misogynisticfeminist said:
This is a worked example in the book, but i can't figure out why it is this way.
Using 0 < (x-a) < \delta and (f(x)-L) < \epsilon for lim_(x\rightarrow a) f(x) = L.
Prove that lim_{x\rightarrow2} (4x-3) = 5
I can understand the steps until
{4} (x-2) < \epsilon and 0 < (x-2) < \delta
then, they suddenly get, \epsilon = \delta/4...
Cant really understand how they arrive at there, and they don't even show that the the limit is 5.
First- BE CAREFUL! It is important to state definitions
precisely. There are two errors I see in:
Using 0 < (x-a) < \delta and (f(x)-L) < \epsilon for lim_(x\rightarrow a) f(x) = L.
The first is that you don't say
how those inequalities are to be used! The second is that you are missing the absolute values signs.
The precise definition is: lim_(x\rightarrow a) f(x) = L if and only if, for any \epsilon>0, there exist \delta> 0 such that if 0<|x-a|< \delta then |f(x)-L|< \epsilon.
Here, a= 2, f(x)= 4x- 3, and L= 5. In order to show that that definition holds (that the limit really is 5) we must show that, for any \epsilon> 0 such a \delta[/b] really does exist. The best way to do that is to show how to find it!<br />
<br />
We <b>want[\b] |f(x)-L|= \epsilon. <br />
But |4x-3-5|= |4x- 8|= 4|x-2| so that is the same as 4|x-2|&lt; \epsilon or |x-2|&lt; \frac{\epsilon}{4}. <br />
Now compare that with |x-2|&lt; \delta! Looks like a good choice for \delta would be \frac{\epsilon}{4} doesn't it?<br />
<br />
In fact, we can do exactly that. A "strict" proof would be: given \epsilon&gt;0, let \delta= \frac{\epsilon}{4}. Then if |x-2|&lt; \delta, |x- 2|&lt; \frac{\epsilon}{4} so that 4|x-2|&lt; \epsilon.<br />
But then |4x- 8|= |4x-3-5|= |f(x)- L|&lt;\epsilon which what we needed to show.<br />
<br />
You are <b>right</b> to be a little puzzled because your book did not do it that way. Instead of starting from "let \delta= \frac{\epsilon}{4}", as I did here, your text, like most texts, did the "preliminary part" "If I want |f(x)- L|&lt; \epsilon, how can I find \delta" and worked the <b>opposite</b> way. That is sometimes called "synthetic proof": start from what you want to show and arrive at something you know (or can make) true. Strictly speaking, a proof should go the <b>other</b> way- from what you know is true to what you want to prove! <br />
<br />
However, as long as everything you do is <b>reversible</b> (If you can go from 4|x-2|&lt; \epsilon to |x-2|&lt; \frac{\epsilon}{4}, you can certainly go from |x-2|&lt; \frac{\epsilon}{4} to 4|x-2|&lt; \epsilon.) then just doing it one way implies the other way.</b>