Chapter 4: The Boundary Problem for Experiencing Subjects

  • Thread starter hypnagogue
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Boundary
In summary, Rosenberg explores alternatives to physicalism for understanding p-consciousness and develops a version of Liberal Naturalism, which sees nature as composed of one type of ontological 'stuff' that is not all physical. He argues that this framework is more methodologically conservative and ontologically radical than physicalism. He also discusses how previous proponents of this view, such as Whitehead and Russell, have not gone far enough in their revisions. Rosenberg aims to solve fundamental problems and paradoxes surrounding p-consciousness, starting with the boundary problem, which deals with the individuation of experiencing subjects in nature.
  • #1
hypnagogue
Staff Emeritus
Science Advisor
Gold Member
2,285
3
Liberal Naturalism

Having rejected physicalism as a viable ontological framework in which to house p-consciousness, Rosenberg now begins the task of exploring possible alternatives. He will not investigate substance dualism; rather, he will seek to develop a version of Liberal Naturalism, which holds that nature is composed of only one kind of ontological 'stuff,' and that not all aspects of this stuff are physical.

As an opening remark, Rosenberg notes that, insofar as physicalist views introduce "anomolous standards of explanation" for p-consciousness (see chapter 3) in order to avoid rejecting the prevailing metaphysical paradigm, such views are ontologically conservative at the expense of being methodologically radical. In contrast, a Liberal Naturalist bears no strong prior commitments to a given metaphysic, and believes that our highest priority as theory makers should be to achieve a natural and rigorous account of p-consciousness and its place in nature. Thus, a Liberal Naturalist is methodologically conservative at the expense of being ontologically radical. As Rosenberg puts it, "One might suggest that Liberal Naturalism is metaphysics in the service of explanation, whereas physicalism is explanation in service to metaphysics" (pg. 78).

Rosenberg's Liberal Naturalist framework will be a variant of views that have been put forth before, notably by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell, and more recently endorsed by philosophers such as David Chalmers, Michael Lockwood, Galen Strawson, and Thomas Nagel. Nagel's depiction of this view as quoted in the text is eloquent enough to bear repeating in full:

It may be that the physical description of the brain states associated with consciousness is an incomplete account of their essence-- that it is merely the outside view of what we recognize from within as conscious experience. If anything like that is true, then our present conceptions of mind and body are radically inadequate to the reality, and do no provide us with adequate tools for a priori reasoning about them.1

Although the view that physical phenomena have contents or inner aspects related to experience appears promising, Rosenberg argues that those who have endorsed it in the past have not gone far enough. They have treated the view more as an amendment to physicalism rather than a thorough revision, and as Rosenberg works to flesh out his Liberal Naturalist view more fully throughout the book, he makes the case that nothing less than a thorough revision of our theories on how nature works (in particular, how causation works) will be sufficient to find a home for subjective experience.

To guide his investigation over the next few chapters, Rosenberg will draw out those issues and problems surrounding p-consciousness which pose fundamental challenges and paradoxes to our understanding of experience and its relationship to the greater world. In so doing, he aims to discover more precisely the ways in which our current understanding of the world is inadequate, which will in turn crucially inform the shape of his particular Liberal Naturalist theory. Properly constructed, the new theory's metaphysical outlook and explanitory power should then be able to address these paradoxes directly and dissolve them into tractable problems with satisfactory solutions. Rosenberg will meet this challenge in the second half of the book.

Because Rosenberg is in search of a new fundamental understanding of nature, the sort of problems he will consider here will not be ones that challenge our high level notions of mind, or other cognitive phenomena of the sort that might be studied by cognitive science or neuroscience. (Such problems are important and will be addressed eventually in Rosenberg's framework, but will not be suitable for motivating the fundamental shape of his Liberal Naturalist theory.) Rather, the problems considered will be of a more fundamental sort, problems that strike at the very heart of how we view nature in general. The first such problem that Rosenberg considers is the boundary problem.

The Boundary Problem

We begin discussion of the boundary problem with some observations that Rosenberg takes to be uncontentious. These are:

1) Experiencing subjects (such as you and I) come in discrete units. Each 'unit' of experience contains a dynamic field of phenomenal events that are somehow naturally unified to constitute the subject.

2) The phenomenal field of an experiencing subject has boundaries. For instance, a boundary belongs to both your and my phenomenal fields, such that you do not experience my pains and I do not experience yours.

