bell's theorem, then. Indeed, the above situation is EXACTLY what Einstein thought was "really" happening, and about which Bell wrote his famous theorem. The "shared properties" are simply the "hidden variables". Well, it turns out - that's the entire content of Bell's theorem - that of course these shared properties can give rise to correlations in the observation (that's no surprise), but that correlations obtained that way SATISFY CERTAIN NON-TRIVIAL INEQUALITIES. Guess what ? Quantum theory's predictions violate those inequalities (and seem to be confirmed by experiment - under some *very* reasonable extra assumptions).

The hypothesis Bell started with was the following: correlations between probabilitic events can only have two different causes ; otherwise their randomness is independent. These two causes are: a) direct causal influence (meaning: what happens at A has a direct influence of what happens at B), or b) common origin of causes.
This is in fact a universally accepted idea (which turns out to be false in quantum theory), and most "common sense" judgements take it implicitly for granted. In fact, many people forget about the B option, which leads to a lot of nonsense (especially in politically colored studies), but Bell didn't of course.

Let us consider the following study: carefull investigation has led us to find out a remarkable correlation:there is a correlation between "driving a Jaguar" and "having a Rolex", which means that if P_j is the probability for someone to drive a Jaguar (quite low) and P_r is the probability for someone to have a Rolex (also quite low) and P_rj is the probability for someone to drive a jaguar and to have a rolex, then P_rj is bigger than P_r x P_j (which would be the case if there was no correlation).
You can make the case for the following: this proves that there must be a causal influence! And you find this unfair competition in the watch makers market, because you think that this is proof that the salesman who sells you a Jaguar gives you a Rolex with it for free, which would explain the correlation (there's a causal influence).
However, after your complaint, careful investigation of the records of all Jaguar dealers by the financial police brigade show that no such deals were made.
The other way around then ? People who buy a Rolex also get a Jaguar for free ? Mmmm... probably not, either. A mystery correlation then ?
No of course not. The answer is of course B: the common cause: if you're rich, there's more chance that you drive a Jaguar AND buy a Rolex !

So Bell set out to consider what happens if, for one reason or another, A (direct causal influence) is excluded, what happens with correlations by common cause, which you seem to think that explains entanglement. So his hypothesis was that a joint probability P(A,B) can only deviate from P(A) x P(B) if there is a common cause, which he called a "hidden variable" (in our case, it is the bank account of the people having jaguars and rolex watches). But for THE SAME VALUE of the hidden variable (same amount of money $$ on the bank account), you could expect that P_jr($$) = P_j($$) x P_r($$). Maybe it isn't. But then there is maybe yet another hidden variable, say "taste for luxury items T" etc...
So the idea of Bell was: lump ALL of the common causes, specified by values of hidden variables together in a set of parameters L ; if we have all common causes taken into L, then (even if we cannot know L) then
P(A,B ; L) = P(A ; L) x P(B ; L) (B1)

All statistical analysis in, say, medicine and human sciences takes this for granted.

Then, Bell said: over the entire population over which we will do our experiments, L will be distributed according to an (unknown) probability distribution p(L).

Of course, from B1 then follows that the measured joint probability over that population is then given by:

P(A,B) = integral P(A,B ; L) dp(L) = integral P(A;L) P(B;L) dp(L)
and:
P(A) = integral P(A ; L) dp(L)
P(B) = integral P(B ; L) dp(L)

I call these the equations B2.

We can extend them by considering ALL KINDS of correlations:
P(A, not B) = integral P(A ; L) {1 - P(B;L)} dp(L) etc...

As such, for TWO properties (A and B), they put some constraints on the values of P(A,B), P(A) and P(B), the 4 possibilities:
P(A,B) = a
P(A, not B) = b
P(not A, B) = c
P(not A, not B) = 1 - a - b - c
with a,b,c arbitrary numbers between 0 and 1, such that a+b+c <= 1
We have that P(A) = a + b and P(B) = 1 - a - c, which leads us to:

P(A) = P(A,B) + b and P(B) = 1 - P(A,B) - c with b + c <= 1 - P(A,B).

Call this the set of equations B3. For 2 properties A and B, this has nothing spectacular. But if you use that same reasoning for 3 properties A, B and C, you get more stringent conditions on P(A,B), P(A,C) ... ; which are however not very surprising for a statistician.

But now comes the point: if you calculate P(A,B), P(A,C) and P(B,C) from QM for certain properties A, B and C of an entangled state, then you do NOT satify these conditions ! This means that these probabilities cannot be described by something that has a "common cause" (hidden or not) as set out from the beginning. It even means that there is no LOGICAL POSSIBILITY for the properties A, B and C to be associated simultaneously to individual events, because the probabilities then simply don't add up to 1, each being between 0 and 1 !

The only way out is that you cannot measure A, B and C simultaneously. Horray ! That's the case in QM. But that means that you have to CHANGE YOUR MEASUREMENT SETUP to decide whether you measure A,B or A,C or B,C. And THEN there is a possibility: namely that this change in measurement setup CHANGES THE POPULATION p(L), so that when you are calculating P(A,B), you use ANOTHER p(L) than when you are calculating P(A,C). But that needs faster-than-light communication, because it means that, upon EMISSION, the pair will have to know what you are going to measure, to know from what population p(L) it has to be drawn: that can only happen through direct causal influence from the choice of the measurement to the population p(L).

So there is no way out: or there is a common cause L, with distribution p(L) (which is then of course the same, no matter what we are going to measure) and then we satisfy these equations, or there is not such a common cause, in which case there has to be a direct influence of the choice of the measurement on p(L) (or we abandon entirely the model that some L is at the origin of the outcomes). Given QM predictions and experimental results, clearly we are in the second case if we assign a reality to the measurements at spacelike separations.

My explanation (MWI) simply says that the measurement at Bob didn't take place, and only has a meaning when Alice learns about it ; at which point a direct causal influence can be kept local.

cheers,
Patrick.
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
775
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
737
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
1K
Replies
50
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
26
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
969
Replies
1
Views
827
Replies
19
Views
961
Replies
41
Views
2K
Back
Top