Errors in Ballentine (QM Textbook)?

  • Thread starter Thread starter PeterDonis
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Errors Textbook
AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on criticisms of Ballentine's interpretation of quantum mechanics, particularly regarding his claims about the Copenhagen interpretation and experimental evidence, such as the "watched pot" experiment. Participants argue that Ballentine misrepresents key concepts and lacks a clear statement on state reduction, leading to incorrect conclusions. There is a debate about whether Ballentine's textbook is suitable for beginners in quantum mechanics, with some asserting it is advanced and potentially misleading without a solid foundation in the subject. Despite the criticisms, some acknowledge that Ballentine's work can provoke deeper thinking about foundational issues in quantum mechanics. Overall, the conversation highlights the importance of understanding various interpretations and the potential pitfalls of relying solely on one source.
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
PeterDonis said:
As discussed (and as noted in the 7 Rules Insights article), Ballentine does not include Rule 7 in his axioms. His equation 9.9 is more or less equivalent to Rule 7, but as the Insights article notes, Ballentine does not accept that equation as fundamental. He derives it as an effective rule in his equation 9.28.

But the question is whether the derivation is correct.

It is not generally accepted that postulate 7 can of the Insights article can be derived from the first 6 postulates alone, so if Ballentine is doing that, it is not consensus physics.

Nielsen and Chuang state in their textbook published in 2000 & 2010 (p85) "The status of Postulate 3 as a fundamental postulate intrigues many people. Measuring devices are quantum mechanical systems, so the quantum system being measured and the measuring device together are part of a larger, isolated, quantum mechanical system. (It may be necessary to include quantum systems other than the system being measured and the measuring device to obtain a completely isolated system, but the point is that this can be done.) According to Postulate 2, the evolution of this larger isolated system can be described by a unitary evolution. Might it be possible to derive Postulate 3 as a consequence of this picture? Despite considerable investigation along these lines there is still disagreement between physicists about whether or not this is possible. We, however, are going to take the very pragmatic approach that in practice it is clear when to apply Postulate 2 and when to apply Postulate 3, and not worry about deriving one postulate from the other." [Here both the Born rule and state reduction are included in their postulate 3, so it is slightly different from the case where Ballentine states the Born rule but omits state reduction as a postulate.]

It is possible to derive postulate 7 as an effective rule with other assumptions, eg. hidden variables, if so, what additional assumptions has Ballentine used?

Other possibilities are that Ballentine is unaware that he has used the postulate here, since he rejects it in his criticism of Interpretation A and the watched pot experiment, and thus has made a double error of rejecting the postulate, and using it.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #53
atyy said:
It is not generally accepted that postulate 7 can of the Insights article can be derived from the first 6 postulates alone

The term "derived" is ambiguous. Ballentine does not claim to derive his version of the projection postulate (his equation 9.28) as a rigorous mathematical theorem valid in all cases. He only derives it as an "effective rule" (to use the term used in the Insights article) applying to certain particular cases. Doing that is not inconsistent with it being impossible to derive it as a rigorous mathematical theorem valid in all cases.

That said, from what I can see, Ballentine's derivation of his effective rule appears to assume the ensemble interpretation; if that is the case, then that would be an additional assumption.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba, dextercioby and vanhees71
  • #54
PeterDonis said:
As discussed (and as noted in the 7 Rules Insights article), Ballentine does not include Rule 7 in his axioms. His equation 9.9 is more or less equivalent to Rule 7, but as the Insights article notes, Ballentine does not accept that equation as fundamental.
Yes, that matches my reading of Ballentine.

He derives it as an effective rule in his equation 9.28.
No, this does not match my reading of Ballentine. (Where does he use the phrase "effective rule" or equivalent? I don't see that.)

Also, (9.28) and hence (9.29) are specific to filtering-type measurements.