2.5) Together, the boundedness and unity of the phenomenal field make for a sort of inherent, natural individuation for experiencing subjects. Without these twin aspects of boundedness and unity, nothing like a human experiencing subject could exist. (Rosenberg states this immediately following his second observation, but I think it's important enough in the context of the discussion to come to merit its own listing here.)

3) Human consciousness is only a particular instance of the more general concept of an experiencing subject. Other kinds of subjects with experiences vastly different from humans might exist.

4) Human consciousness is tied to the physical body and its cognitive processes, which exist at a middle level in nature. Individuation at this middle level tends to be highly context sensitive and interest relative in a way that individuation of the world's fundamental microphysical constituents, and the universe as a whole, are not.

5) Various levels of cohesion and organization exist between microphysical phenomena and middle level human cognitive processes, and likewise between human cognition and the universe as a whole.

The task before us is to pull these observations together to account for the boundedness of subjective experience and how it could exist in nature. Why is it that experience is bounded at all, and what aspects of nature support the fact that human p-consciousness is individuated at the middle level in the particular way that it is? If humans' phenomenal fields are tied to their physical bodies, and human p-conscious is individuated at a middle level of nature, then how are the relevant parts of the physical human body likewise individuated at the middle level? These questions form the boundary problem for experiencing subjects.

Because we have no good answer to the boundary problem, our conception of where the boundaries that individuate experiening subjects find their expression in nature is extremely loose. We can draw a virtually arbitrary amount of imaginary boundaries in nature that might support experiencing subjects without fear of contradicting what we otherwise know about the world, and the results of our thought experiments can be surprising, absurd, or even (for the human case) outright false.

For instance, Rosenberg cites various neuroscientific research that seems to indicate that global, synchronous neuronal activity in the cortex plays a role in establishing the boundedness and unity of a human's phenomenal experience. If this is right, might it not be the case that some subsets of this synchronous cortical activity themselves present sufficient conditions to support the existence of experiencing subjects (albeit ones less cognitively complex than, and perhaps of a phenomenal character alien to, the 'full blown' human consciousness with which we are acquainted)? Maybe, maybe not-- we don't appear to have the relevant concepts needed to decide the issue. Although such a situation might appear surprising if it were true, it seems as if we at least have to grant the possibility, given what knowledge and theory we have to work with. (Interestingly, Rosenberg suggests that we may already have empirical evidence from multiple personal disorder studies that a single human brain can support multiple experiencing subjects on the same upper level of cortical organization.)

Rosenberg uses thought experiments in order to show the extent to which our loose concepts pertaining to the boundary problem can be stretched without breaking. For a given cognitive system, it seems coherent to suppose that various subsystems within it are experiencing subjects, but that the system as a whole is not. Likewise, it seems coherent to suppose that both the subsystems and the system as a whole are individual experiencing subjects. There is no ceiling that tells us at what point we should stop attributing subjecthood to larger portions of the system. Extending beyond biological systems, we cannot even rule out the idea that an entire economy might provide the proper kind of causal organization to support the existence of an experiencing subject, even if this strikes us as strange or outright absurd.

If there is no immediate ceiling constraining how high we can potententially attribute experiential subjecthood, there is no immediate floor either. For a cognitive system, we can just as well suppose that the parts are not subjects of experience but that the whole is, e.g. because some (nebulously conceived but often alluded to) point of sufficient complexity has been achieved by the whole but not the parts. But if this were the case, what is to stop us from conceiving of a world where the point of sufficient complexity for experiential subjecthood has been modified? In conjunction with our previous conjectures, we might conceive of a world where the point of sufficient complexity is elevated above the level of complexity exhibited by human brains but below that of the economy. In such a world, humans would not be experiencing subjects, but the economy would.

Rosenberg argues that we can shift the conceptual boundaries across nature so freely because of the way we characterize phenomena at its middle level. We carve up the world at this middle level according to some interest relative, abstract patterns that are extracted from the actual, underlying microphysical phenomena, and there are arbitrarily many of such patterns that are consistent with the same physical/causal circumstances. As a consequence, we wind up with arbitrarily many abstract patterns of organization that present themselves as candidates to support the individuation of experiencing subjects, with sometimes counterintuitive and even bewildering results. It is clear that such interest relative descriptions of the middle level of nature will not do. As Rosenberg says, "We need a natural criterion for individuation, one that illuminates the specialness of some patterns over others as supporters of experience" (pg. 87)-- we need boundaries and unities that are in some sense actually, objectively existent and recognized by nature, not ones created by observors and projected onto nature.

