Uncountable Set with this property

  • Thread starter Thread starter Dragonfall
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Property Set
AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on the existence of an uncountable set of positive reals where every countable decreasing sequence sums to a finite number. It is argued that if such a set contains any non-empty interval, it cannot satisfy this property due to the implications of measure theory, specifically that sets with non-zero measure must contain intervals. The conclusion drawn is that any uncountable set with the desired property must have zero measure, leading to a contradiction since sets of zero measure are countable. Various proofs and counterexamples, including the Cantor set, are discussed to explore the nuances of accumulation points and well-ordering in the context of real numbers. Ultimately, the consensus suggests that no such uncountable set can exist under the given conditions.
Dragonfall
Messages
1,023
Reaction score
5
Does there exist an uncountable set of positive reals such that every countable decreasing sequence from that set sums to a finite number?
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
I don't know how to prove it rigorously, but I'd think it reduces to a problem in measure theory.

If your uncountable set contains any non-empty interval [a, b], it fails to have the countable-sums property.

All non-empty intervals have a nonzero measure. I wouldn't be surprised if the converse was true for the real numbers. Let's assume it is for now. This means that if our uncountable set has a nonzero measure, it contains an interval, and fails to have our desired property. So, we conclude our set has zero measure.

Sets of zero measure are countable. This is our contradiction.Again, this is just my intuition. I don't know much about measure theory, but if I did, this is what I would expect the proof to look like ;-)EDIT: Or maybe the Cantor set is a counter example to the last assumption I made. It is uncountable with zero measure. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Measure_zero)
 
Last edited:
Tac-Tics said:
EDIT: Or maybe the Cantor set is a counter example to the last assumption I made. It is uncountable with zero measure. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Measure_zero)
Beat me to it.
 
I'm thinking that any uncountable set has at least one accumulation point away from zero. The problem is that if the accumulation point is from a sequence of increasing numbers instead of decreasing. Then it wouldn't work.
 
Pretty sure this proof works:

Obviously, if a set S is to have the desired property, then S \cap [a,b] is finite for all positive a and b. (Indeed, if S \cap [a,b] has infinitely many elements, we can choose a countably infinite, decreasing sequence, which necessarily diverges, since all terms are \geq a.) Furthermore, if S has this property, then any uncountable subset of S also does; thus, WLOG, S \subseteq (0, \infty) (if S \cap (0, \infty) is countable, then S \cap (-\infty, 0) is uncountable, and we may proceed in essentially the same way). Define \displaystyle U_i = \left[ \frac{1}{i + 1}, \frac{1}{i} \right] for i \geq 1, and U_0 = [1, \infty]. By above, \displaystyle \bigcup_{i = 0}^{\infty} (S \cap U_i) = S (since S \subseteq (0, \infty)); however, recall that each term S \cap U_i has finite order. Thus, S is a countable union of finite sets, and is therefore countable. This is a contradiction; hence, no such set can exist.
 
VKint said:
(Indeed, if S \cap [a,b] has infinitely many elements, we can choose a countably infinite, decreasing sequence, which necessarily diverges, since all terms are \geq a.)
Actually, that's not guaranteed. For example, consider the infinite set containing
1, 1.9, 1.99, 1.999, 1.9999, 1.99999, ...​
Every decreasing sequence whose elements in this set is necessarily finite.

The thing we can prove with this argument is that S \cap [a, \infty) is well-ordered by <.
 
Excellent point, Hurkyl; I guess that's what I get for trying to write up a post while on Vicodin. Wisdom teeth... :(

I think my proof can still be repaired, though. All I really need to show is that S \cap U_i is countable for all i (a countable union of countable sets is countable). We prove the following lemma:

Lemma: Let V be a bounded set of real numbers. If, for all x \in V, the set \{ y \in V \; | \; y &lt; x \} is countable, then V is countable.
Proof: Let q = \sup(V). Clearly, if q \in V, we're done. Thus, WLOG, q \notin V. Let p be a lower bound for V, and let d = q - p. Define \displaystyle T_i = \left[ q - \frac{d}{2^i}, q \right]. Since q is the supremum of V, it is also an accumulation point, so V \cap T_i \neq \emptyset for all i. Thus, using the axiom of choice if necessary, we can choose some non-decreasing sequence of points x_i \in V \cap T_i. Finally, define Q_i = \{ z \in V \; | \; z &lt; x_i \} (running out of letters...) and observe that \displaystyle V = \bigcup_{i = 0}^{\infty} Q_i, i.e., a countable union of countable sets (by hypothesis). This concludes the proof.

Now that we have this result, we can prove that S \cap U_i is countable by contradiction. As before, the contradiction comes from assuming that S \cap U_i is uncountable, and constructing a countable decreasing sequence of points in S \cap U_i. Indeed, if S \cap U_i is uncountable, we can choose some x_0 \in S \cap U_i such that \{ y \in S \cap U_i \; | \; y&lt;x \} is uncountable by the lemma. It should be easy to see now that we can construct a strictly decreasing sequence of points in S \cap U_i inductively, which gives the same contradiction as before.
 
Every well ordered (by <) set is countable. Then S=\cup_a (S\cap [a,\infty)) for a that are inverse powers of 2. S is therefore a countable union of countable sets, which is countable. Contradiction.

