DrChinese said:
Can you tell me a little about how spin fits in? I am interested to learn more about that.
In the simplest possible version, you just do the obvious thing: make the wave function a spinor (satisfying, e.g., the Pauli equation rather than the Schroedinger equation). The guidance formula for spinless particles (grad psi / psi) stays basically the same too -- you need only throw a psi-dagger in the numerator and denominator to contract the spin indices.
So the ontology for particles with spin is really no different from the ontology for spinless particles. There's just a particle being guided around by a wave -- it just happens that the wave has two components (i.e., is a spinor). So when a particle riding a certain wave packet enters, say, a Stern-Gerlach device, the usual Pauli-equation-type-time-evolution causes the wave packet to split into two disjoint lumps, one of which comes out "up" along the field, the other coming out "down." And the particle just (deterministically) ends up in one or the other of those two packets, depending on its initial position. And it's a theorem that, if the initial position is Born-rule distributed (i.e., the Quantum Equilibrium Hypothesis) then the probability for an "up" or "down" "measurement outcome" is just exactly what is predicted by orthodox QM. But unlike the orthodox theory, Bohm needs no strange measurement axioms, collapse postulates, or other "magic" to make this come out -- the particle is detected near the "up" output port of the device because (whether the detector is present there or not) that's where the particle *is*.
Notice that this means "spin" isn't really a property carried by the particle at all. The particle itself isn't rotating about an axis like a tiny basketball, the way students are taught to visualize spin (but then warned not to take such visualizations too seriously). It's just a point particle -- the "spin properties" are carried exclusively by the wave function.
But there's an even stronger sense in which particles (according to Bohm's theory) don't carry spin. Spin is a "contextual property". This means that the outcome you get depends not just on the operator corresonding to the type of measurement you're doing, but the *specific* implementation of that measurement (e.g., which other commuting operators are being measured simultaneously). David Albert cooked up the simplest possible example to illustrate this. Imagine a Bohmian spin 1/2 particle coming up toward a SG device that will "measure its spin in the z direction". And suppose the initial position of the particle is such that it comes out the "spin up" output port of the SG device. Now do a thought experiment: let that same initial particle+wave be incident on the same exact SG device, but let the SG device be rotated 180 degrees so that the B-field is now pointing in the -z instead of the +z direction. Note, according to QM, this is still a device that will "measure its spin in the z direction." But according to BM (and making some other minor assumptions that aren't worth mentioning) the particle (in, mind you, the exact same initial state) will now come out of the "spin down" port of the SG device (i.e., will emerge from the device going the same direction as before).
So two situations with identical incoming particles (and they are identical at the level of the uncontrollable "hidden variable", position, not just in the sense of having been prepared the same way) and two apparatuses that "measure the particle's spin in the z direction" give different outcomes! Shocking, right? Well, not really. It is only shocking if you insist on believing that the particle really genuinely has a property called "spin" which is literally "measured" (in the sense of revealing the pre-existing value of the property) in these experiments. But according to BM, that just isn't the case. Spin is a contextual property -- the value you get depends not just on the state of the particle, but on *how* you perform the measurement -- in other words, spin isn't really "measured" at all, not literally. To say that spin is a contextual property is really just a cumbersome way of saying it isn't a property at all. See the splendid article by Goldstein et al on "Naive Realism about Operators" for more detail on this important point.
I stress it here because Dr. Chinese seems hell bent on defining a "realistic theory" to be one that attributes definite pre-measurement values to all possible observables. Hence, according to him, Bohm's theory isn't "realistic" because it doesn't attribute definite spin values to particles. In fact it says spin isn't even a property that particles possess. Yet I think it should be crystal clear that Bohm's theory is entirely "realistic", if that just means that it denies all of the idealistic nonsense (esse ist percipi) of the orthodox theory (in particular, the idea that nothing exists until it is measured, measurement is a fundamentally different kind of process than non-measurement, etc.). It's just that in BM everything always comes down to the *position* of things, so all this talk of "measuring spin" has to be carefully parsed out in terms of positions (of detector needles, if nothing else). And then everything makes perfect sense, and you reproduce all the QM predictions with a totally straightforward *realistic* theory that is completely immune to the measurement problem that plagues OQM.