The fundamental microphysical entities of the world, be they particles or strings or something else, appear to be good candidates to play the role of these naturally bounded, actually existent units. But this leaves us with a bootstrapping problem. If microphysical entities provide the boundaries for experiencing subjects, how is it that humans at the middle level of nature, towering far above the level of these microphysical individuals, could be experiencing subjects as well?

Another good suggestion is that natural boundaries flow along the lines of causal interaction in the world, but this leaves us with the problem of halting a runaway process. In this case, it appears as if we cannot ultimately individuate any given phenomena in the visible universe from one another, and we are left with only the universe as a whole as an experiencing subject. Once again, we have not accommodated experiencing subjects at a middle level of nature.

We are not without hope, however. The suggestion that causation grounds natural individuation remains a promising possibility, since if anything meets the criterion of being an inherent organizational feature of nature, it would seem to be causal interaction. But how do we prevent causal interaction from individuating anything smaller than the entire universe? Rosenberg takes Michael Lockwood's words to be suggestive: "quantum mechanics seems to be telling us that it is a classical prejudice to suppose that the world is not intrinsically structured at anything but the level of elementary particles, and their actions and interactions.2" Perhaps a closer analysis of causation in the spirit of Lockwood's observation could suggest ways in which causation actually might provide a basis for natural individuation at the middle level of nature. If so, we would seem to have the makings of a satisfactory response to the boundary problem.

1. Nagel, Thomas. (1998) "Conceiving the Impossible and the Mind-Body Problem." Philosophy 73, no. 285:337-52.

2. Lockwood, Michael. (1993) "The Grain Problem." In Objections to Physicalism, edited by Howard Robinson, 271-91. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I'm afraid I do not understand this part of the book. Is GR saying that at present we have no basis on which to conclude that consciousness is (ontologically) individuated?

Or is he assuming that it is individuated and proposing that causation might provide the mechanism by which this individuation occurs?

Given that he suggests that everything reduces to one substance that is not wholly physical, is he suggesting that causation occurs both physically and non-physically, and/or that in the final analyis nothing is ontologically individuated? Sorry if I'm being dense.
 
  • #3
Canute said:
I'm afraid I do not understand this part of the book. Is GR saying that at present we have no basis on which to conclude that consciousness is (ontologically) individuated?

He is saying that the first person evidence shows us that experience is an individuated phenomenon, and further that this individuation is not an arbitrary construct, but rather seems to be an inherent feature of nature.

Or is he assuming that it is individuated and proposing that causation might provide the mechanism by which this individuation occurs?

He doesn't assume experience is individuated, he concludes it based on first person evidence. If experience is inherently individuated (as demonstrated from the first person) and if experience is integrally tied to physical phenomena (as demonstrated from third person neuroscientific data), then we need to find some objective basis for the inherent individuation of the former in the inherent individuation of some phenomena in the latter. For instance, if certain synchronous neural activity is causally related with the boundedness of experience, we need to find what is special about that neural activity such that it provides the basis for an inherent individuation that is recognized by / makes a causal difference to nature.

Given that he suggests that everything reduces to one substance that is not wholly physical, is he suggesting that causation occurs both physically and non-physically, and/or that in the final analyis nothing is ontologically individuated? Sorry if I'm being dense.

He will make the case in the second half of the book for some non-physical aspects of causation. Ultimately he will use the non-physical aspects of causation to provide the conditions for inherent individuation in nature.
 
  • #4
Hmm. Many people find that first-person experience leads them to conclude that consciousness is not individuated, or at least is only individuated at an everyday human level. Hence for instance Schroedinger's assertion that the apparent plurality of souls is an illusion. But I suppose this is an issue for later. Thanks for the explanation.
 
  • #5
When Rosenberg says consciousness is individuated, he is referring to the unity and boundary conditions on subjective experience (see observations 1 and 2 in the original post). To argue that experience is not individuated in this way, one would have to argue that at least one of these conditions do not hold. But they seem like completely unobjectionable observations to me.

For instance, as I am looking at my computer monitor,
1) the various visual qualities of shape and color that I observe are in some sense integrated into a coherent, unitary experience, and
2) I am certainly not experiencing your own visual experience of what your computer monitor looks like.
In this sense, my visual experience of my computer monitor is individuated as an experiential unit that is distinct from your own unitary experience of your monitor. In what sense might this assertion be arguable?
 
  • #6
As far as it goes it is not arguable. However it might become arguable if GR takes this individuation as holding at a fundamental level. For me this is more or less the same problem that I had on the issue bare differences. I cannot be sure that I agree or disagree because there are loose ends.

