Black hole at the beginning of time

In summary: There are multiple interpretations of what "the underlying observer" might be, and it's a bit of a philosophical question. It's... complicated. There are multiple interpretations of what "the underlying observer" might be, and it's a bit of a philosophical question.
  • #36
cianfa72 said:
Is the reverse also true ?
No. One could have a preferred direction (i.e., lack of isotropy) in a homogeneous spacetime, as long as the preferred direction was the same everywhere.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
PAllen said:
The converse is false. Consider the simple example of a two cylinder - no point or small region is distinguishable from any other, so you have homogeneity. However, it is nowhere isotropic, as there is everywhere a distinguishable direction.
In this example the 'preferred/distinguishable' direction is that in which the curvature is null, I believe.
 
  • #38
cianfa72 said:
In this example the 'preferred/distinguishable' direction is that in which the curvature is null, I believe.
A simple example is the idealised uniform gravitational field. You have a homogeneous gravitational field (the same everyone), but a common direction of gravitational force.

A geometric example is the surface of an infinite cylinder. Every point is the same, but there's always a circumferencial direction and a longitudinal direction. So, homogeneous but not isotropic.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #39
PeroK said:
A geometric example is the surface of an infinite cylinder. Every point is the same, but there's always a circumferential direction and a longitudinal direction. So, homogeneous but not isotropic.
ok, so the condition of isotropy everywhere (that implies homogeneity everywhere) does mean the spatial curvature everywhere on each spacelike hypersurface point has to be constant. Hence the 3 allowed geometries with constant positive, null or negative curvature, namely spherical, flat or hyperbolic spatial geometry in each spatial slices.
 
  • #40
cianfa72 said:
ok, so the condition of isotropy everywhere (that implies homogeneity everywhere)
A non-rigorous argument of the contrapositive (that inhomogenity implies anisotropy) is:

If points ##A## and ##B## are different, then we have anisotropy for a point midway between ##A## and ##B##. That should at least help remember which way round the implication goes!
 
  • #41
cianfa72 said:
In this example the 'preferred/distinguishable' direction is that in which the curvature is null, I believe.
No. Curvature is zero everywhere on a cylinder, and curvature doesn't have a "direction".

The "preferred" direction on the cylinder is the one in which the geodesics are closed circles.
 
  • Like
Likes cianfa72
  • #42
PeterDonis said:
No. Curvature is zero everywhere on a cylinder, and curvature doesn't have a "direction".
Ah yes, the 'extrinsic' curvature of a cylinder does not matter.
 
Last edited:
  • #43
PeterDonis said:
The "preferred" direction on the cylinder is the one in which the geodesics are closed circles.
So the 'preferred' direction on the cylinder is actually matter of topology.
 
  • #44
cianfa72 said:
So the 'preferred' direction on the cylinder is actually matter of topology.
No. Geodesics are not a matter of topology; you need to have a metric to know which curves are geodesics.
 
  • #45
PeterDonis said:
No. Geodesics are not a matter of topology; you need to have a metric to know which curves are geodesics.
Sure, however on the cylinder the metric is flat then from a metric point of view all geodesics are indistinguibile. It is the topology that picks a preferred direction.
 
  • #46
cianfa72 said:
on the cylinder the metric is flat then from a metric point of view all geodesics are indistinguibile.
No, they aren't. Geodesics go in different directions and can be distinguished that way. In fact, without a metric you don't even have a well-defined concept of "direction" to begin with (since you need a metric for angles as well as lengths), so it's not clear that you can define what isotropy means.

cianfa72 said:
It is the topology that picks a preferred direction.
The topology certainly is one factor, since it is what makes one particular set of geodesics closed curves. But you also need the metric to know that they are geodesics (as well as to define the concept of "direction", as above).
 
  • Like
Likes cianfa72
  • #47
So we can say both (metric and topology) are actually needed in order to define isotropy.
 
