Originally posted by Fliption
Mentat, are you suggesting that these two examples cannot be understood reductively, in principal? To me, they appear to be examples of things that aren't intuitive given are current knowledge of physics but this is probably a temporary situation. I suspect you agree with me on this and you're arguing the same thing applies to consciouness.
Yeah, I guess I'm thinking along the same lines as you are. To be sure: Are you saying that it is possible in principle, but not in practice, to reductively explain the examples I gave, and that consciousness is no different?
The view that Hypnagogue has presented in various threads is that consciousness cannot be reductively explained in principal. It's not just an question of current knowledge and technology. So from here you would need to explain why you think consciousness is no different from the examples you mentioned. You only said "it seems as rational" to think so. Why not address the specific points of the argument? It is extremely hard to do, so take your time. I've been trying to figure out a way myself but haven't been able to and currently do not think is is possible.
I see what you mean.
I read your quote, and from it deduced that, in order to prove that consciousness is explanable in principle (even if not in practice), just like those other physical phenomena, I would have to actually take a step-by-step reductive approach to consciousness, myself.
In this attempt, I'd have to draw on work that's already been done by scientists and philosophers. Let me forewarn you all that this explanation may get a little confusing, but I will try to clarify any confusions that I can. Also, it may not seem readily evident that this is a theory of consciousness/sentience per se. However, I will put the idea to the test at the end, and see if it's workable. Here goes...
For consciousness to be reductively explanable, in the way that hurricanes are reductively explanable, something must first be clarified: The aim is to take a reductionist approach to consciousness,
using the scientific method only.
This is obviously necessary, since we are trying to deduce the possibility of creating a
scientific theory of consciousness. However, there is an important philosophical repercussion to this: One can no longer ask "why" these processes produce consciousness. Science can only show us 1) Which mechanisms are conscious; 2) Which mechanisms are certainly
not; and 3) How to create a conscious mechanism.
Now, they only kind of reductive explanation of consciousness that I've been able to agree with has been a "selectionist" kind. Selectionist theories of consciousness are theories that, basically, give the basic unit of conscious experience, and then apply Darwinian mechanics to these units.
Basically, any Darwinian process must have 6 things:
1) There must be a pattern.
2) It (the pattern) must reproduce itself.
3) Variant patterns must sometimes be produced (by chance).
4) The pattern and its variant must compete with one another for occupation of a limited work space.
5) The competition is biased by a multifaceted environment.
6) New variants always preferentially occur around the more successful of the current patterns.
These are the six parts of any Darwinian process, as stated by William Calvin, in
The Cerebral Code: Thinking a thought in the mosaics of the mind. (BTW, in his theory, the most basic units of consciousness are hexagonal arrays of synchronously-firing neurons, each of which comes from a synchronously-firing triangular array.
But, what is the relevance of all of this? Well, it is my position that, since this process has indeed been observed occurring in the neocortex of more advanced animals (including humans), this must be the process that brings forth consciousness.
So, let's say that we identify the most discreet unit of consciousness as a hexagonal array of synchronously-firing neurons (btw, I really suggest that you all read
The Cerebral Code, as Calvin explains his theory much better than I can). We now have a pattern, and there is nothing philosophically wrong with postulating that this pattern occurs, as it is in no way conscious. Even saying that a spatiotemporal firing pattern is initiated whenever a pyrimidal neuron (those specialized neurons in the neocortex) is stimulated has little (if any) philosophical repercussion.
Now that we have the pattern, we next need a process of reproduction. What must be remembered for this part of it is that each member of the aforementioned hexagonal arrays is capable of firing with neurons outside of it's array, and does indeed do this. So, because of this tendency for synchronicity in self-restimulation (btw, I don't think I was clear enough on this previously: A set of "synchronously-firing" neurons is an array wherein each member is self-restimulating (IOW, each member is repeatedly re-stimulating itself, and is doing so in a pattern that finds synchronicity with the self-stimulation of the other neurons in its array)), one can easily see that other, nearby, neurons ("nearby", referring to the nearness of one neuron's axon terminals to the dendrites of another neuron) may be stimulated, and thus begin to re-stimulate themselves in synch with that "nearby" member of a hexagonal array.
If you're still with me, let's move on to the next step in the Darwinian process: The production of variant patterns (mutations).
I don't think too much time should be spent on this issue as it is a somewhat obvious circumstance that, where there is reproduction of a complex pattern, there will be "error". Thus, the production of variant patterns is just a natural consequence.
Next, the pattern and its variant patterns must compete for occupation of a limited work space. Now, let's say that we have an (hexagonal) array of neurons, that were initially stimulated by (for example) seeing an apple (more specifically: by the entrance of photons, bouncing off of an apple, into the retina, which then stimulated many "nearby" neurons, who, in turn, stimulated other "nearby" neurons, forming many spatiotemporal arrays). We'll call this array an "apple array". But, let's say that, one day, we saw an orange. Now, perhaps we associated these two, and so the orange can be seen as a variant on the original "apple" arrays (or, perhaps, as simply a new introduction). Well, these arrays constantly re-stimulate themselves, and must thus compete for supremacy whenever there is a new stimulation that bears resemblance to an "apple/orange".
IOW, when I see (let's say) an orange sitting on a table, there is a stimulation, and those spatiotemporal patterns which bear closer resemblance to the thing I'm seeing will "adopt" this new memory as one of their own...it will join their array. This takes up some "work space", which the "apple arrays" will have lost.
Points 5 and 6 were basically covered in that example, as well, since - if in this competition (for identification and memorization of the new object) there were neurons that had no previous array to belong to - you could have a "no-man's-land" where there was plenty of room for a completely new stimulus. However, in the case of the apples and oranges, there were arrays that were primed for a new spatiotemporal stimulus, and they quickly competed for this new space.
It's just like in biological evolution, where a population can either be isolated completely, or have varying degrees of interaction with already existent beings - the latter possibility is much more limiting to the new being's ability to variate.
Now, all this may not seem like much of a theory of consciousness, but think of this: If all these processes occur, and there are constant new stimulations (along with re-exitation of purely spatial arrays), then you have a working theory of the processing mechanism of the brain.
Now to test it out. Let's say you want to understand how someone makes "choices" (as this is clearly an integral part of being a sentient creature - being able to make choices). If the choice is something simple, like the old vanilla vs. chocolate ice cream illustration, then it's a bit too easy to just say: Arrays that correspond to "chocolate" happen to also correspond with previous enjoyable experience, whereas this is lacking in the "vanilla" arrays, and so chocolate is the biased choice. Actually, it seems that most (if not all) "choices" can be explained rather simply by such "this array is the biased choice, and thus prevailed over the competition".
No, I think the real test would be to show how it is that these functions translate to subjective experience. The problem is, from the scientific limitations we accepted at first, we can't really ask "why is this mechanism conscious, while others are not". We can, however, see if this approach meets up with the
scientific criteria...Let's see, does it: 1) Equip us to decide whether a system is conscious or not? Sure it does - if the system does have this Darwinian process occurring, then it is conscious; 2) Does it help us decide when something is
not conscious? Of course, by the inverse logic of #1; 3) Does it allow us to (in principle) produce a conscious mechanism of our own? Absolutely. If we can produce a machine (no matter what it's made of) whose discreet "thought units" are made up of synchronously-self-restimulating quanta, and these patterns can be reproduced, with allowance for error, and competition between the "parent" and "variant" copies in biased environment...well, you have a Darwin machine, and you have consciousness.
Again, I recommend the book
The Cerebral Code: thinking a thought in the mosaics of the mind, by William Calvin.
g2g now. I'll check for responses tomorrow, if I can.