Understanding Ehrenfest Theorem & Its Implications in QM

  • Thread starter Thread starter McLaren Rulez
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Theorem
McLaren Rulez
Messages
289
Reaction score
3
Hi,

In the Wikipedia derivation of this theorem, there is a step which I do not follow. This uses the Heisenberg picture to get Ehrenfest's theorem. A is an operator at t=0 and A(t) is the evolved operator.

\frac{d}{dt}A(t) = \frac{i}{\hbar}e^{iHt/\hbar}(HA-AH)e^{-iHt/\hbar} +e^{iHt/\hbar}(\frac{\partial A}{\partial t})e^{-iHt/\hbar} = \frac{i}{\hbar}(HA-AH)+\frac{\partial A}{\partial t}

The last step is said to be true because e^{iHt/\hbar} commutes with H. But I don't see how that leads to the equality. Can someone explain?

Secondly, when the Ehrenfest theorem is applied, we get classical laws. For instance, Newton's second law with the original classical variables replaced by expectation values of the quantum operator i.e. x becomes <x> and so on. But in general, is it true that any classical law can be written in terms of QM through Ehrenfest's theorem (provided we can define the relevant operators)? Is Ehrenfest's theorem the thing that actually connects QM with classical mechanics?

Thank you!
 
Physics news on Phys.org
In the last equality the first two "A"s should be written as "A(t)"s... Because they are
e^{iHt}Ae^{-iHt}, since you can pass the e^{iHt} past H.
 
olgranpappy, thank you. That is something I overlooked.

Regarding the second part of my question, does anyone have any answers? Thank you
 
McLaren Rulez said:
Secondly, when the Ehrenfest theorem is applied, we get classical laws. For instance, Newton's second law with the original classical variables replaced by expectation values of the quantum operator i.e. x becomes <x> and so on. But in general, is it true that any classical law can be written in terms of QM through Ehrenfest's theorem (provided we can define the relevant operators)? Is Ehrenfest's theorem the thing that actually connects QM with classical mechanics?
I would say yes. Classically, observables are functions on the phase space. The time evolution of these functions can be described by the poisson bracket of the function and the Hamiltonian of the system. This corresponds to the Ehrenfest theorem.

In the Heisenberg picture, this relation is even more explicit. The Heisenberg equation applies not only to expectation values, but to the now time-dependent observables themself.
 
Last edited:
Thank you kith. I didn't realize how important the Ehrenfest theorem was until now. I wonder why it is hardly emphasized in textbooks like Griffiths which only brings it up in some exercises here and there when it is so fundamental in connecting QM to CM.
 
Thank you dextercioby, but that paper appears to be slightly too technical for me. I would like to clarify another two questions if I may.

1) Would it be correct if I said that a quantum state \psi is an analog of a classical state of a particle if and only if, for every operator O, the expectation value <\psi|O|\psi> is the same as the classical measurment that corresponds to that observable O on that particle? For example, if I choose the position operator, x, then \psi is an analog of a classical state of a particle only if <\psi|x|\psi> is the same as the measurement of the position of that classical state. Is this true?

2) I think (do correct me if I am wrong) that Ehrenfest's theorem is often useful in proving the above statement by considering an arbitrary wavefunction to compute the expectation value and thus deriving a classical law from QM. For instance, we consider an arbitrary wavefunction in the relation \frac{d}{dt}<\psi|x|\psi> and after applying Ehrenfest's theorem, we find that this is equal to \frac{1}{m}<\psi|p|\psi>. Since this is true for any wavefunction, we must have the classical equation \frac{d}{dt}x=p/m. Is the above analysis correct?

As always, thank you so much for reading through and helping me out!
 
You pretty much got the right idea. Indeed, on a superficial level quantum mechanics is not too different from its classical counterpart. The Heisenberg equation of motion strongly resembles the Hamilton equations. Of course, the meaning and the conclusions one reaches are fundamentally different, because one theory is a generalization of the other.
 
the problem with Ehrenfest theorem is that it is limited, it cannot explain the classical bohr atom (as this has been discussed in another thread). and cannot generalize QFT to classical. although I do think it has very badly been over looked as for the connection between CM and QM. And that is basically because of the accepted wave-PARTICLE(!) daulity.
 
  • #10
qsa said:
the problem with Ehrenfest theorem is that it is limited, it cannot explain the classical bohr atom (as this has been discussed in another thread). and cannot generalize QFT to classical. although I do think it has very badly been over looked as for the connection between CM and QM. And that is basically because of the accepted wave-PARTICLE(!) daulity.

wat?
 
  • #12
qsa said:
https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=518300

any specific question is welcome.something like what do you mean by ...

Oh, sorry, I confused myself with Nernst Theorem that was propagated by Paul Ehrenfest. As far as I know, Ehrenfest's Theorem is a claim that expectation values of operators satisfy equations of classical mechanics.
 