This is why I would like to understand more about the metaphysic that underlies these ideas. GR says that Liberal Naturalism does not entail any specific metaphysic, but it seems to me that what he proposes does imply a metaphysic, or at least restrict the choice of metaphysical systems to those that are consistent with LN. I would be much happier working through his detailed arguments, and understand them better, if I had some idea of where he's heading in this respect.

But I can wait. For now I'll go along with him, but with reservations. I'd certainly agree that our consciousness normally appears to be individuated into distinct selves.
 
  • #7
I agree with Nagel (quoted on page 78) that our present conceptions may be radically inadequate to explain the reality of consciousness. I think that my view of consciousness, as the only fundamental entity in existence, is a radical departure from common present conceptions. But I think that hypothesis leads to fairly straightforward answers to all the hard questions.

On page 89 Rosenberg expresses the same objection to Shannon's definition of 'information' as I hold. What is missing is the identification of the entity to whom the difference makes a difference.
 
  • #8
Canute said:
As far as it goes it is not arguable. However it might become arguable if GR takes this individuation as holding at a fundamental level.

That last sentence is a little ambiguous for me to know exactly what you're getting at. He does hold that the individuation of experiencing subjects is not an arbitrary distinction, but an inherent feature of nature, and that our theories of nature will have to account for this inherent individuation somehow.

It would be interesting to see a counterargument or objection to the inherentness of this individuation that does not deny the boundedness and unity of experience, but prima facie, it seems that the boundedness and unity of experience already secure the case for inherent individuation of experiencing subjects.

For me this is more or less the same problem that I had on the issue bare differences. I cannot be sure that I agree or disagree because there are loose ends.

What loose ends do you have in mind?

This is why I would like to understand more about the metaphysic that underlies these ideas. GR says that Liberal Naturalism does not entail any specific metaphysic, but it seems to me that what he proposes does imply a metaphysic, or at least restrict the choice of metaphysical systems to those that are consistent with LN. I would be much happier working through his detailed arguments, and understand them better, if I had some idea of where he's heading in this respect.

Obviously Liberal Naturalism is not consistent with, say, physicalism. But there are really a wide range of ontologies that are consistent with the basic tenets that nature is composed of only one kind of 'stuff,' and that physicalism is not a satisfactory or complete description of this 'stuff.' For instance, even in this chapter we see reference to ontologies by eg Lockwood that reject physicalism, complementing its extrinsic structures with some kind of intrinsic aspects. Rosenberg rejects such proposals because he does not think they satisfactorily address the boundary problem. But both Lockwood's proposal and the one Rosenberg will develop in the book are forms of Liberal Naturalism.

If you are interested in a more detailed, overarching view of where this is headed, there are several summaries in the "Forum Guidelines" thread. You may also want to read http://ai.uga.edu/~ghrosenb/1998_Tucson_Paper.htm , which is essentially a broad overview of Rosenberg's thesis derived from a talk he gave at the 1998 Tucson conference.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #9
I'd like to get more of a pulse on how all the participants view this chapter. Are the observations and arguments here more or less uncontroversial? Do we agree that the boundary problem is a serious problem that must be accounted for by any theory of consciousness, be it a physicalist one or not?
 
  • #10
It seems, from the given data, that the physicalist explanation of the apparent boundedness of experience lies in the connectedness of different parts of the brain. We talk about having "selves" because, as of right now, every part of our brain can share information with the part responsible for making these reports. We run into different cases, however, when we consider persons that have undergone a hemispheric separation procedure, in which there now seems to be at least distinct experiencing subjects in the brain, one that forms verbal reports, and one that forms other kinds of reports. In principle, it seems possible to further break down the brain into even more distinct subjects of experience by further separation, although at some point the brain will cease to function, as there is a certain threshold connectedness necessary for any information-processing to take place at all. So if the question is why do we normal humans with intact connected brains seem to be distinct subjects of experience? Then physicalism answers tentatively by saying it is because that is the highest level at which the individual information-processing parts of the brain can communicate with one another neuronally. Wire together two separate brains and perhaps it would be possible to merge two subjects of experience into one.
 
  • #11
hypnagogue said:
That last sentence is a little ambiguous for me to know exactly what you're getting at. He does hold that the individuation of experiencing subjects is not an arbitrary distinction, but an inherent feature of nature, and that our theories of nature will have to account for this inherent individuation somehow.

