Hi Meopemuk,
meopemuk said:
I would like to disagree with your statement "If one removes the
particle source, the screen is still there and the positions of various
grid regions on that screen still exist as references. In this sense,
we can still "measure position" even if there's no physical
experimental system in the lab."
Hmmm. Yet another case where I was already absolutely certain that
saying it that way would get me into trouble, so I'd better try and
clarify what I was thinking. I'll do so in the context of your
explanation...
To "measure position" you need to measure something, i.e., a physical
systems. Without the particle source you cannot realistically measure
anything. Unless there happens to be a speck of dust on the screen.
Then you can say: "Oh, the position of this dust particle is x".
Agreed. Although,... strictly speaking,... you can only say "I saw an
event flash within some region (x,y) on my position reference grid."
Without physically present electrons, alpha-particles, or dust
particles you can perform measurements only in your imagination.
Yes, but this is partly where I should have been clearer. See below.
Even when you don't have any physical system/particle in your lab, the
screen (for measuring positions) and the clock (for "measuring" time)
are still fundamentally different. In this situation, you don't get any
useful physical information from the screen (it does not perform any
measurements), but you still get "time measurements" from the clock. I
put "time measurements" in quotes, because they are not measurements in
the usual sense of this word: they are not applied to any specific
physical system. Time is simply an attribute of your experimental setup
- a numerical parameter.
But the position grid is also an "attribute of the experimental setup"
-- a set of numerical parameters. If you didn't have a memory, you
wouldn't realize that the number on the clock face keeps changing.
Similarly, if you couldn't move your head or refocus your eyes,
you wouldn't realize that there are multiple position grid regions.
The situation changes once you turn on your scattering machine and
begin to receive flashes from particles on the screen. Then you
collect physically meaningful data about real physical systems -
particles. You can say: "particle 1 had position x1", "particle 2 had
position x2", etc.
Strictly speaking, you can only say "there was a flash at position
x1", etc, and you can record these observations in a spatial sequence
(on paper) that correlates with your mental sense of time progression.
These measurements involve interactions between
physical system (particle) and the measuring apparatus (the screen).
They tell you something about particle properties. That's why we call
particle position an observable.
If we write down not only the grid position where a flash occurred, but
also the reading from our local clock, why is the time reading less
physically significant than the grid reading? In both cases, we're
correlating an event (flash) with previously established reference
systems (a position grid and a clock).
Clock readings are not affected by the presence/absence of particles
in your experiment. The clock keeps ticking at the same rate
independent on what are the states of particles hitting the screen.
But the position grid also continues to exist in the absence of
flash events.
So, clock readings cannot be called "observables". Their
"measurements" do not involve interaction between a physical system
and a measuring apparatus. They remain a parameter, which simply
labels everything that occurs in the laboratory at each specific time
instant. So, it would be incorrect to say that "particle 1 had time
t1". The correct statement is "particle 1 had position x1 when the
laboratory clock showed time t1".
Actually, I think both statements are not quite correct. I'd prefer
to say "an event occurred at lab grid position (x,y) when the
lab clock showed time t", and so on.
I.e., since we're recording not only the grid position of an event but
also the clock reading, why should the clock reading not be considered
an observed number associated with the event, just as the position grid
reference is also a number (or pair of numbers) associated with the
event?
So, from their operational meanings, "time" and "position" are very
different beasts. One should be careful not to mix them (like apples
and oranges) in the same 4D Minkowski continuum. [...]
I agree that time and position are different, and that 4D Minkowski
space is little more than a (problematic) carrier space for certain
Poincare representations. My objection against relegating time
to a lesser status than position is more to do with the role of
both position and time in parameterizing observed events.