[...] from what I can see, Ballentine's derivation of his effective rule appears to assume the ensemble interpretation;
He derives the formula (9.28) in the context of filter-type measurements only, and if you're going to do filtering, of course the experimental preparation must supply an ensemble to the filter's input.

atty said:
But the question is whether the derivation is correct.
If there is no "derivation" of such kind in the first place, but rather a derivation of a specific formula applicable to filter-type measurements only, then this is not the question, but rather a straw man.

atty said:
Other possibilities are that Ballentine is unaware that he has used the postulate here, since he rejects it in his criticism of Interpretation A and the watched pot experiment, and thus has made a double error of rejecting the postulate, and using it.
Straw man again.

Indeed, another possibility is that you haven't studied carefully what Ballentine has actually written.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #55
PeterDonis said:
That said, from what I can see, Ballentine's derivation of his effective rule appears to assume the ensemble interpretation; if that is the case, then that would be an additional assumption.

How would the ensemble interpretation allow the derivation? This is the assignment of a state to a subensemble - but at this point, has Ballentine given any postulates that allow the assignment of a state to a subensemble?

One can assign subensembles as in Bohmian Mechanics with the addition of hidden variables. However, it doesn't seem that Ballentine has stated any clear statement of hidden variables. Ballentine does mention Einstein's Ensemble Interpretation, which does have hidden variables. However, one needs to define the variables and their dynamics for a derivation, as in Bohmian Mechanics.

Possibly another way to to define subensembles would be to define the quantum state(s) of subensembles before the measurement. However, we know that in general there is not a unique assignment of the state of subensembles, and a measurement is still needed to pick out the relevant subensemble. That would again require a postulate equivalent to the postulation of state reduction, which has been rejected by Ballentine.
 
  • #56
atyy said:
How would the ensemble interpretation allow the derivation?

See @strangerep's response in post #54.
 
  • #57
PeterDonis said:
See @strangerep's response in post #54.

Strangerep says "He derives the formula (9.28) in the context of filter-type measurements only, and if you're going to do filtering, of course the experimental preparation must supply an ensemble to the filter's input." It's hard to see why this is different from postulating state reduction, which has been rejected. Does the "of course" correspond to obvious but unstated steps in a derivation, or is the "of course" a postulate from physical intuition?

The problem here is to make sense of Eq 9.28 given that state reduction has been rejected, and only unitary evolution of the quantum state asserted. A correct derivation consistent with Ballentine must be consistent with his criticism of Interpretation A, otherwise it will also be subject to those (wrong) criticisms.
 
  • #58
PeterDonis said:
Agreed. I had raised the possibility earlier that something might have changed between editions of Ballentine, but that turned out not to be the case. So it looks like we'll need to make some corrections to the article.

@A. Neumaier will have to clarify that part, as I think it wasn't in the drafts I read, or I missed it. However, the possibility is the edition and page numbers are correct, and that A. Neurmaier read that as a derivation of effective state reduction, because that is what Ballentine intends 9.21 to be. At this point, Ballentine believes that Interpretation A has a state reduction, and he is trying to explain why Interpretation A seems to work most of the time.

However, this cannot be taken to be a correct derivation of collapse for 9.28, since Interpretation A in fact does not have a state reduction at that point in the experiment being discussed. Only Ballentine's wrong conception of Interpretation A has a state reduction.
 
  • #59
vanhees71 said:
It's hard to say, what Bohr really meant ;-)). I'm not sure whether or not he proposed a state reduction.

Interestingly, Weinberg's QM text (p82) says "As Bohr acknowledged, in the Copenhagen interpretation a measurement changes the state of a system in a way that cannot itself be described by quantum mechanics. [footnote 3] This can be seen from the interpretive rules of the theory. If we measure ... then the state will collapse ..." The footnote 3 he gives says "There are variants of the Copenhagen interpretation sharing this feature, some of them described by B. S. DeWitt, Physics Today, September 1970, p. 30."
 
  • #60
PeterDonis said:
The term "derived" is ambiguous. Ballentine does not claim to derive his version of the projection postulate (his equation 9.28) as a rigorous mathematical theorem valid in all cases. He only derives it as an "effective rule" (to use the term used in the Insights article) applying to certain particular cases. Doing that is not inconsistent with it being impossible to derive it as a rigorous mathematical theorem valid in all cases.

