Clarifying Neumaier's Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Wave or Particle?

  • Thread starter cube137
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Quantum
In summary, Neumaier's interpretation of quantum mechanics, known as the thermal interpretation, is similar to the statistical interpretation but ascribes uncertain properties to each single system. This is fully consistent with a statistical description and matches classical thermodynamics in equilibrium. In this interpretation, everything has wave nature and particles are localized concentrations of mass and energy, with wave functions having no meaning except for systems with few degrees of freedom. The state of the system is described by a density matrix or a monotone linear operator, and is considered real and objective rather than just information. The photon in the double slit experiment travels as a wave and disappears upon detection, leaving random spots at a rate determined by the impinging energy density. Neumaier's interpretation also provides
  • #36
vanhees71 said:
clearly rejects the probabilistic interpretation (in the last section of the book containing his "Four lectures on wave mechanics").
Can you please quote his rejection statement and his reasons for it?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Schrödinger, "Four Lectures on Wave Mechanics" (1928)

An obvious statistical interpretation of the ##\psi##-function
has been put forward, viz. that it does not relate to a
single system at all but to an assemblage of systems,
##\psi \bar{\psi}## determining the fraction of the systems which happen
to be in a definite configuration. This view is a little
unsatisfactory, since it offers no explanation whatever
why the Quantities ##a_{ki}## yield all the information which they
do yield*. In connexion with the statistical interpretation
it has been said that to any physical quantity which would
have a definite physical meaning and be in principle (prin-
cipiell) measurable according to the classical picture of the
atom, there belong definite proper values (just as e.g.
the proper values ##E_k## belong to the energy); and it has
been said that the result of measuring such a quantity
will always be one or the other of these proper values,
but never anything intermediate. It seems to me that
this 1st statement contains a rather vague conception, namely
that of measuring a quantity (e.g. energy or moment of
momentum), which relates to the classical picture of the
atom, i.e. to an obviously wrong one. Is it not rather bold
to interpret measurements according to a picture which
we know to be wrong? May they not have quite another
meaning according to the picture which will finally be
forced upon our mind? For example: let a beam of
electronic rays pass through a layer of mercury vapour, and
measure the deflection of the beam in an electric and in a
magnetic field before and after the beam has traversed
the vapour. According to the older conceptions this is
interpreted as a measurement of differences of energy-
levels in the mercury atom. The wave-picture furnishes
another interpretation, namely, that the frequency of
part of the electronic waves has been diminished by an
amount equal to the difference of two proper frequencies
of the mercury. Is it quite certain that these two
interpretations do not interfere with one another, and that the
old one can be maintained together with the new one?
Is it quite certain that the conception of energy,
indispensable as it is in macroscopic phenomena, has any
other meaning in micro-mechanical phenomena than the
number of vibrations in h seconds?
 
  • #38
vanhees71 said:
If we have a single electron and measure its position we see a pointlike trace on a screen (or nowadays a pixel in a digital device) but not a spread charge distribution.
As mentioned before in post #31, this is because what is measured is the track after the first ionization, where the single electron has a cigar-shaped charge distribution and moves along the cigar's long direction. Nobody expects to measure a spread charge distribution in this case.
 
Last edited:
  • #39
Exactly! So why do you claim the correctness of Schrödinger's original interpretation of the single-particle wavefunction, which clearly is a misconception.
 
  • #40
vanhees71 said:
Exactly! So why do you claim the correctness of Schrödinger's original interpretation of the single-particle wavefunction, which clearly is a misconception.
Because in all cases where one can measure the charge distribution of a single electron it conforms to his interpretation. Before the first ionization, we cannot measure the charge distribution of the electron. So we have either deny that it has a charge distribution (which is the take of the Copenhagen interpretation), or to find a definition of the charge distribution that makes sense both in the observable and in the unobservable case (which, for a single electron, is Schroedinger's interpretation). Both points of view completely agree on the measurable part, hence are equally valid.

But the Copenhagen view has a very strange side effect: The mean of something nonexistent exists!?? How can this be? The ensemble interpretation inherits this strange property, though in a less outspoken way.
 
  • #41
No they do not agree on the measurable part, because the one states that we measure a point-like location and the other states that we measure a smeared distribution. Everybody who has ever made an experiment with a weak radioactive source finds points on the scintillation screen. No single event gives a smeared distribution. QT is about what's measurable and observable not about theoretical constructs.

Scanning a probe with a tunnel microscope measures ensembles and not locations of a single particle! That's why it can resolve the distributions.

