RedX said:
What's the point of defining \sigma algebras, i.e., why must we assign measures only to elements of a \sigma algebra?
Second, can you give an example of a set contained in the Lebesgue \sigma algebra, but not the Borel \sigma algebra? Also, is there a set not contained even in the Lebesgue \sigma algebra?
The idea of sigma algebra is designed to abstractly describe the properties for which our intuitive idea of measurement must hold. Arbitrary unions and complements seem necessary. For instance if the whole space has measure 5 and a subset has measure 2 we would think that its complement must be measurable and have measure 3. There is little else to it.
I think the Borel sigma algebra is the smallest sigma algebra that contains all of the open sets.
Such an algebra may have sets in it which we would like to be measurable but are not. These are subsets of sets of measure zero. We would like for these subsets to also have measure zero. Including them is called completing the sigma algebra.
This definition is a little slick. What is really wanted is if A is a proper subset of B and has the same measure as B we would like any subset of B that contains A to also have the same measure. This works, meaning that the extended measure is still a measure and the extended collection of sets is still a sigma algebra. A little thought shows that by including all subsets of sets of measure zero and extending the collection of sets through arbitrary union and complementation, we get all of the sets we want.
there are subsets of sets of measure zero - e.g. the Cantor set - that are not Borel measurable. I think Wikipedia should have something on this.
I think that a basis for the reals over the rationals is not Lebesque measurable.
The proof that I remember is to show that a linear map from the reals to the reals that is linear over the rationals but not over the reals is not only discontinuous but also non-measurable. One solves this by showing that if it were measurable then it would be continuous. I could be remembering this wrong. You should check it. I would be interested to see your proof.
There is a cool construction of a non-Lebesque measurable subset of the square which shows that the idea of measurability is related to the axioms of set theory. Specifically, if one assumes that the continuum hypothesis is true i.e. that the cardinality of the reals is the same as that of the first uncountable ordinal, then one can find a non-measurable subset of the square.
Take a well ordering of the reals assuming the Continuum Hypothesis is true.
Consider the set of points, (x,y) in the square such that x precedes y in this ordering.
This set is non-measurable. Why?
Consider it's characteristic function. If the set is measurable then the integral of this function will equal its measure. Fubini's Theorem says that we can find this integral by double integration and that it does not matter which axis, x or y, that we integrate across first. let's try it.
If we hold y fixed and integrate along x then the integral is zero because there are only countably many x that precede y and a countable set has measure zero. So the double integral is also zero.
If we hold x fixed, then x precedes all but countably many y so the integral equals one. This contradiction of Fubini's Theorem shows that the set is not measurable.