AcidRainLiTE said:
I just had a discussion with someone who said he thought about quotient rings of polynomials as simply adjoining an element that is a root of the polynomial defining the ideal.
For example, consider a field, F, and a polynomial, x-a, in F[x]. If we let (x-a) denote the ideal generated by x-a, then we can form the quotient ring F[x]/(x-a). He was saying we can think about this ring as F[a] (i.e. adjoining a (which is a root of x-a) to the original field F).
This seems like a very useful intuition to have, but I am still struggling to see how it is true. Up until now, I've been thinking of the quotient ring simply in terms of a bunch of equivalence classes of polynomials, which is difficult to have an intuition for.
First, to choose a first degree polynomial x-a is not very interesting (although formally correct), since we only get F back: F[a]=F, since a in F (otherwise, x-a would not be a polynomial over F).
Second, for this to work, we must use an
irreducible polynomial over F, for otherwise, the quotient ring will not be a field.
Suppose that we take the quotient ring F[x]/I, where I is the ideal generated by an irreducible polynomial p(x) over F with degree n.
Then, two polynomials over F lie in the same equivalence class iff their difference is divisible by p(x). It follows that every equivalence class must contain a unique polynomial of degree < n. (Take any polynomial in the class and divide it with p(x). The remainder lies in the same class and has degree < n. If there are two such polynomials, their difference has degree < n and is divisble by p(x), so the difference is 0. Hence, this polynomial is unique.)
So we can represent each equivalence class in a unique way by a polynomial over F of degree < n, and of course, every such polynomial lies in an equivalence class and is represented by this very class.
The set of equivalence classes represented in this way by constant polynominals constitutes a subring of the quotient ring which is isomorphic to F, and this is therefore identified with F in a natural way. This means that we can substitute an element in the quotient ring for x in p(x) and get a new element in the quotient ring, so a polynomial over F can be considered as a polynomial over the quotient ring too. If we do this for the class [x], we see that p([x])=[p(x)])=[0]=0, so [x] ia zero pf p(x) over the quotient ring.
If we rename [x] as a, we see that the quotient ring contains no proper subring that contains both F and a. Therefore, we can write the quitient ring as F(a).
We must also prove that the quotient ring F(a) is a field. Let [q(x)] be a nonzero element in F(a). This means that the representative q(x) is not divisible by p(x) (otherwise [q(x)]=[0]=0). Since p(x) is irreducible over F (this is the only time we use this assumption) it follows from the Euclidean algorithm that 1 is a greatest common divisor of q(x) and p(x), and that there are polynomials b(x) and c(x) over F such that
b(x)q(x)+c(x)p(x)=1, and hence, [b(x)][q(x)]=[1]=1, since [p(x)]=[0]=0.
This means that [q(x)] has a multiplicative inverse in F(a): [q(x)]^(-1)=[b(x)].
Since [q(x)] was an arbitrary nonzero element in F(a), F(a) is a field.
It can also be proved that if K is any field which contains F, and an element b such that p(b)=0, then F(b), the smallest subfield of K which contains F and b, is isomorphic to the field F(a) constructed here, so in this sense, our extension is unique.
(An isomorphism can easily be constructed by starting from the evaluation homomorphism for F[x] at b, and notice that this becomes well defined for the quotient field F(a) and indeed an isomorphism onto F(b).)