Last edited:
  • #48
PeterDonis said:
The assumption, stated in an invariant way, is that the spacetime can be foliated by spacelike 3-surfaces that are all homogeneous and isotropic. This of course implies that one can choose a coordinate chart in which each such 3-surface is a surface of constant coordinate time.
ok, it is simple as defining a function of spacetime (i.e. the coordinate time function ##t##) such that its level sets are the given spacelike hypersurfaces (3-surfaces) foliating the spacetime.

PeterDonis said:
I believe that the existence of a family of timelike worldlines that is orthogonal to the above spacelike 3-surfaces can also be derived from the above assumption. This then implies that the metric in above coordinate chart
So, as far as I can understand, the above chart is the one that assigns constant spatial coordinates to each worldline in the family of timelike worldlines orthogonal to the given family of spacelike hypersurfaces and as timelike coordinate the coordinate time function ##t##.
 
  • #49
cianfa72 said:
it is simple as defining a function of spacetime (i.e. the coordinate time function ) such that its level sets are the given spacelike hypersurfaces (3-surfaces) foliating the spacetime.
Yes.

cianfa72 said:
the above chart is the one that assigns constant spatial coordinates to each worldline in the family of timelike worldlines orthogonal to the given family of spacelike hypersurfaces and as timelike coordinate the coordinate time function ##t##.
A chart whose coordinate time ##t## behaves as above does not have to assign constant spatial coordinates to each worldline that is orthogonal to the spacelike hypersurfaces of constant ##t##. There are an infinite number of possible charts with the same coordinate time ##t##. But there is a unique such chart that does assign constant spatial coordinates to each worldline that is orthogonal to the spacelike hypersurfaces of constant ##t##; that is the standard FRW chart used in cosmology.
 
  • #50
PeterDonis said:
There are an infinite number of possible charts with the same coordinate time ##t##. But there is a unique such chart that does assign constant spatial coordinates to each worldline that is orthogonal to the spacelike hypersurfaces of constant ##t##; that is the standard FRW chart used in cosmology.
Actually, strictly speaking, I believe there is a complete family of such charts since we can just continuously remap the values of spatial coordinates assigned to each of the worldlines orthogonal to the spacelike hypersurfaces of constant ##t## by adding the same constant to the old values assigned to them.
 
Last edited:
  • #51
cianfa72 said:
strictly speaking, there is a complete family of such charts since we can just continuously remap the values of spatial coordinates assigned to each of the worldlines orthogonal to the spacelike hypersurfaces of constant by adding the same constant to the old values assigned to them.
You can do that for the flat and open cases (i.e., zero and negative curvature), yes. For the closed case (positive curvature), the handling of the spatial part of the chart has to be somewhat different (strictly speaking, there can't be a single chart covering all of a spacelike 3-surface since an n-sphere can't be covered by a single chart).

More generally, there are of course a variety of transformations you can apply to the spatial part of the chart in any FRW spacetime, without changing the property that comoving worldlines have constant spatial coordinates in the chart. So yes, in that sense no chart is truly unique.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and cianfa72
  • #52
PeterDonis said:
You can do that for the flat and open cases (i.e., zero and negative curvature), yes.
Ah ok, so for FRLW open cases there exist actually a global chart for the entire spacetime.
 
  • #53
cianfa72 said:
for FRLW open cases there exist actually a global chart for the entire spacetime
For the flat and open cases (i.e., the ones with infinite spacelike 3-surfaces), yes.
 
  • Like
Likes cianfa72
  • #54
PeroK said:
A non-rigorous argument of the contrapositive (that inhomogenity implies anisotropy) is:

If points ##A## and ##B## are different, then we have anisotropy for a point midway between ##A## and ##B##. That should at least help remember which way round the implication goes!
If I understand your arguments right the point is that you assume that the space is isotropic around any of its points. Only then follows homogeneity. If it's isotropic only around one point it's not necessarily homogeneous (e.g., "Schwarzschild spacetime").
 
