When the http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/physics/Relativity/SR/rocket.html mentions that the twin paradox in flat spacetime can be understood from the traveling twin's point of view if you introduce a uniform gravitational field at the moment of acceleration, but I'm pretty sure the curvature of spacetime is independent of your coordinate system, so if it's flat in the earth-twin's inertial coordinate system it must be flat in the traveling twin's non-inertial coordinate system too, despite the uniform gravitational field seen in this system). The equivalence principle defines an equivalence between local observations in a gravitational field which involves curved spacetime and identical observations made in flat spacetime.
Zanket said:
You’re reading something into those quotes that isn’t there.
Care to give your own interpretation of why the first quote refers to "unaccelerated Cartesian coordinate systems" and the second refers to getting "closer and closer to an ideal inertial reference frame"? Those statements seems to be pretty unambiguously saying that the equivalence principle involves an equivalence between local observations of a freefalling observer and observations made by
inertial observers in flat spacetime.
For slightly more authoritative sources, I looked up the definitions of the equivalence principle in two of the most popular GR textbooks,
Gravitation by Misner, Thorne and Wheeler, and
Gravitation and Cosmology by Weinberg. Here's what
Gravitation says (p. 386):
in any and every local Lorentz frame, anywhere and anytime in the universe, all the (nongravitational) laws of physics must take on their familiar special-relativistic forms. Equivalently: there is no way, by experiments confined to infinitesimally small regions of spacetime, to distinguish one local Lorentz frame in one region of spacetime from any other local Lorentz frame in the same or any other region.
The technical definition of a "local Lorentz frame" is given on p. 207, but it basically means a coordinate system that is as close as possible to an inertial frame of SR in the neighborhood of a given event--as they put it "A local lorentz frame at a given event p0 is the closest thing there is to a global Lorentz frame at that event". Also note the statement in that quote about "experiments confined to infinitesimally small regions of spacetime", which is another way of saying you're looking at the limit as the size of your region approaches zero.
As for Weinberg's book, it defines the equivalence principle this way (p. 68):
Therefore we formulate the equivalence principle as the statement that at every space-time point in an arbitrary gravitational field it is possible to choose a "locally inertial coordinate system" such that, within a sufficiently small region of the point in question, the laws of nature take the same form as in unaccelerated Cartesian coordinate systems in the absence of gravitation.
So again, note that they are clearly talking about an equivalence between a "locally inertial coordinate system" in a gravitational field and the laws of nature as seen in an
unaccelerated coordinate system in flat spacetime, ie an inertial coordinate system. Again, this is what the equivalence principle is fundamentally about, although you can
derive the equivalence between local observations of an accelerating observer in flat spacetime and an observer at rest in a gravitational field from this basic statement of the equivalence principle.
Zanket said:
One of the quotes says, “Hence all special relativity equations can be expected to work in this small segment of spacetime.” (Boldface mine.) That includes the relativistic rocket equations, equations of special relativity for constant noninertial acceleration.
...equations which can be understood perfectly well from the point of view of an inertial coordinate system, and which can also apply locally if you let the time-intervals become arbitarily small. So, I don't see why you think this would contradict my statement that the equivalence principle is fundamentally drawing an equivalence between local observations made by 1) freefalling observers in a gravitational field and 2) inertial observers in flat spacetime.
JesseM said:
That's not what I said. Nothing moves faster than c in any inertial frame, but things do move faster than c in non-inertial frames, and there's no reason to consider inertial frames as representing what "actually" happens while non-inertial frames do not.
...
Again, the distinction between "actually" and "apparently" is physically meaningless, it's just a question of which type of coordinate system you use to analyze the problem.
Zanket said:
I don’t see any objection here, to what is in the original post. More on this below.
It wasn't meant to be, I was just objecting to your statements that "nothing actually moves faster than c" and "But apparently the buoy does" in your last post to me--the distinction you were drawing between what "actually" happens vs. what "apparently" happens seems meaningless to me.
JesseM said:
This is only true to the extent that you can derive this from the fact that the freefall observer must see the same thing locally as the inertial SR observer. For example, if the inertial observer sees a uniformly accelerating experimenter pass by him making measurements, and a freefalling observer passes by an experimenter at rest in a gravitational field making the same type of measurements, the equivalence between the freefall observer's observations and the inertial observer's observations implies that they must see the two experimenters getting the same results on their measurements (note that there is no need to consider non-inertial coordinate systems in seeing why this is true). The fundamental definition of the equivalence principle is always about freefalling observers in curved spacetime vs. inertial ones in flat spacetime, statements about the equivalence of accelerating observers and observers at rest in gravitational fields are just secondary consequences of the basic definition.
Zanket said:
Now I’m really confused as to what your objection is. It seems that your objection was that #3, what the crew observes, does not apply to #4, what an observer on a planet observes, because their frames are noninertial and you think the equivalence principle applies only to inertial observers. But you acknowledge above that the two noninertial experimenters must get the same results on their measurements according to the equivalence principle.
I objected to your vague handwavey statement about what the crew "observes". If you can specify precisely how the accelerating-in-flat-spacetime/at-rest-in-a-gravitational-field observers can set up a physical measuring apparatus to assign coordinates to
local events, and show that the accelerating-in-flat-spacetime will find that a local buoy is traveling faster than c according to the coordinates assigned by this device, then I would say that the at-rest-in-a-gravitational-field observer must find precisely the same results according to the equivalence principle. One major problem is that you seem to want to talk about the two observers assigning speeds to distant buoys rather than local ones. But if there is a way of constructing a coordinate system such that even local buoys are measured to move faster than c by the accelerating rocket, then the rocket at rest in a gravitational field would indeed have to measure the same thing.