my_wan said:
Certainly in some cases we know we are working with a "useful fantasy", but to say that because we are fundamentally limited in our capacity to "know" entails that all such characterizations are factually "useful fantasies" tacitly oversteps what we can factually know, such a claim is a mind projection fallacy.
How can you tell in which cases we are working with a "useful fantasy" about the reality and which cases we are working with the actual reality? To even make this language internally inconsistent, we must accept that even fantasies have a sliding scale of connection to reality, which is just what I mean by "usefulness", but never cross a line into being something fundamentally different from a fantasy-- all that demonstrably changes is the usefulness of the fantasy. Yes, in standard language, we don't call something a fantasy any more if it has demonstrable usefulness, but this is sheer convenience-- we do not need to lose sight of the fact that the same basic process occurs with a useful fantasy and a pure fantasy, they are both mental pictures we adopt to achieve some purpose. All that changes is the purpose, and the standard of usefulness that is applied. My use of the term "fantasy" is not designed to suggest that science is pure fantasy, it is designed to place scientific thinking into its demonstrably proper place: inside our head, where it quite clearly does indeed occur.
To some realist your opinion as stated does not even constitute realism.
Indeed, and this is the central point. I'm not trying to divert this thread into a discussion of my personal philosophical opinions, this issue is right at the heart of just exactly what it is that PBR has proved about valid
interpretations of quantum mechanics. PBR have adopted a very narrow view of what realism is, too narrow to be able to claim that they are using "only mild assumptions." Their version of realism is indeed often adopted by scientists, but I claim that it is internally inconsistent with science.
Now, I will admit that it is typical for scientists to adopt a view of scientific ontology that is perfectly convenient but rather naive, and is not really consistent with either the historical trajectory of science, nor to what scientists actually do. In particular, nothing in the history of physics, nor in the actions of any physicist, actually require any such thing as a concept of a true physical ontology (including the concept of "properties" that drive the logic of the PBR argument). In history, and in practice, all physical ontologies are borrowed from mathematics, and have no formal status within physics itself. They are contextual, provisional, and goal-oriented, a fact that is perfectly demonstrable by considering any standard physics curriculum. Thus, there is no basis for claiming that "realism" involves regarding physics as something that it has never been and likely never will be. None of this has anything to do with my personal philosophical choices, it is all just demonstrable truths about what physics is, not what we might like it to be. So I am arguing that the "realism" that PBR regards as a "mild assumption" in their proof is not only highly unrealistic, it is an example of the mind projection fallacy. Or should I say, the mind projection fantasy!
In other words it makes no sense to define the world in which we directly interact "the physical world" while also denying that the actual constituents from which the world is derived are not physical. Like denying atoms are not real, but hurricanes are. In a sense that is trying to have your cake and eat it to. So I'm not objecting to either an ontic or epistemic foundational characterization. I'm simple saying that if you label it one way at the experiential level then denying those same labels at a different level is incongruent.
And I would say the simple path that avoids any such incongruences is simply recognizing that any ontological statements we choose to make, whether they be about hurricanes or atoms or any physical "properties" of our world, are all going to be effective and useful pictures that we are choosing to borrow from conceptual structures like mathematics or everyday experience, and have no separate "existence" in the real world-- they exist only in the conceptual structures that we borrow them from. Same for properties-- so we can use properties within the context that they serve us, but we cannot prove things from using them, we cannot let a picture drive our logic that tells us what kinds of
interpretations of quantum mechanics are possible, unless we allow that our proof only applies to those who would enter into our picture, and make our "mild" assumptions.
For instance, you state the opinion that it is natural that real ontic entities are not the foundational basis of the universe. If I applied you judgement of Jaynes to this statement couldn't I insist that you are not a realist, and that calling yourself so constitutes a mind projection fallacy ostensibly to justify the [real]ity of your own opinion?
The issue here is, which should we regard as the "null hypothesis": that the ontic entities we create in our language about reality really are the foundational basis of the universe, or that they really are only what we can demonstrate them to be (ideas we create in our language and our mathematical theories, which are then transplanted from the conceptual structures in which they demonstrably exist and used in physical contexts where they do not demonstrably exist). All I am saying is this: the true realist must adopt the latter, not the former, as their null hypothesis, because to do otherwise is a basic category error. It is fully realistic to notice category errors, that's not a mind projection fallacy. Ironically, the mind projection fallacy is an identification of a particular type of category error, and I claim that my approach is the one that
avoids mind projection fallacies.
How does this differ from the hurricane analogy?
It doesn't, it's just another such analogy taken from physics. The hurricane analogy serves admirably, it is a perfect example of what I mean when I say that scientific ontologies are contextual, provisional, and goal-oriented, and that is also the reason that if we wish to imagine that systems have "properties", we should not use that picture to drive a logical necessity that these properties must determine the behavior of the system. That is actually reverse logic-- the usefulness of properties stems solely from the behaviors of the systems, not the other way around, and the usefulness of the property concept is contextual, provisional, and goal-oriented, but not unique and not logically closed. It should never appear in any proof of anything general, and it should never be viewed as a "mild" assumption, but rather, it is the assumption that colors everything that results from it. Not recognizing the import of what has been assumed is always the source of circular reasoning.