It would be interesting to see a counterargument or objection to the inherentness of this individuation that does not deny the boundedness and unity of experience, but prima facie, it seems that the boundedness and unity of experience already secure the case for inherent individuation of experiencing subjects.
People who research into consciousness directly tend to conclude that the individuation of human consciousness is in a sense an illusion. That is, they conclude that ordinary human consciousness is epiphenomenal on something that is not individuated but is (roughly speaking) an undifferentiated continuum. After all, GR himself argues that there is only one substance. If so then it cannot be differentiated for reasons that Leibnitz gives. (Something that is one thing cannot have physical extension etc)

Here are some brief counterarguments, or counter-opinions anyway . I've posted a number of them to show that the argument can be made from various different perspectives. Sorry if it's too much. (I don't wish to argue about this here, just point out that the ontological individuation of consciousness is an assumption, one which many people would not accept, and certainly not a known fact.)

"The implied Unicity, the totality of undivided mind, is itself a concept of its own division or duality, for relatively – relativity being relative to what itself is – it cannot be conceived or known at all.

All that could ever be known about it is simply that, being Absolute, it must necessarily be devoid of any kind of objective existence whatsoever, other than that of the totality of all possible phenomena which constitute its relative appearance."

Wu Wu Wei
In Ramesh Balsekar
The Ultimate Understanding

"The world may not only be more singular than we think, it may be more singular than we can think. "

Robert Kaplan
The Nothing That Is -
A Natural History of Zero
Penguin, London (1999) (p 160)

"[t]he attributes "subject" and "object," "represented" and "representative," "thing" and "thought" mean then a practical distinction of the utmost importance, but a distinction which is of a FUNCTIONAL order only, and not at all ontological as understood by classical dualism."

William James
"The Notion of Consciousness."
In The Writings of William James, ed. John J. McDermott.
University of Chicago Press (1905/1977) (p193)

"For the ‘reductionist’ view can be sustained only if it is realized that both the resulting parts, physical and mental, are of our own making. Faced with a dynamic and ongoing continuum of awareness which it is not equipped to comprehend in its entirety, our intellect seeks to reduce this continuum to apprehensible pieces, selecting certain aspects on which to focus and arranging these according to formats of its own. Just as a seascape artist finds difficulty in capturing their fluid subject and is obliged to frame and arrest that which they seek to portray, so our intellect seeks to apprehend piecemeal that which is essentially whole and continuous. But a continuum cannot be so fragmented."

George Dupenois
‘Mind, Matter and Reality’
The Philosopher, Vol. LXXXVIII No. 1

"It is, I suspect, only in a nineteenth-century social science that the abstraction of the dialectics of opposites could have been established. This also applies to the observer’s properties.…There is mutual reflection between describer and description. But here again we have been used to taking these terms as opposites: observer/observed, subject/object as Hegelian pairs. From my point of view, these poles are not effectively opposed, but moments of a larger unity that sits on a metalevel with respect to both terms."

F. J. Varela
‘Principles of Biological Autonomy’ (1979 p. 101).
In Some-Thing from No-Thing: G. Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form http://www.angelfire.com/super/magicrobin/lof.htm


"Emptiness should be understood in the context of dependent arising and it should evoke a sense of fullness, of things created by causes and conditions. We should not think that the self is something that was originally there and can be eliminated through meditation. In fact, the self is something that never existed in the first place."

Tenzin Gyatso
The Dalai Lama
The Little Book of Buddhism
Compiled and edited Renuka Singh
Rider, London 2000 (p138)

"How does the idea of plurality (so emphatically opposed by the Upanishad writers) arise at all? Consciousness finds itself intimately connected with, and dependent on, the physical state of a limited region of matter, the body… Now, there is a great plurality of similar bodies. Hence the pluralisation of consciousness or minds seems a very suggestive hypothesis. Probably all simple ingenious people, as well as the great majority of western philosophers, have accepted it.

It leads almost immediately to the invention of souls, as many as there are bodies, and to the question whether they are mortal as the body is or whether they are immortal and capable of existing by themselves. The former alternative is distasteful, while the latter frankly forgets, ignores, or disowns the facts upon which the plurality hypothesis rests. Much sillier questions have been asked: Do animals also have souls? It has even been questioned whether women, or only men, have souls.

Such consequences, even if only tentative, must make us suspicious of the plurality hypothesis, which is common to all official western creeds. Are we not inclining to much greater nonsense if in discarding their gross superstitions, we retain their naïve idea of pluraity of souls, but "remedy" it be declaring the souls to be perishable, to be annihilated with the respective bodies?

