marcus said:
A and B are well-educated so they expect that one of them will get +1 and one get -1. Everything is crystal clear to them. Off they go to their respective stations, which are quite far apart.
the day arrives and A does her measurement and she gets -1, so she applies the appropriate projection operator and collapses part of her wavefunction to show the new information she has about HER electron.
She also has in her wavefunction or state vector some experience of how RELIABLE the other experimenter, B, is. And how often B's location is hit by hurricanes. In the hypothetical situation that B is TOTALLY reliable, always remembers to do what she is supposed to, TOTALLY competent, always gets her lab machines to work perfectly, and NEVER hit by hurricanes, then of course B would be expected to be reading +1 right now, because the spins on a given axis add up to one.
But that would not be realistic. So A does not commit herself right away, she doesn't collapse the wavefunction in her state space that codes the outcome of the distant measurement because she doesn't have that information yet.
Before she does that she will at least telephone, or maybe even go and check out the other station, where B is. Before recording any information about B's electron, she has to get in CAUSAL CONTACT.
SO THE COLLAPSE OF A's wavefunction is LOCAL. Somebody had to get in somebody else's lightcone, or even go over and stand next to them at the same spot, for it to happen.
Yes, this is a perfectly all right view from a "solipsist" viewpoint: there is only ONE observer in this world, in casu "A". We never talk about the experience "B" lives, we only talk about what A OBSERVES from "B"s state.
As such, one can indeed see quantum theory as the theory that explains A's experience: first A sees her local result (local collapse of A's state), then A encounters B (local collapse of A's experience of B's state)...
So collapse occurs when A becomes, say, consciously aware of something.
This is all fine and well.
The problem arrives when we want the theory to describe at the same time also what B experiences, from its viewpoint.
Now, you can of course say that we should now apply the formalism on B's side, but there's a problem.
When A became aware of her result, and locally collapsed HER wavefunction, what can we say on B's side, from B's point of view ?
If you have A's wavefunction collapse from B's side too, then we are in contradiction with what we tried to establish, namely only "local collapse upon local becoming aware of the result". But if A's wavefunction DIDN'T collapse from B's point of view, then WE'VE LOST THE POTENTIAL LINK WITH A's experienced world.
From A's PoV:
State before A measures:
|a+>(u |b-> + v |b+>) + |a-> (x |b+> + y |b->)
A measures and "experiences" the result, it is +:
--> collapse (for A) into |A+>(u |b-> + v |b+>)
B might measure far away, but A doesn't know yet...
A meets B, and "measures" B's state, result of B is +:
--> collapse (for A) into |A+> | B+>
fine.
From B's PoV:
State before A measures:
|a+>(u |b-> + v |b+>) + |a-> (x |b+> + y |b->)
A measures, but this doesn't change anything to B yet.
B measures now, finds -
--> Collapse on B's side: (u |a+> + y |a->) |B->
B meets A, finds -:
--> Collapse on B's side: |A->|B->
All this is nice and well, except that from A's PoV, A and B got + and +, while from B's PoV, they both got - and -
This can be solved in a MWI scenario, by replacing collapse by "branch is consciously observed by"
Take # the "is conscious state by A" tag, and * the "is conscious state by B" tag, then we just have the state:
Before measurement, all states are still part of the "relative state" of A and of B:
|a+#*>(u |b-#*> + v |b+#*>) + |a-#*> (x |b+#*> + y |b-#*>)
A does a measurement, and found +, only changes the accessible states of A ; we remove what is NOT anymore part of "A's conscious world" (is projected out by the "collapse according to A":
|a+#*>(u |b-#*> + v |b+#*>) + |a-*> (x |b+*> + y |b-*>)
B does a measurement and found -:
|a+#*>(u |b-#*> + v |b+#>) + |a-*> (x |b+> + y |b-*>)
Now, A and B meet.
First, A "measures" B (that is, A learns about the "B" state) A learns that B saw +, so this gives:
|a+#*>(u |b-*> + v |b+#>) + |a-*> (x |b+> + y |b-*>)
About at the same time, B measures A, that is, B learns that "A saw -":
|a+#>(u |b-> + v |b+#>) + |a-*> (x |b+> + y |b-*>)
What now emerges is that, in "A's mental world", symbolized by #, the state of the first particle is seen to be a+ and the state of the b particle is seen to be b+. In "B's mental world", symbolized by *, the state of particle a is -, and the one of b is - too.
So both "relative views" intermixed is simply a many worlds view where the "objective" wavefunction didn't collapse, but where "the awareness of a state" narrowed down its scope as a function of what it was made aware off, to the piece of the overall wavefunction that corresponds to its measurement results.
As such, the Rovelli flavor of the relative state view is the "one-observer" version of the many worlds view (where many observers are considered in parallel).