meopemuk said:
I agree that fields make a useful mathematical concept.
But Weinberg wrote a book about physics. Clearly he thinks that fields make a useful physical concept.
meopemuk said:
The mathematical usefulness of fields does not prove that quantum field is a measurable physical concept.
The expectation values of the quantum electromagnetic field is routinely measured by many engineers, hence the quantum electromagnetic field is as much a measurable physical concept as the position of a particle, where one commonly - namely except in diffraction experiments - also measures only the expectation value.
meopemuk said:
I am not an expert in this, but I always thought that the current in semiconductors can be reliably calculated with usual classical methods. Actually, presently I am working in semiconductor industry where such calculations are performed routinely without any involvement of quantum mechanics or QFT.
One doesn't need quantum methods on the engineering level, just as one doesn't need quantum theory to use superconducting solenoids as magnets.
Nevertheless, the classical formulas are all derived from quantum field theory.
The behavior of semiconductors on the atomic level is determined in solid state physics by QED in an external periodic potential with or without impurities. In some cases, nonrelativistic QED (or even coarser approximations) is enough, but not always:
http://scholar.google.com lists about 18,800 references for the keywords
semiconductor relativistic
The valence electrons in a metal are so much delocalized that the electrons must be regarded as a quantum fluid (described by a electron density field) rather than as a collection of particles. Moreover, even when talking in the 'particle language, solid state physicists think of the valence electrons as quasi-particles whose very definition is in terms of fields.
meopemuk said:
I can agree that simple quantum effects (e.g., tunneling) may become visible in nanostructures at low temperatures. However, I've never heard that radiative corrections (whose description demands QFT methods) have any visible effect on the behavior of semiconductors.
The classical Maxwell equations don't fall from heaven as classical equations independent of quantum mechanics but are the macroscopic limit of QED. This is completely independent of either semiconductors or radiative corrections.
meopemuk said:
It would be a different matter if you are talking about condensed matter quantum field theory, which uses approximately continuous fields (such as the phonon field or electron current density). I agree that this heuristic quantum field theory has made a lot of progress in such areas as superconductivity, etc. But I thought that we are discussing fundamental, presumably exact relativistic QFT of elementary particles, which is the subject of Weinberg's book.
The _only_ difference between condensed matter quantum fields and relativistic quantum fields is that the former have nonlocal interactions and transform under the Galilei group, while the latter have local interactions and transform under the Poincare group. But both are based on the same concept of a quantum field.
Quantum fields are also more basic than particles in condensed matter theory. Indeed, the concept of identical particles has no logical basis on the particle level and must be introduced in an ad hoc way to get agreement with experiment. And it completely destroys the very basis of a reasonable particle concept: the possibility to assign observables (self-adjoint operators) to the position of a particle inside a multiparticle system. There _are_ no such observables.
On the other hand, identical particles are one of the most elementary consequences of the
quantum field concept, and certain smeared fields are both observable in the formal sense of being self-adjoint operators on the Hilbert space of the system _and_ in the sense of measurable expectation values.
meopemuk said:
Electrons bound in a molecule or a crystal. Chemists think of them in terms of charge density (a field concept), and solid state physicists think of them in terms of a fluid (another field concept). Particles are not experimentally identifiable except under very extreme circumstances.
Finally, the difficulties you have in forcing QED into the Procrustes bed of a pure particle picture
are proof of that the latter is unnatural and incomplete. Indeed, the canonical Fock space electrons that figure in your approach lack the electromagnetic field with which they need to be accompanied as asymptotic, physical particles) in order to exhibit the correct infrared behavior.
You would notice further problems if you were to extend your theory to handle the relaticistic plasma (see, e.g., H.A. Weldon, Phys. Rev. D 26, 1394–1407 (1982), http://llacolen.ciencias.uchile.cl/~vmunoz/download/papers/w82.pdf ). I wonder how you'd do that in your version of QED.
By the way, in your book you give a fairly complete list of publications related to Faddeev's dressing method, which is the basis of your perturbative particle-only approach to QED. Maybe you want to add the following one...
I.Ya. Aref'eva
Renormalized scattering theory for the Lee model
Teoret. Mat. Fiz. 12 (1972) 331-348
Theor. Math. Phys. 12 (1972), 859-872
http://mi.mathnet.ru/eng/tmf2995
Maybe you should send a link to your book to your fellow countryman Faddeev, whom you owe so much, and ask him why he gave up his dressing approach in favor of the usual field theoretic methods that lead him to the today accepted solution of the infrared problem in QED.