The only possible alternative is simply to keep the immediate experience that consciousness is a singular of which the plural is unknown; that there is only one thing and that, what seems to be a plurality, is merely a series of different aspects of this one thing, produced by a deception (the Indian MAYA); the same illusion is produced in a gallery of mirrors, and in the same way Gaurisankar and Mt. Everest turned out to be the same peak, seen from different valleys...

...Yet each of us has the undisputable impression that the sum total of his own experience and memeory forms a unit, quite distinct from that of any other person. He refers to it as "I". What is this "I"?

If you analyse it closely, you will, I think, find that it is just a little bit more than a collection of single data (experiences and memories), namely, the canvas upon which they are collected. And you will, on close introspection, find that what you really mean by "I," is that ground-stuff on which they are collected. You may come to a distant country, lose sight of all your friends, may all but forget them; you acquire new friends, you share life with them as intensely as you ever did with your old ones. Less and less important will become the fact that, while living your new life, you still recollect the old one. "The youth that I was," you may come to speak of him in the third person; indeed, the protagonist of the novel you are reading is probably nearer to your heart, certainly more intensely alive and better known to you. Yet there has been no intermediate braak, no death. And even if a skilled hypnotist succeeded in blotting out entirely all your earlier reminiscences, you would not find that he had killed you. In no case is there a loss of personal existence to deplore. Nor will there ever be."

Erwin Scrödinger
The I That Is God
In Ken Wilbur
Quantum Questions
(p 93)

A common metaphor for the relation between individuated consciousness and the continuum is that of the waves on the surface of the ocean. In a sense they are differentiated and in a sense not. (Oddly enough I heard actor Richard Gere give this explanation of consciousness in a recent interview).

What loose ends do you have in mind?
Those relating to bare differences already mentioned, (i.e. a quibble about how he distinguishes between quantative and qualitative differences) and those relating to the assumed ontological individuation of consciousness.

On the issue of what metaphysical system GR is heading for I read the link you posted but all he seemed to say there was that LN is inconsistent with physicalism and materialism. My impression, admittedly from only skimming through the book and not understanding all of it, is that he says no more than this. This doesn't matter, my comment was simply that it would have helped me if he had presented his ideas in the context of an overarching metaphysical system.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
loseyourname said:
It seems, from the given data, that the physicalist explanation of the apparent boundedness of experience lies in the connectedness of different parts of the brain.

The neuroscientific data you mention here (also acknowledged by Rosenberg in the text) is surely relevant to the boundary problem, and any theory of consciousness-- physicalist or not-- will need to take it into account. It looks like this data gives us important clues as to what conditions need to be met to constitute an individuated, experiencing subject.

But as far as it goes, such data is only suggestive of what may account for individuation in the specific case of human brains. A theory that comprehensively answers to the boundary problem will provide general principles that account for the individuation of experiencing subjects in any context, and should be able to predict what systems are likely to be experiencing subjects on the basis of these principles.

The fuzzy nature of terms such as 'connectedness' and 'information processing' must be addressed, then, to give a satisfactory answer to the boundary problem. Clearly there is a sense in which the brain is an information processing system that exhibits a high degree of connectedness, but how can we validly extend these terms to other systems? What constitutes the connectedness of the brain, and what (if any) special features of this connectedness are necessary to support an experiencing subject? Are there constraints that must be satisfied, such as the proper kind of physical constitution of the connected parts, or operation over proper kinds of time frames, or constraints on the type of connections, that count as constituting the relevant kind of 'connectedness' exhibited by the brain?

This is where Rosenberg's concerns about observer relative, context sensitive characterizations come in. Suppose, for instance, that we can perfectly model the activity of the brain on a computer. If this is true, we can also perfectly model the activity of the brain on a suitably large abacus over a suitably large time frame. Will the shuffling of abacus beads over centuries eventually add up to a subjective experience of, say, hiking through a forest? What about the observer relative characterization of this system? Perhaps the abacus models a pattern of brain activity of Sam as he hikes through a forest, if we take each bead to represent a particular atom in the brain; but what if we take each bead to represent a quark, or even an entire neuron? Is there any sense in which the abacus system itself will somehow 'recognize' that a certain level of abstract representation of its computing elements is appropriate for modeling a brain, and thereby become an experiencing subject as if its beads really were inherently modeling the appropriate level of abstraction? If so, by what means does this phenomena occur? How does nature 'know' that under certain interpretations of the system, it exhibits behavior isomorphic to a functioning human brain?