That said, from what I can see, Ballentine's derivation of his effective rule appears to assume the ensemble interpretation; if that is the case, then that would be an additional assumption.
He simple defines what is understood as a projective or von Neumann filter measurement. It's not a general rule or postulate but just a definition of a special type of experiment, which an be formulated in terms of the postulates of the minimal interpretation (as described in our Insights article). That such types of experiments are feasible in the real world is also evident from the many real-world experiments done with all kinds of systems in the labs where QT is investigated (e.g., quantum optics, AMO, HEP, condensed matter...).
 
  • #61
vanhees71 said:
He simple defines what is understood as a projective or von Neumann filter measurement. It's not a general rule or postulate but just a definition of a special type of experiment, which an be formulated in terms of the postulates of the minimal interpretation (as described in our Insights article). That such types of experiments are feasible in the real world is also evident from the many real-world experiments done with all kinds of systems in the labs where QT is investigated (e.g., quantum optics, AMO, HEP, condensed matter...).

So it's still a postulate. It's postulate 7 in https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/the-7-basic-rules-of-quantum-mechanics/.
 
  • #62
I'm not happy with calling it a postulate for the said reason. It's the definition of a special (usually idealized) kind of experiments. It's rather a question of how to apply the theory to a specific kind of preparation-observation procedures in each individual case of such a kind of experiment.
 
  • #63
vanhees71 said:
I'm not happy with calling it a postulate for the said reason. It's the definition of a special (usually idealized) kind of experiments. It's rather a question of how to apply the theory to a specific kind of preparation-observation procedures in each individual case of such a kind of experiment.

Well, that's an easily fixed reason. We can just use the more general state reduction postulate. For discrete variables, the more general state reduction postulate can be derived by using the projection postulate on a measurement model. This complaint is different from Ballentine's criticism of orthodox quantum mechanics by asserting that there is only unitary evolution of the quantum state.
 
  • #64
There is only unitary evolution of the quantum state when considering a closed system.

A filter measurement necessarily involves more than the measured system, namely the filter.
 
  • #65
vanhees71 said:
There is only unitary evolution of the quantum state when considering a closed system.

A filter measurement necessarily involves more than the measured system, namely the filter.

Then after that, one needs the state reduction postulate.
 
  • #66
No, you need to take a partial trace and describe the evolution by some master equation. That can be FAPP a kind of "state reduction", but it's nothing outside the dynamical laws of QT!
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and jbergman
  • #67
vanhees71 said:
No, you need to take a partial trace and describe the evolution by some master equation. That can be FAPP a kind of "state reduction", but it's nothing outside the dynamical laws of QT!

Well, we shall have to disagree. There is a reason state reduction is stated in many good textbooks.
 
  • #68
Well, I fail to see its necessity and why one should have, in the case of local relativistic QFT (the Standard Model!), a self-contradiction between the successful formalism and an unneeded statement.
 
  • Like
Likes jbergman
  • #69
vanhees71 said:
There is only unitary evolution of the quantum state when considering a closed system.
But unitary evolution is deterministic. Does it mean that the quantum state of a closed system evolves deterministically and that there is no randomness in the quantum state of a closed system? But something does change randomly in a closed system, right? So does it mean that, in a closed system, there is something which is not the quantum state?
 
  • #70
There is no randomness in the evolution of the quantum state at all. Why should there be? The Schrödinger equation is a perfectly deterministic equation for the wave function.

Quantum theory is probabilistic in its notion of the meaning of the state (Born's rule). Observables don't necessarily take determined values but this depends on the state the system is prepared in. That's why measuring an observable on an ensemble of equally prepared systems, which is not determined to have a certain value, results in a random-number distribution whose statistics is described by the probabilities given by the state the system is prepared in (via Born's rule).

I don't understand your last sentence. A system is described by an observable algebra (realized usually by a set of self-adjoint operators) on an appropriate Hilbert space. The properties of the system is described by the statistical operator, representing its state. What else should there be?
 
