Garth said:
It seems you have no idea what I have been arguing about.
First I agree with everything you said about a local extremum. It is on that fact that there are multiple geodesic paths through curved space-time that the whole paradox depends.
OK, I was also suspecting communications failure, but now that now that we've hopefuly killed and buried the "local vs global" maximum issue, let's move on a bit.
I think, mainly based on past discussions, that what's bothering you ultimately is how you go about explaining the different observations of different observers in terms of Mach's principle.
Personally I don't actually believe in Mach's principle, so I don't explain things in terms of it. But I can make some general comments anyway.
To calculate the proper times of each observer, we just have to integrate dtau along their paths as has been discussed at length.
To calculate dtau, we only need the metric of space-time. So the means to answer the question of "which observer ages the most" is contained purely in the geometry of space-time.
So the route to answer your question is to ask - how is the geometry of space-time (i.e. the metric) determined by the distribution of matter via "Mach's principle"? Knowing how the metric is determined, we can then determine which observer has the greatest elapsed time, which is a purely geometric question about space-time.
The problem with this formulation is that its difficult, except in a very general way, to describe the distribution of matter in space-time without a metric. (And if you have a metric, it pre-determines the distribution of matter!).
For very simple problems one can get a lot of mileage out of symmetry, and an "equation of state". One assumes, for instance, a spherically symmetrical planet, and then some "equation of state" for the matter in it.
In standard GR, we need only pressure vs density as the "equation of state". I'm really not sure what SCC needs in addition (if anything) - I mention it mainly because I'm pretty sure it's on your mind, and needed for you to answer the question.
So given symmetry (a spherically symmetric planet) and an equation of state, what else do we need to solve Einstein's equations? We need boundary conditions - usually asymptotic flatness of space-time at infinity. This also gets rid of "gravitational radiation" issues, any such gravitational raditionis included in the boundary condtions. For the spherically symmetric planet case, we already know that the boundary conditions we want (asymptotic flatness, no gravitational radiation) are going to yield a Schwarzschild solution outside the planet.
This is a very messy problem, but you only want to do it in "weak fields". Without SCC, we can ignore the pressure terms and think of gravity as only being due to density. This let's us get rid of pressure altogether, except as it affects the density profile. We basically get Newtonian gravity. Following through, we get the calculation I did much earlier in the thread
You'll have to add in additional terms in SCC as needed, or higher order terms.
This gives a rather interesting result that the times are almost exactly the same. The result is so close that we start to have to worry about the equation of state to be able to answer the question - i.e. we actually need to know the density vs depth profile of our planet to be able to tell which observer has the longest time.
If the planet were of totally uniform density, the effects all cancel out to the first order. Since I haven't consistenly included all second order effects, I can't say for sure what happens to the second order.
I'm not totally confident, but based on the Virial theorem analysis, I believe that if the planet has a dense core, the observer that "bobs" will wind up with a longer proper time than the observer who stays still, because he will gain more by leaving the potential well than he will lose from his velocity.
I suspect you may be looking for "short-cuts" from the above rather involved approach, but I don't see how you are going to pull it off and guarantee accurate answers. Given the first-order cancellation of effects, I think the problem really is as hard as I'm making it out to be.
.