Hi !
Of course, it all depends on how you "introduce" quantum mechanics, and what I wanted to point out is that many introductions of quantum theory seem to hide the essential idea of quantum superposition (and its inherent strangeness) by doing things like talking about waves. They're in good company, as many of the historical founders of quantum mechanics did the same. But my personal opinion is that this is just delaying the surprise, and you can't hide it anymore with entanglement - although entanglement is nothing else but a specific application of quantum superposition. In fact Einstein SAW this immediately and used entanglement to *illustrate* the (for him unacceptable) weirdness of quantum superposition in general.
Usually, when you are first exposed to quantum mechanics, you've had courses in classical mechanics, and in electromagnetism. So you know about fields, and you know about particles. And quantum mechanics is often introduced by "associating" a wave to a particle. As for linear wave dynamics, the superposition principle is true, the superposition principle for the "wave equation" in quantum mechanics is not so very surprising. It looks like the linearity of the Maxwell equations. And then you are drawn into the technicalities of the calculations, and you end up doing quantum mechanics, solving the hydrogen atom and so on, while thinking in "classical waves". And at the end of the calculation, you take the Born rule, and produce probabilities. And you feel at ease. More or less. Yes, there is the funny two-slit experiment, but it is "interference", like in optics.
I like Feynman's lectures (3rd volume) a lot, because Feynman explicitly does NOT go that route and confronts people immediately with the fundamental weirdness of QM.
The superposition principle does NOT say that you associate a wave to a particle. The superposition principle says this, and it is profoundly shocking:
if a system can be in a state A, where certain observables take on specific values ;
and that system can also be in a state B, where certan observables take on other specific values
then that system can be considered to be in ANY state c1 |A> + c2 |B>, with c1 and c2 complex weights.
Note that it DOES NOT MEAN that those observables now take on the value c1 a + c2 b or something, no. It means that the system "takes on SIMULTANEOUSLY the values a and b with complex weights", but if you measure them, you get a, or you get b, with probabilities given by |c1|^2 resp |c2|^2.
This by itself would give you a statistical ensemble where the phase of c1 and c2 doesn't matter, but things go further:
certain superpositions yield precise values for (other) observables, which can only have those precise values when we have those superpositions.
And the "ensemble" is dead, we have genuine quantum weirdness.
The big difference between this quantum superposition and "field superposition" is that the *values* of the observables are not simply c1 a + c2 b.
Take an electron. State A is: the electron is on my desk. State B is: the electron is in the dustbin.
The state c1 A + c2 B is NOT: the electron is somewhere in between my desk and the dustbin. No. It means that the electron is "with amplitude c1" on my desk, and "with amplitude c2" in the dustbin. But maybe it has now a well-defined energy which it didn't have in the state "is on my desk" or "is in the dustbin".
That's terribly weird. The electron is SIMULTANEOUSLY and with complex weights "on my desk" and "in the dustbin". If I try TO FIND OUT where the electron is, I will never find the answer "somewhere mixed on my desk and in the dustbin". No, I will get a straight answer: "on my desk" or "in the dustbin". With each a certain probability. But if I don't find out, it is in two places at once.
Now, for a single particle, a general state corresponds to a complex number for each of the potential position states it can be in, which corresponds to a complex number for each point in space, and we think that is a "field". We forget that it is a superposition of individual position states. The calculations are as if it are fields, as long as we have one single particle.
You are only hit again by the strangeness of superposition when you consider 2-particle states. They are not "two fields". They are superpositions of all possible position COUPLES, because a priori, the description of a single state of two particles consists of a pair of positions: particle 1 is here, and particle 2 is there.
Possible states of an apple and an orange:
state 1: apple is on my desk, orange is in the dustbin
state 2: apple and orange are on my desk
state 3: apple is in the dustbin, orange is on my desk
state 4: apple and orange are in the dustbin
Applying the superposition principle, we have that our apple and our orange can be in a state given by 4 complex numbers, c1, c2, c3, c4:
c1 | apple is on my desk and orange is in the dustbin> + c2 |state2> + c3 |state 3> + c4 |state 4>
Now, it can be that the system has only a well-defined energy, say, in the states:
|state1> + |state3>
|state1> - |state3>
|state2> + |state4>
|state2> - |state4>
these are entangled states. There's nothing particular here: we simply applied the superposition principle, as we did also for single-particle states: we listed all "observable" states with a well-defined value for a certain set of observables (positions of apple and orange), and then we applied the superposition principle to find ALL allowed states of this system.
ThomasT said:
But "normal" superposition isn't weird. Is it? It seems readily, easily 'grasped'. That is, if the amplitude of wave A produces X and the amplitude of wave B produces Y, then the combined amplitudes, A + B, produce X + Y.
Yes, for a real field.
Ok, you lost me here. Please elaborate.
The essential point in the two-slit experiment is that the number of electrons arriving at a certain point on the screen is NOT the sum of the number of electrons that went through slit A and arrived at that point PLUS the number of electrons that went through slit B and arrived at that same point, but on the other hand that if you go and measure right behind the slits, each electron arrives OR at slit 1 OR at slit 2.
So this means that there is a (superposition) state "goes through slit 1 and goes through slit 2" which is not the same as "goes through slit 1 OR goes through slit 2 with probabilities 50% 50%", because then we would have simply 2 populations of electrons, and the number of electrons on a point on the screen would be the number of electrons on that point from population 1 plus the number of points on the screen from population 2, which it isn't.
In other words, the two-slit experiment proves that the quantum state |slit 1> + |slit 2> genuinely exists, and is NOT simply an ensemble of electrons "slit 1" and electrons "slit 2".
The point is that with the two-slit experiment, because it is a one-particle system, you can still get away with it thinking you have actually "waves".
Not sure what you're saying. The thing is, I believe in the wave nature (as well as the particle nature) of ... reality. Quanta, including electrons and photons, ARE waves. And I would venture that their wave nature is better understood than their particle nature. Doesn't everything you know about physics point to a fundamental wave reality?
The point is that if you associate a single wave to each particle, you STILL do not get agreement with quantum mechanics, because of 2-particle states. And then you only see the difference with "entangled states". Entangled states simply illustrate, on the 2 or more particle level, that the TRICK of getting away with superposition on the 1-particle level, namely associating waves with particles, was of limited utility, and that you hit the same difficulty now again.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Le_Bourgeois_gentilhomme
His philosophy lesson becomes a basic lesson on language in which he is surprised and delighted to learn that he has been speaking "prose" all his life without knowing it