  • #71
vanhees71 said:
A system is described by an observable algebra (realized usually by a set of self-adjoint operators) on an appropriate Hilbert space. The properties of the system is described by the statistical operator, representing its state. What else should there be?
So there are two things, the state (which is deterministic) and the observables (which are random). I have two questions.

1) Do observables have random values when they are not measured?

2) If observables are random, how is it compatible with the Heisenberg picture where the observable operator has a deterministic evolution with time?
 
  • #72
1) doesn't make sense, and it's not what quantum theory says. Quantum theory tells you the probability to find a certain value when measuring an observable, given the state the measured system is prepared in.

2) Quantum theory doesn't depend on the picture of time evolution used. The observable (probabilistic) predictions of quantum theory are always in the picture-independent matrix elements of the statistical operator,
$$\rho(t,o,o') \langle o,t|\hat{\rho}(t)|o,t' \rangle.$$
where ##|o,t \rangle## is a common eigenvector of a complete set of compatible observables ##O##.

Both the equations of motion for the states (statistical operators) and the self-adjoint operators representing observables in an arbitrary picture of time evolution are of course deterministic.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #73
vanhees71 said:
1) doesn't make sense, and it's not what quantum theory says. Quantum theory tells you the probability to find a certain value when measuring an observable, given the state the measured system is prepared in.
Does quantum theory say anything about those values when they are not measured?

vanhees71 said:
2) Quantum theory doesn't depend on the picture of time evolution used. The observable (probabilistic) predictions of quantum theory are always in the picture-independent matrix elements of the statistical operator,
$$\rho(t,o,o') \langle o,t|\hat{\rho}(t)|o,t' \rangle.$$
where ##|o,t \rangle## is a common eigenvector of a complete set of compatible observables ##O##.

Both the equations of motion for the states (statistical operators) and the self-adjoint operators representing observables in an arbitrary picture of time evolution are of course deterministic.
So there are 3 things, not 2. The state (which is deterministic), the observable operator (which is also deterministic), and the value of the observable operator (which is random). Is that right?
 
  • #74
Quantum theory predicts the values of observables when measured. Physics doesn't care about unobserved things.

An observable operator doesn't take values. It's a linear mapping ##\mathcal{H} \rightarrow \mathcal{H}##.

I'm a bit puzzled why we are discussing these completely basic undisputed facts about QT all of a sudden.
 
  • #75
vanhees71 said:
Physics doesn't care about unobserved things.
So why do you care that conserved charge exists even when it is not measured?
 
  • #76
vanhees71 said:
I'm a bit puzzled why we are discussing these completely basic undisputed facts about QT all of a sudden.
That's my strategy of phishing, to catch you in an inconsistency. :wink:
Now I think I know what exactly is inconsistent in your interpretation, it's inconsistent double standards of relevancy.
 
  • #77
Demystifier said:
So why do you care that conserved charge exists even when it is not measured?
Some might say that an unobserved universe doesn't exist; for an observer to exists in the first place it or he needs a universe to exists in and for such a universe to exists it needs an observer in it that will observe/notice its existence.

But this is just philosophy...
Life goes in circles anyways.
:cool:
 
  • #78
vanhees71 said:
I'm not happy with calling it a postulate for the said reason. It's the definition of a special (usually idealized) kind of experiments. It's rather a question of how to apply the theory to a specific kind of preparation-observation procedures in each individual case of such a kind of experiment.
I have quoted the general version of the postulate in the other thread. Do you think the state-after-measurement rule (2.93) there shouldn't be included as part of a postulate because it can be derived from the other postulates? (I'm not sure if it makes sense to keep these two threads separate)
 
  • #79
vanhees71 said:
There is only unitary evolution of the quantum state when considering a closed system.

The term "closed system", at least as it is used in the 7 Basic Rules Insights article, does not include any system on which a measurement is being made. So your statement here, while true, is irrelevant to what happens when a measurement is made, which is the case under discussion.

vanhees71 said:
There is no randomness in the evolution of the quantum state of a closed system at all.