First off to say atoms are real does not entail that they are strictly independent, any more than a real hurricane is independent from the atmosphere, a white dwarf star is not independent of the mass it contains, etc.
True, but if atoms are real, and dependent on other things for that reality, then we must also assert what those other things are or else we cannot coherently talk about what an atom is. Again, the escape from this paradox is simple-- there is no need at all to regard atoms, or hurricanes, as real, so we can talk about them the way we should be talking about them: as concepts and pictures that we evoke for some specific and contextual purpose. That's just exactly what they are, why on Earth should we need to pretend they are something different to be able to call ourselves realists? Why do we need to be unrealistic to count ourselves realists? I say the realist is the person who does not fool themself.
Hence saying we should be able to tell if a white dwarf is a kind of atom is like saying if pool balls are real independent entities we should be able to say if pool balls are a type of triangle because they form a triangle in the raked position.
Yes, that's right, that's the problem with true ontologies! They just don't lead to coherent and internally consistent language, that's why it is a fantasy to imagine that a pool ball is a real thing, and not what it quite demonstrably is: a picture we borrow from some conceptual structure (generally geometrical or mathematical in nature) because it serves various purposes for us to so borrow it. But serving some purposes does not require it serve all purposes, whereas if a pool ball was "really real", then it must serve all purposes. How can something be real but break down in some context? For example, if a pool ball is real, does it have a surface, or doesn't it? Is the pool ball real, but its surface is not real? You can see the dilemmas one gets into if one insists on making the mind projection fallacy that objects that have demonstrable existence only in some conceptual structure also have existence in the "real world."
That is why symmetries take center stage in modern physics. It's the only thing we can both know and is not subject to choice, such as ontological opinions are. It is also what makes theorems, such as PBR, possible and meaningful in constraining possible models or interpretations of QM.
Yet the stated assumptions of PBR are not "let us assume the following symmetry." Instead, their assumption was that systems have properties that determine what happens to the system. Nothing in physics requires this to be true, and nothing in realism requires it either, unless a naive version of both is in use.
Though you are right that we cannot assume a priori determinism determines what happens in the usual sense, neither can we assume it doesn't in spite of contrary opinions.
Nothing in my logic requires that determinism is wrong, just like nothing in the mind projection fallacy requires that what the mind is projecting is wrong. It only requires that it is not known to be right, and thinking it must be right is then the fallacy-- the same fallacy applied by the PBR assumptions.
How we codify causal connections in science almost certainly is a construct of how we think. Yet the symmetries these causal connections entail are not.
I would label that as a mind projection fantasy-- the idea that we can tell the difference between when our codifications are a construct of how we think, and when they are not. We just don't have that ability, it's logically impossible. Symmetries also come from our mind, they are concepts that demonstrably exist in a mathematical or geometrical structure only. Applying them in the real world is just as contextual, provisional, and goal-oriented as any other scientific ontology, and thinking they are something "more real" than that is a mind projection fallacy.
If one model gives property set A and another equally valid model gives property set B, then set A can be mapped onto set B and visa versa, else the two models would not be equally valid.
I agree with that but I'm not sure I see the relevance-- models are always going to invoke properties, that's just what they do. But the models never cause reality to do what the model does, so there is never any reason to imagine that the reality involves "hidden variables" that are not in the model. If the properties are not in the model, they are not "hidden", they are simply nonexistent for that model (and reality
never has them). We can imagine some other model that does use those properties, but we cannot say those properties caused the system in question to behave the way it did, no model can claim to involve a "complete set of properties" the way the PBR proof invokes (unless "completeness" is defined in the provisional sense of "sufficient to get the predictions of the theory", but all theories do that, the properties are then just the states).
Let me say it like this: if one believes that ontic elements actually underpin a theory that does not refer to them, then one must hold that any statistical interpretation of the states of the theory must be built from ensembles of those ontic elements. But if the theory does not actually construct its states that way, it would be quite a coincidence if it could be interpreted that way. The key point is, wave functions can still be viewed as epistemic (as I do) if one simply asserts the very realist attitude that the epistemic states of any theory are always going to be the same as the ontic states of that theory (because the latter doesn't really exist independently of the former, there is no such thing as ontic states of a theory that could ever be distinguished from the epistemic states of that theory). No properties, no proof.
I think that you appear to be undervaluing the immutability of symmetries on the grounds that these symmetries can be contextualized in a myriad of different ways. In it's simplest form the true reality that some people chase is equivalent to arguing over whether the car was doing 70 mph or the ground was doing 70 mph under it. In more complex circumstances this non-physical coordinate attribute vastly changes the character and even apparent identity of what reality is. Even your "dressed atoms" is simply a regrouping of coordinates such that variable sets are regrouped as fewer sets of different variables.
Absolutely, that's the point-- we must not reify our coordinates, it would be an example of the mind projection fallacy. But that's just the coordinate projection fallacy-- the mind projection fallacy goes much deeper. It must extend to everything the mind is doing, because as soon as we think we can use our mind to tell the difference, we are committing the mind projection fallacy. We cannot have it both ways, which is just what Jaynes appears to do-- if he disagrees with something, it is the mind projection fallacy, but if he agrees with it (like "atoms are real"), then he thinks his mind can tell the difference between when it is projecting and when it isn't. I cannot imagine how he thinks he can navigate that core logical inconsistency.