It's too early to demand that physicalism, or any theory for that matter, comprehensively answer these questions pertaining to the boundary problem. For now, I am just interested in asserting that these really are problems that need to be contended with. Would you agree that any theory of consciousness, be it couched in physicalism or not, would eventually need to address these questions and come to satisfactory answers?
 
Last edited:
  • #13
hypnagogue said:
It's too early to demand that physicalism, or any theory for that matter, comprehensively answer these questions pertaining to the boundary problem. For now, I am just interested in asserting that these really are problems that need to be contended with. Would you agree that any theory of consciousness, be it couched in physicalism or not, would eventually need to address these questions and come to satisfactory answers?

Yes, of course. Any theory of how experience arises must be able to predict exactly what the threshold conditions are for a given system to be an experiencing system. Physicalist hypotheses do exist to some extent, for example the hypothesis that action potentials sychronized at 40Hz result in an experience of the neuronal arrays in synch. I suspect that whatever turns out to be the most compelling hypothesis will probably prove to be such a parameter of downward causation on a non-linear complex system (again with the fuzzy terminology - they are defined mathematically, but I'm not familiar with the mathematics). This, however, as you point out, is not a theory until it can (1) be confirmed to be the case for neuronal systems and (2) be extended to non-neuronal systems. I don't want to speculate too wildly, but I suspect a large abacus would not suffice. Certainly this particular hypothesis would not posit an abacus as an experiencing system, as an abacus displays no synchronized electrical signals over parts of its bead array.

One good question that could be asked of this hypothesis right now is how it would account for the apparent split of indivuation in the hemispheric separation cases. It isn't my hypothesis and I'm not a professional neuroscientist, so I won't pretend to know the answer, but I suspect this very problem is part of the reason that the 40Hz hypothesis has encountered a good deal of opposition from many in the scientific community.
 
Last edited:
  • #14
hypnagogue said:
Suppose, for instance, that we can perfectly model the activity of the brain on a computer.

Seems to me that a computer is made up of transistors which operate in their linear modes of operations. We'll never model the highly non-linear behavior of a human brain on devices which resemble modern-day computers.

If this is true, we can also perfectly model the activity of the brain on a suitably large abacus over a suitably large time frame. Will the shuffling of abacus beads over centuries eventually add up to a subjective experience of, say, hiking through a forest?

I think it would, expecting the abacus brain to exhibit a marvelously complex array of dynamics which I believe would resemble qualities which if interpreted "broadly" would meet the criteria of a conscious "experience".
 
  • #15
Canute, some of those quotations you provided that mention subject/object distinctions (or lack thereof) seem more pertinent to the relationship between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject than to the boundedness and unity of experiencing subjects. As we've discussed previously, Rosenberg indeed acknowledges that a relationship obtains between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject such that the existence of one already presupposes the existence of the other.

Also, I must again contest your use of the word 'assumption.' An assumption is a claim that is taken for granted to be true, without the benefit of logical or empirical support. Rosenberg very clearly provides reasons for believing that his claims about the individuation of experiencing subject are true. Whether one finds them to be contentious or not, one cannot write them off as assumptions.

In any case, the relevant point about the boundedness and unity of experiencing subjects to take away from this chapter is that these conditions are not arbitrary, but in some sense are actually existent conditions in nature. Recall Rosenberg's discussion of the manner in which we individuate physical phenomena at the middle level of nature:

Typically, our individuation of objects at this middle level of nature is fluid, conext sensitive, and interest relative. It is highly conceptual and hinges on facts about the abstract organization and causal cohesion of physical activity. As a consequence, events or objects may form parts of many individuals simultaneously, depending on how one organizes the world and draws the individuating boundaries. For example, a cell may be an individual; also, at the same time, it may be part of an organ; at the same time, it may be part of an individuated bodily system such as the reproductive system; at the same time, it may be part of the organism as a whole and part of that organism's society; at the same time, it might be part of an ecosystem. (pg. 80-81, emphasis mine)

Note that there does not seem to be any strong sense in which nature privileges a cell's status as an individual in itself, or as merely part of a larger individual. We, as observers, are the ones who draw the conceptual boundaries that determine whether a cell is to be considered as an individual or not.

Contrast this with the manner in which we find ourselves as experiencing subjects to be individuated. We do not decide how to draw the relevant boundaries; in a very real sense, these boundaries are enforced upon us by nature. As a consequence, there must be some sense in which these boundaries are actually existent in and 'recognized by' nature; if they did not enjoy some kind of privileged existence in nature, there would be no mechanism by which they could force themselves upon us.