See my bolded addition above. With that addition, you are simply stating a property of unitary evolution of a closed system, as that term is defined above. But again, that property is not relevant to what happens when a measurement is made.
 
  • #80
Everyone, please bear in mind that this thread is about the specific discussion of errors in Ballentine, and that we are in the regular QM forum, where the accepted statement of the postulates of QM is that given in the 7 Basic Rules Insights article. We are investigating the possibility that the Ballentine reference in that article might need to be corrected, but that is not intended to open the doors to a general discussion of everyone's views of QM. Also please bear in mind that interpretation discussions belong in the interpretations subforum, not this one.
 
  • #81
kith said:
I'm not sure if it makes sense to keep these two threads separate

This thread is specifically about Ballentine, as I noted in my previous post just now. And as I also noted in that post, the relevant version of any postulate for purposes of this thread is what is in the 7 Basic Rules Insights article, not any other source.
 
  • #82
Since there seems to be enough information indicating that we will need to make some corrections to the 7 Basic Rules Insights article, I have moved posts specifically on that topic to the discussion thread for the article, here:

https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/the-7-basic-rules-of-quantum-mechanics.971724/

Please move further discussion of what corrections need to be made to the Insights article to that thread.
 
  • #83
PeterDonis said:
I think this is a separate question from the one I described above.
In principle, yes. In practice, part of the critique of the projection postulate is that it isn't general. This discussion has been going on at PF without resolution for a long time and currently, I think the best road to identify the core of the issue is the general case. I think this thread and it's spin-off have contributed quite a bit here, so in any case thanks for starting them.

PeterDonis said:
Perhaps we need to either augment the article or do a follow-up article to cover how the rules need to be generalized to the POVM formalism. If there is interest in doing that, I'll start a separate thread on that topic (and post a link to it here).
I would appreciate this but I can only contribute limited time and limited expertise.
 
  • #84
PeterDonis said:
The term "closed system", at least as it is used in the 7 Basic Rules Insights article, does not include any system on which a measurement is being made. So your statement here, while true, is irrelevant to what happens when a measurement is made, which is the case under discussion.

I suspect that @vanhees71 refers to a closed system, because he believes that we can in principle include the observer and measurement apparatus in the quantum state, so that there is only unitary evolution. This is also my reading of what Ballentine means in his textbook, given his criticism of standard QM. I believe that postulating unitary evolution without state reduction is not correct unless one introduces additional postulates (eg. as attempted by many worlds, hidden variables, which also remain non-standard).
 
  • #85
kith said:
In practice, part of the critique of the projection postulate is that it isn't general. This discussion has been going on at PF without resolution for a long time and currently, I think the best road to identify the core of the issue is the general case.

As I noted in post #82 a little bit ago, I have moved that discussion to the comment thread on the Insights article.
 
  • #86
atyy said:
I suspect that @vanhees71 refers to a closed system, because he believes that we can in principle include the observer and measurement apparatus in the quantum state, so that there is only unitary evolution.

But just including the observer and measurement apparatus is not enough. You also have to include the environment, which potentially can include the entire rest of the universe.

I think at this point things become highly interpretation-dependent.

atyy said:
This is also my reading of what Ballentine means in his textbook, given his criticism of standard QM.

I'm not sure Ballentine's viewpoint is that of "only unitary evolution", because he believes quantum measurements have single outcomes. You can't get single outcomes out of only unitary evolution. I'm not sure Ballentine is taking any of the alternative viewpoints you mention (many worlds, hidden variables, etc.), but it doesn't seem to me like he is taking an "only unitary evolution" viewpoint either.
 
  • #87
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure Ballentine's viewpoint is that of "only unitary evolution", because he believes quantum measurements have single outcomes.
Please give a specific reference that supports your account of what Ballentine supposedly believes.

[Sorry, but I don't like unsupported verbaling. In the spirit of the PF rules, such claims need to be supported by appropriate references.]
 
  • #88
strangerep said:
Please give a specific reference that supports your account of what Ballentine supposedly believes.

