- 14,922
- 28
For each ordinal number i, recurisively define:
<br /> \begin{equation*}\begin{split}<br /> Z_0 = \{ \varnothing \} \\<br /> Z_i = (\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j) \cup \mathcal{P}(\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j)<br /> \end{split}\end{equation*}<br />
Definition: A set S is a Z-set iff there is an ordinal i such that S \in Z_i.
Definition: For any Z-set S, define the "birthday function" B(S) to be the least ordinal i such that S \in Z_i.
The class of Z-sets is an interesting class...
First, notice that i < j \implies Z_i \subseteq Z_j.
Suppose x and y are Z-sets. Let i = B(x) and j = B(y). Let k be the maximum of i and j. Clearly x and y are both in Z_k. Therefore, \{x, y\} \in Z_{k+1}.
Suppose S is any set of Z-sets. Let k = \bigcup_{s \in S} B(s). (Recall that ordinal numbers in ZF are sets, and you can union a collection of ordinals to obtain an ordinal larger than any in the collection) All of the elements of S are in Z_k, therefore S \in Z_{k+1}.
It is vacuously true that if S is any set in Z_0, then any s in S is an element of Z_0.
Let i be an ordinal number. Suppose that for all j < i, we have that for any S \in Z_j we have \forall s \in S: s \in Z_j.
Let S \in Z_i. If S \in Z_j for some j < i, then by our hypothesis, \forall s \in S: s \in Z_j \subseteq Z_i. The only other possibility is that S \in \mathcal{P}(\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j}. Therefore, S \subseteq \bigcup_{j < i}Z_j, and therefore \forall s \in S, \exists j < i: s \in Z_j \subseteq Z_i.
Therefore, \forall S \in Z_i: \forall s \in S: s \in Z_i.
By the principle of transfinite induction, this statement must be true:
For any ordinal i and any set S in Z_i, every element of S is in Z_i.
In other words, if S is a Z-set, then every element of S is a Z-set.
Furthermore, if S \in Z_i, we have \forall s \in S: s \subseteq Z_i, so \bigcup S \subseteq Z_i, therefore \bigcup S \in Z_{i+1}.
So what have we proven?
If x and y are Z-sets, then {x, y} is a Z-set.
If x is a Z-set, then the sumset of x is a Z-set.
If x is a Z-set, then the powerset of x is a Z-set.
Also, it is clear that \varnothing \in Z_0 and \mathcal{N} \in Z_\mathcal{N} (where I'm using the typical set-theoretic version of the natural numbers)
(In fact, for any ordinal i, i \in Z_i)
This looks a lot like the axioms of the pair set, the sum set, the power set, the empty set, and the axiom of infinity! It seems that the class of Z-sets coincides with the class of sets guaranteed to exist by the axioms of Zermelo set theory!
Is that cool or what?
<br /> \begin{equation*}\begin{split}<br /> Z_0 = \{ \varnothing \} \\<br /> Z_i = (\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j) \cup \mathcal{P}(\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j)<br /> \end{split}\end{equation*}<br />
Definition: A set S is a Z-set iff there is an ordinal i such that S \in Z_i.
Definition: For any Z-set S, define the "birthday function" B(S) to be the least ordinal i such that S \in Z_i.
The class of Z-sets is an interesting class...
First, notice that i < j \implies Z_i \subseteq Z_j.
Suppose x and y are Z-sets. Let i = B(x) and j = B(y). Let k be the maximum of i and j. Clearly x and y are both in Z_k. Therefore, \{x, y\} \in Z_{k+1}.
Suppose S is any set of Z-sets. Let k = \bigcup_{s \in S} B(s). (Recall that ordinal numbers in ZF are sets, and you can union a collection of ordinals to obtain an ordinal larger than any in the collection) All of the elements of S are in Z_k, therefore S \in Z_{k+1}.
It is vacuously true that if S is any set in Z_0, then any s in S is an element of Z_0.
Let i be an ordinal number. Suppose that for all j < i, we have that for any S \in Z_j we have \forall s \in S: s \in Z_j.
Let S \in Z_i. If S \in Z_j for some j < i, then by our hypothesis, \forall s \in S: s \in Z_j \subseteq Z_i. The only other possibility is that S \in \mathcal{P}(\bigcup_{j < i} Z_j}. Therefore, S \subseteq \bigcup_{j < i}Z_j, and therefore \forall s \in S, \exists j < i: s \in Z_j \subseteq Z_i.
Therefore, \forall S \in Z_i: \forall s \in S: s \in Z_i.
By the principle of transfinite induction, this statement must be true:
For any ordinal i and any set S in Z_i, every element of S is in Z_i.
In other words, if S is a Z-set, then every element of S is a Z-set.
Furthermore, if S \in Z_i, we have \forall s \in S: s \subseteq Z_i, so \bigcup S \subseteq Z_i, therefore \bigcup S \in Z_{i+1}.
So what have we proven?
If x and y are Z-sets, then {x, y} is a Z-set.
If x is a Z-set, then the sumset of x is a Z-set.
If x is a Z-set, then the powerset of x is a Z-set.
Also, it is clear that \varnothing \in Z_0 and \mathcal{N} \in Z_\mathcal{N} (where I'm using the typical set-theoretic version of the natural numbers)
(In fact, for any ordinal i, i \in Z_i)
This looks a lot like the axioms of the pair set, the sum set, the power set, the empty set, and the axiom of infinity! It seems that the class of Z-sets coincides with the class of sets guaranteed to exist by the axioms of Zermelo set theory!
Is that cool or what?