The ensemble interpretation doesn't claim that something nonexistent exists. Also the no-nonsense flavor of Copenhagen (Bohr himself included; Heisenberg has to be taken with a grain of salt ;-)) hasn't ever claimed such a thing. The only, in my opinion correct, claim is that an observable has a predetermined value if and only if the state of the system says so, i.e., if the probability to find this value is 1. That's a tautology, if you ask me!

Take the example of an electron in a hydrogen atom in its ground state. It has no definite position but a probability distribution of positions. Whenever measured you find a point-like particle (for which you usually have to destroy the atom, i.e., you have to kick out the electron, if you want a sufficient spatial resolution). If you want to measure the probability distribution you need an ensemble of hydrogen atoms. You can also use the same atom many times, you only have to make sure that you always prepare it in its ground state again before you measure the electron's position again.
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
Take the example of an electron in a hydrogen atom in its ground state. It has no definite position but a probability distribution of positions.
What does it mean for a single electron to have a probability distribution of positions? The latter is a property of an ensemble, not of a single system!
vanhees71 said:
QT is about what's measurable and observable not about theoretical constructs.
Then what is measurable and observable about the probability distribution of positions of a single electron?
 
  • #43
vanhees71 said:
Everybody who has ever made an experiment with a weak radioactive source finds points on the scintillation screen. No single event gives a smeared distribution.
Again this is since, by Mott's argument, the first ionization changes the state of the electron to one with a point-like geometric cross section, which is then measured, and of course leads to a point-like flash. The measurement (irreversible amplification) is not one of the unperturbed electron in its spherical state emanating from the source but one of the perturbed state caused by the interaction leading to the first ionization.
 
Last edited:
  • #44
vanhees71 said:
Take the example of an electron in a hydrogen atom in its ground state. It has no definite position but a probability distribution of positions. Whenever measured you find a point-like particle (for which you usually have to destroy the atom, i.e., you have to kick out the electron, if you want a sufficient spatial resolution). [...] you need an ensemble of hydrogen atoms.
Don't you agree that destroying the atom definitely changes the state of the electron?

Consider the following analogous situation: To measure the chemical structure of a complex molecule you have to destroy sufficiently many copies of it, split them into pieces that can be analyzed by a mass spectrometer, and afterwards find out how overlapping fragments can be combined to a whole. At the end, if you are able to reconstruct a unique chemical formula, your measurement was successful.

What you try to argue is like saying that in the analogous situation that whenever you measure the complex molecule you always find fragments, and conclude that the complex molecule must be an ensemble of fragments with the remarkable property that they seem to come from a single molecule that is never observed in the measurement process. Whereas the natural interpretation is that there is a single molecule, which changes its state during the measurement, so that only its fragments are measured.

In the same vein, rather than arguing that when analysing an atom one always measures rays impinging on a screen that seem to come from a spherical charge distribution which is only visible in the ensemble, it is far more natural to assume that the spherical charge distribution exists but is destroyed by the measurement process, so that the latter has to be repeated often enough to recover the original, spherical structure.

The example discussed in posts #47 and #49 of the thread Are tracks in collision experiments proof of particles? suggest the same.
 
  • #45
A. Neumaier said:
What does it mean for a single electron to have a probability distribution of positions? The latter is a property of an ensemble, not of a single system!

Then what is measurable and observable about the probability distribution of positions of a single electron?
As you say: You prepare an ensemble of independently prepared single-electrons and measure their positions, leading to the probability distribution by the usual statistical evaluation procedures. The position of the single electron is not determined when prepared in the hydrogen-atom ground state, but you know the probability distribution by solving the time-independent Schrödinger equation. You can verify the predicted probability distribution only on an ensemble. This is the standard point of view of the ensemble interpretation.
 
  • #46
A. Neumaier said:
Again this is since, by Mott's argument, the first ionization changes the state of the electron to one with a point-like geometric cross section, which is then measured, and of course leads to a point-like flash. The measurement (irreversible amplification) is not one of the unperturbed electron in its spherical state emanating from the source but one of the perturbed state caused by the interaction leading to the first ionization.
That's what makes such a scientillator a good position-measurement device. It's one way to define the position observable operationally, and without such a definition the idea of observables is empty.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
36
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
433
Replies
3
Views
762
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
13
Views
620
Replies
2
Views
802
Replies
1
Views
609
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
616
Replies
4
Views
706
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
1K
Back
Top