Um, his entire textbook?

Seriously, I'm not sure where to start, since the assumption that individual measurements have single outcomes seems to me to be there in pretty much everything he says. Certainly it seems to be a necessary assumption of the ensemble interpretation that he explicitly adopts. If you really aren't seeing that when you read his textbook, then I can try to pick out particular passages that give me that impression.
 
  • #89
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure Ballentine's viewpoint is that of "only unitary evolution", because he believes quantum measurements have single outcomes. You can't get single outcomes out of only unitary evolution. I'm not sure Ballentine is taking any of the alternative viewpoints you mention (many worlds, hidden variables, etc.), but it doesn't seem to me like he is taking an "only unitary evolution" viewpoint either.

When I mean his point of view is only unitary evolution, I mean only unitary evolution as part of the first 6 postulates in the 7 Basic Rules, ie. including the Born Rule but excluding state reduction, and probably without hidden variables. I think this is the most plausible reading of his text, because of what he says in the section "The measurement theorem for general states" which contains Eq 9.10 to 9.13 (interpretation apart, the mathematics is essentially the same as Zurek's Eq 1-5 and Eq 6, without Eq 7 in https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0306072). In this section Ballentine uses only unitary evolution, shows that state reduction is not the outcome of unitary evolution, and uses that an argument against accepting state reduction.

The Born rule gives single measurement outcomes, but it does not give quantum states corresponding to the single measurement outcomes, which is why I think Ballentine wrongly rejects the state reduction postulate without replacing it with anything else.

The other plausible reading, but I think less likely, is that Ballentine assumes hidden variables, since he refers to Einstein's Ensemble interpretation. But like you, I think this is not likely what he means (otherwise vanhees71 would not read Ballentine as a minimal statistical interpretation).
 
  • #90
  • #91
PeterDonis said:
Since your post took this question far beyond just a question about Ballentine specifically, and well over the line into interpretation, I have moved it to the other thread in the interpretations forum where collapse is being discussed:

https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/difference-between-collapse-and-projection.998545/post-6445336
Fine with me, but if this splits in zillions of subthreads it's hard to follow. I think the claim that Ballentine's book is "wrong" is just the claim that the ensemble interpretation is "wrong". So why not keeping the postings in one thread such that the context of the arguments is clear.

But I think, I made my argument now several times, and don't need to repeat it further anyway.
 
  • #92
vanhees71 said:
I think the claim that Ballentine's book is "wrong" is just the claim that the ensemble interpretation is "wrong".

And that discussion belongs in the thread in the interpretations subforum, which is where I have moved all posts along those lines.

vanhees71 said:
why not keeping the postings in one thread such that the context of the arguments is clear.

Because interpretation discussions are always matters of opinion. If Ballentine prefers the ensemble interpretation, that's his business. No one can say he's "wrong" for doing that; doing it is not an "error" in his textbook. But if there are errors in Ballentine about minimal QM itself, apart from any interpretation, that is what this thread, which is in the regular QM forum, is about.
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy and Motore
  • #93
There are ways to derive the state reduction rule without hidden variables. They involve using a simultaneous measurement (for which the Born rule applies) to define a sequential measurement (which requires state reduction), and requiring consistency between the simultaneous and sequential calculations.

Heuristically, one can see this in Bell tests, where if the measurement is simultaneous in one frame, it is sequential in another, then it can be seen that state reduction is required for consistency.

Another example is found in using an instrument to define state reduction, where a simultaneous measurement on the apparatus and the system is considered to be equivalent to sequential measurements on the system, eg. section 6.2.3 on Conditional output states in
https://arxiv.org/abs/0810.3536
Guide to Mathematical Concepts of Quantum Theory
Teiko Heinosaari, Mario Ziman

However, these are not compatible with Ballentine's assertion that unitary evolution alone should disallow state reduction and they are not compatible with Ballentine's criticism of Messiah's statement that the measurement unpredictably disturbs the system. In the above notes by Heinosaari and Ziman, section 6.3.1 says No information without disturbance. If one is not continually enlarging the Hilbert space with each measurement, then the state reduction postulate does give correct quantum mechanics.
 