EDIT: I think you went overboard there with your lemma.
 
Every well ordered (by <) set is countable.

Not if you allow the axiom of choice...I think.
 
  • #10
VKint said:
Not if you allow the axiom of choice...I think.

But then an uncountable well-ordered set would be a counterexample to your contradiction, it would have the property we're looking for!
 
  • #11
But then an uncountable well-ordered set would be a counterexample to your contradiction.

Not at all. You'll notice that in the statement of my lemma, I specifically noted that the result only applied to set of real numbers, implying the the usual ordering on the reals must be used for the result to remain valid. In other words, the lemma proved that no uncountable set is well-ordered under the usual ordering of \mathbb{R}, which does not preclude the existence of some other well-ordering.

EDIT: I just realize that this was what you were getting at all along when you said "well ordered (by <)," in which case you were correct. My lemma was essentially just a proof of your statement that "every well ordered (by <) set is countable." Apologies for the misunderstanding.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Incidentally, where did this problem come from?
 
  • #13
I thought it up when I was playing around with the idea of uncountable sums (a previous post).
 
  • #14
If one permits the Axiom of Choice, the reals can be well ordered.

(In fact the Well Ordering Theorem, the Axiom of Choice, and Zorn's Lemma (among others) are all equivalent.)

--Elucidus
 
  • #15
So trying to rewrite what you've written in a more generally useful form, I think you've shown the following.

Define an uncountable accumulation point of a set X to be a point such that every neighborhood of that point contains uncountably many points of X.
(I doubt this is a standard term)

Every uncountable subset of R has an uncountable accumulation point​

and a slight modification will allow

Every uncountable subset of R has at least countably infinitely many uncountable accumulation points​


I haven't worked out whether or not it must have uncountably many uncountably accumulation points...
 
  • #16
Every uncountable subset of R has an uncountable accumulation point

I don't see how this follows directly from what I proved. However, it's fairly easy to prove this by using the second-countability of \mathbb{R}. Indeed, if S \subseteq \mathbb{R} is uncountable but has no uncountable accumulation point, then for all x \in S there exists an open set U_x with x \in U_x and S \cap U_x countable. Open sets are closed even under uncountable unions, so the set \displaystyle T = \bigcup_{x \in S} U_x is open. However, since \mathbb{R} is second-countable, each U_x may be written as a union of base open sets B_{x,i} for i \in I_x (i.e., some countable index set), each of which has S \cap B_{x,i} countable. We then have \displaystyle T = \bigcup_{x \in S, \; i \in I_x} B_{x,i}. However, since the base is countable, this is at most a countable union. The set S is then a countable union of countable sets, so it is countable.

Your next proposition follows fairly trivially from the first (by simply removing successive uncountable accumulation points). I also think I have a proof that any uncountable S \in \mathbb{R} must have uncountably many uncountable accumulation points. Indeed, suppose not. Let X \subseteq S be the set of all uncountable accumulation points. Then, since X is countable, S \setminus X is uncountable. Thus, S \setminus X must contain an uncountable accumulation point, contradicting assumption.

Thoughts?
 
  • #17
VKint said:
I don't see how this follows directly from what I proved.
I don't remember precisely what I was thinking -- but I had convinced myself my first proposition was either an easy consequence of what you had proved, or that your proof of your lemma contained most/all of the bits needed to prove my proposition.


The proof you give of my second and third propositions is flawed -- accumulation points of S don't actually have to be elements of S, so you don't get the contradiction you were relying on.
 
  • #18
Hurkyl said:
Define an uncountable accumulation point of a set X to be a point such that every neighborhood of that point contains uncountably many points of X. (I doubt this is a standard term)

"condensation point"
 
  • #19
The proof you give of my second and third propositions is flawed -- accumulation points of S don't actually have to be elements of S, so you don't get the contradiction you were relying on.

I must have misunderstood what you intended. The proof I gave in #16 assumed that uncountable accumulation points ("condensation points") must lie in the uncountable set itself, and proved that every uncountable subset of \mathbb{R} must have at least one such point. If you wanted to prove the existence of a condensation point not necessarily in the target set, you could do it by an inductive method similar to that used to prove the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem--dividing a bounded region containing an uncountable set into finitely many pieces at each step, and picking one point from a piece with uncountably many points. In the end, you get a convergent sequence of points in the set, which must converge to a condensation point.
 
  • #20
How about simply this:

For any a>0, there must be a right neighbourhood of a containing no members of S (otherwise we could create a decreasing sequence approaching a), i.e. a number b>a such that there are only countably many members of S on the interval \langle a; b\rangle. Assuming that there are uncountably many members of S on the interval \langle a;+\infty) yields a contradiction: just take the supremum* of all c>a s.t. there are only countably many members of S on the interval \langle a; c \rangle and extend the interval a little. Therefore, for any a>0, there is only a countable number of members of S greater than a. But this proves the proposition, as S is the countable union of sets of the form S \cap \langle \frac{1}{n} ; \infty).

edit: * if no such number exists, then S \cap \langle a; \infty) is countable, being a countable union of countable sets.
 
  • #21
Preno said:
How about simply this...

Yup, that's pretty much what we did back there.

Elucidus said:
If one permits the Axiom of Choice, the reals can be well ordered.

Yes, but < is not a well-ordering of the reals.
 
Back
Top