  • #55
vanhees71 said:
If I understand your arguments right the point is that you assume that the space is isotropic around any of its points. Only then follows homogeneity. If it's isotropic only around one point it's not necessarily homogeneous (e.g., "Schwarzschild spacetime").
The argument is that if it's not homogeneous then it can't be isotropic. This is logically equivalent to if it's isotropic then it must be homogeneous.

It's called the law of contraposition.
 
  • #56
PeterDonis said:
For the flat and open cases (i.e., the ones with infinite spacelike 3-surfaces), yes.
ok, so for the FLRW hyperbolic case (i.e. family of spacelike hypersurfaces homogeneous and isotropic each with a different constant negative curvature) the global chart described above is such that worldlines of comoving geodesic congruence are 'at rest' in it however the global chart itself is not inertial since the congruence is not 'rigid' (i.e. there is tidal gravity since the distance between comoving worldlines does change).
 
Last edited:
  • #57
PeroK said:
The argument is that if it's not homogeneous then it can't be isotropic. This is logically equivalent to if it's isotropic then it must be homogeneous.

It's called the law of contraposition.
This I don't understand intuitively. Situations, where the system is isotropic wrt. one point but not homogeneous just because of singling out this one point, are very common. Just take the situation of Schwarzschild spacetime. There you have a spherically symmetric star, and spacetime is isotropic around the center of the star but not homogeneous.

What's meant in cosmological principle is that space for a "standard observer" is isotropic around any point. Then space is necessarily both homogeneous and isotropic.

In Weinberg, Gravitation and Cosmology there's also a nice formal discussion analyzing symmetries of Riemannian spaces (Killing vectors) confirming this: If a space is istropic around all of its points it's also homogeneous.
 
  • #58
vanhees71 said:
In Weinberg, Gravitation and Cosmology there's also a nice formal discussion analyzing symmetries of Riemannian spaces (Killing vectors) confirming this: If a space is istropic around all of its points it's also homogeneous.
Yes, a formal proof to show that for any manifold isotropy implies homogeneity is not going to be easy (and it's perhaps not even easy to see why this might be true). The logically equivalent contrapositive (non-homogeneity implies anisotropy) is, however, easier to justify. To construct a formal proof would still require precise definitions of a manifold and the properties in question.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #59
PeroK said:
a formal proof to show that for any manifold isotropy implies homogeneity
Is impossible as you state it here since, as @vanhees71 has correctly pointed out, isotropy about only one point does not imply homogeneity. Off the top of my head I'm not sure what the minimum number of points is at which isotropy is required, in order for homogeneity to be necessarily implied.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #60
cianfa72 said:
so for the FLRW hyperbolic case (i.e. family of spacelike hypersurfaces homogeneous and isotropic each with a different constant negative curvature) the global chart described above is such that worldlines of comoving geodesic congruence are 'at rest' in it
Yes.

cianfa72 said:
however the global chart itself is not inertial since the congruence is not 'rigid' (i.e. there is tidal gravity since the distance between comoving worldlines does change).
No global chart in any curved spacetime can be inertial.
 
  • Like
Likes cianfa72
  • #61
PeterDonis said:
Is impossible as you state it here since, as @vanhees71 has correctly pointed out, isotropy about only one point does not imply homogeneity.
It's clear from the context that "isotropic" means isotropic at every point. That must be the default terminology in any case.
 
  • #62
Well, it's obvious that isotropy around only one point is not enough. It's however also pretty intuitive that isotropy around all points implies homogeneity (but not the other way, i.e., homogeneity does not imply isotropy around any point). Weinberg's definitions and proofs in Gravitation and Cosmology (Chpt. 13) is also not too difficult to follow.
 
  • #63
PeterDonis said:
No global chart in any curved spacetime can be inertial.
Yes that's is true in general, in the particular case of chart described in #56 the reason behind it should be that pointed out there, I believe.
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
29
Views
291
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
11
Views
697
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
4
Views
180
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
4
Views
387
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
2
Views
830
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
23
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
57
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
67
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
5
Views
538
Back
Top