  • #13
McLaren Rulez said:
1) Would it be correct if I said that a quantum state \psi is an analog of a classical state of a particle if and only if, for every operator O, the expectation value <\psi|O|\psi> is the same as the classical measurment that corresponds to that observable O on that particle? For example, if I choose the position operator, x, then \psi is an analog of a classical state of a particle only if <\psi|x|\psi> is the same as the measurement of the position of that classical state. Is this true?
I don't think so. Consider a free particle. Position and Momentum are related by the Fourier transform. The expectation values don't change if we change the width of the position distribution. So very delocalized and therefore very "quantum mechanical" states may have the same expectation values like more "classical" states with small uncertainties in both momentum and position.

Btw: In classical mechanics, a measurement simply reads out the value of a observable (which is a function on the phase space). So unlike in QM, there is no need to talk about classical measurements, but only about the observables themselves.
 
  • #14
qsa said:
the problem with Ehrenfest theorem is that it is limited, it cannot explain the classical bohr atom
Classical accelerated point charges radiate, so the Bohr model is not classical.

qsa said:
and cannot generalize QFT to classical.
QFT cannot be "generalized" to a classical field theory, since it is the more fundamental theory. And like in non-relativistic QM, the classical equations (Maxwell's) correspond to Heisenberg equations (for the field operators E and B). So there should be no problem in applying Ehrenfest's theorem here.
 
  • #15
kith said:
I don't think so. Consider a free particle. Position and Momentum are related by the Fourier transform. The expectation values don't change if we change the width of the position distribution. So very delocalized and therefore very "quantum mechanical" states may have the same expectation values like more "classical" states with small uncertainties in both momentum and position.

So what that means is that there is more than one quantum state that corresponds to the classical state. But we only considered the position and momentum operators acting on the state. Isn't it possible that for other operators, say energy, the expectation values for various states differ and only one of those states will give us the same result as the classical energy?
 
  • #16
McLaren Rulez said:
So what that means is that there is more than one quantum state that corresponds to the classical state.
I think this wording is misleading. There is no classical analogon of delocalized states for example, so I would not say that such a state "corresponds" to a classical state just because its expectation value may be the same as for the state of a localized particle.

Or consider a position distribution which is zero at the expectation value <X> and has two widely separated peaks. In measurements, you will never find this particle near <X>. So this state does not at all correspond to a classical state (x, p) in phase space with the classical observables x = <X> and p = <P>.

[Maybe you are being confused by the fact that classically, the position and momentum observables are represented by the trivial functions f(x,p)=x and f(x,p)=p.]
 
Last edited:
  • #17
I see your point. Okay, so not every quantum state has a classical analog. But the reverse must be true right? Every classical state must have a quantum analog since QM is a more general theory than CM. And this quantum analog must have expectation values that agree with the classical measurement. Is this statement correct?
 
  • #18
kith said:
Classical accelerated point charges radiate, so the Bohr model is not classical.

I hate to bicker about words. but here is a wiki bohr model


"
To overcome this difficulty, Niels Bohr proposed, in 1913, what is now called the Bohr model of the atom. He suggested that electrons could only have certain classical motions:". certainly electron going around the proton is not a quantum picture.anyway, what ever you call it it cannot produce it.





kith said:
QFT cannot be "generalized" to a classical field theory, since it is the more fundamental theory. And like in non-relativistic QM, the classical equations (Maxwell's) correspond to Heisenberg equations (for the field operators E and B). So there should be no problem in applying Ehrenfest's theorem here.

maybe the wording caused some confusion, but I meant that the theorm has no role to play like explaining the 1/r law for instance. I am not aware that Ehrenfest's theorem can make the qm maxwell connection, any reference is appreciated.
 
Last edited:
  • #19
McLaren Rulez said:
I see your point. Okay, so not every quantum state has a classical analog. But the reverse must be true right? Every classical state must have a quantum analog since QM is a more general theory than CM.
Yes. But it is not a one to one correspondence. Any quantum mechanical state with sufficiently small uncertainties (and of course the right expectation values) will do.
qsa said:
To overcome this difficulty, Niels Bohr proposed, in 1913, what is now called the Bohr model of the atom. He suggested that electrons could only have certain classical motions:". certainly electron going arount the proron is not a quantum picture.anyway, what ever you call it it cannot produce it.
Let me put it another way: The Ehrenfest theorem is a statement about how classical equations of motion emerge from quantum mechanics. What are the classical equations of motion of the Bohr model?
 
  • #20
kith said:
Yes. But it is not a one to one correspondence. Any quantum mechanical state with sufficiently small uncertainties (and of course the right expectation values) will do.

Let me put it another way: The Ehrenfest theorem is a statement about how classical equations of motion emerge from quantum mechanics. What are the classical equations of motion of the Bohr model?

the point is that it is not clear how to go from the shrodinger equation describing hydrogen atom to the bohr model. if you have some idea I will be happy to hear it.
 
Back
Top