  • #94
atyy said:
@A. Neumaier will have to clarify that part, as I think it wasn't in the drafts I read, or I missed it. However, the possibility is the edition and page numbers are correct, and that A. Neumaier read that as a derivation of effective state reduction, because that is what Ballentine intends 9.21 to be. At this point, Ballentine believes that Interpretation A has a state reduction, and he is trying to explain why Interpretation A seems to work most of the time.
See my comments here.
 
  • #96
A. Neumaier said:
See my comments here.

Thanks. I think the revised comments have essentially the same meaning as the original comments.

With respect to the subject of the OP of this thread, I think Ballentine's derivation in that section is problematic, as it
(i) is in the context of wrongly assuming that the standard interpretation has a state reduction, where the standard interpretation has none.
(ii) on p244, Ballentine says about his derivation that "This “reduction” of the state is not a new fundamental process, and, contrary to the impression given in some of the older literature, it has nothing specifically to do with measurement."

Well, perhaps it is not a new fundamental process (we don't care about that in the orthodox interpretation, as the state is just a way of calculating probabilities of measurement outcomes), but given that Nielsen and Chuang still state reduction as a postulate, explicitly acknowledging that its derivation is controversial, it still remains correct to state it as a postulate. And even if one derives state reduction in the orthodox interpretation by defining it via consistency of simultaneous and sequential measurements (reference in post #93), there the state reduction is specifically related to measurement, and specifically with the measurement outcome.
 
  • #97
PeterDonis said:
Um, his entire textbook? [...]
Oh, I see now what you meant. I misunderstood you before.

(It's probably time for me to exit this thread, take a Bex, and have a good lie down.)
 
  • #98
atyy said:
Thanks. I think the revised comments have essentially the same meaning as the original comments.

With respect to the subject of the OP of this thread, I think Ballentine's derivation in that section is problematic, as it
(i) is in the context of wrongly assuming that the standard interpretation has a state reduction, where the standard interpretation has none.
(ii) on p244, Ballentine says about his derivation that "This “reduction” of the state is not a new fundamental process, and, contrary to the impression given in some of the older literature, it has nothing specifically to do with measurement."

Well, perhaps it is not a new fundamental process (we don't care about that in the orthodox interpretation, as the state is just a way of calculating probabilities of measurement outcomes), but given that Nielsen and Chuang still state reduction as a postulate, explicitly acknowledging that its derivation is controversial, it still remains correct to state it as a postulate. And even if one derives state reduction in the orthodox interpretation by defining it via consistency of simultaneous and sequential measurements (reference in post #93), there the state reduction is specifically related to measurement, and specifically with the measurement outcome.
I agree.
 
  • #99
atyy said:
Heuristically, one can see this in Bell tests, where if the measurement is simultaneous in one frame, it is sequential in another, then it can be seen that state reduction is required for consistency.
This is self-contradictory: According to local relativistic QFT (in this case particularly QED) describes all findings correctly. This implies that there can be no causal effect between measurement events that are spacelike separated (that's a mathematical statement!). So there can be no state reduction through the measurement at one place affecting causally the outcome of the (in some frame) later measurement at the other place.

Since nature is frame-independent if there's no state reduction in one frame, there cannot be one in any other.
 
  • #100
vanhees71 said:
This is self-contradictory: According to local relativistic QFT (in this case particularly QED) describes all findings correctly. This implies that there can be no causal effect between measurement events that are spacelike separated (that's a mathematical statement!). So there can be no state reduction through the measurement at one place affecting causally the outcome of the (in some frame) later measurement at the other place.

Since nature is frame-independent if there's no state reduction in one frame, there cannot be one in any other.

Quantum mechanics is not about cause and effect. It is only about predicting the probabilities of measurement outcomes.
 

Similar threads

Replies
16
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
4K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Replies
62
Views
5K
Replies
13
Views
2K
Replies
225
Views
14K
Replies
0
Views
6K
Back
Top