To accept the inherent boundedness and unity of experience, we need go no further than this. It seems to me that one can believe that experience is inherently individuated in this way and also believe that there is a still more basic, underlying sense in which experience is not individuated (call this belief U). To the extent that I understand your viewpoint and Rosenberg's, I would have to say that the specific framework Rosenberg will go on to develop does not seem to be particularly amenable to U. However, the observations and arguments in this particular chapter do not seem completely incompatible with U, and if one were so inclined, one could probably construct a kind of Liberal Naturalism similar to Rosenberg's that accommodates the 'individuated at one level but unindividuated at another' view.

Having said that, I'm not sure that belief in U rests on very firm footing. The individuation of experience discussed by Rosenberg is a very straightforward observation about the character of our conscious lives, and one is hard pressed to find fault with it. It may be that there are certain meditative practices that lead one to experience a certain all-encompassing unity about nature that seems to transcend the boundaries of normal experience, but it's not clear to me at all that such experiences really dissolve the conditions of boundedness and unity pointed out by Rosenberg. They could very well just be a novel type of phenomenal quality (or a conglomerate thereof) that is nonetheless housed in the same general kind of bounded, unified experiential field that is shared by everyone; for me, this seems like the most likely scenario.
 
Last edited:
  • #16
Hypnagogue said:
To accept the inherent boundedness and unity of experience, we need go no further than this. It seems to me that one can believe that experience is inherently individuated in this way and also believe that there is a still more basic, underlying sense in which experience is not individuated (call this belief U). To the extent that I understand your viewpoint and Rosenberg's, I would have to say that the specific framework Rosenberg will go on to develop does not seem to be particularly amenable to U. However, the observations and arguments in this particular chapter do not seem completely incompatible with U, and if one were so inclined, one could probably construct a kind of Liberal Naturalism similar to Rosenberg's that accommodates the 'individuated at one level but unindividuated at another' view.

Although I know it's bad form to use examples or analogies to talk about abstract concepts, I still need to resort to them, because of my own limitations, so please forgive me. I think it was Plato who used the analogy of music : lyre :: consciousness : human. I would like to update that analogy to a more modern instrument and use it to propose an analog to U, call it U'..

Let's consider this analogy, music : a radio :: consciousness : a living brain.

When the radio is tuned to a station playing, say, a sonata, then in the vicinity of the radio, a performance of the sonata can be heard for some specific duration of time. Thus there is an inherent boundedness to that instance of the performance in space and time. There is also an inherent unity to the performance, as an entity conceived and created by the composer of the sonata. Yet, we in the 21st century know, as Plato or even Newton could not have known, that there is a theory, U', (involving electromagnetism, EM wave propagation, tuned resonant electronic circuits, etc., together with musical instruments played by an orchestra, a tape recording of the orchestra's performance, and a transmitter at a radio station receiving information from a tape player), which adequately explains the phenomenon of that music in the vicinity of the radio at that time.

According to U', there is a deeper unity which is represented by the EM field. This field is much more complex and pervasive than the sound of that sonata in that it extends to regions far beyond where that sonata was heard, and it contains the signals from many more radio stations with their own separate but inherently unified programs.

In my view, an explanation for consciousness analogous to radio would be consistent with Liberal Naturalism and could accommodate "the 'individuated at one level but unindividuated at another' view. "

Such a view would also suggest that we should consider the approaches of neurophysiology to be the equivalent of dissecting and examining a radio in order to discover how the sonata sound was produced. Of course, simply by knowing what is going on in the radio, even in complete detail down to the electrons and even the quarks, the cause of the production of the sonata sound could not be discovered. It is my hunch that, just as in the case of the radio, there is vastly more in reality that is involved in the "production" of consciousness than we have access to with our scientific instruments.
 
  • #17
Hypnagogue

Thank you for not throwing up you hands in horror at those quotes. Your response is extremely reasonable, and I half agree with it. However I feel it doesn't quite let GR off the hook for not dealing properly with the individuation issue. Excuse me for chopping up your post but I find it easier to respond that way.

hypnagogue said:
Canute, some of those quotations you provided that mention subject/object distinctions (or lack thereof) seem more pertinent to the relationship between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject than to the boundedness and unity of experiencing subjects.
Perhaps you're right. I can see that some of them could be given that more limited meaning. To me they are all saying the same thing, by implication if not explicitly, but that could be my misinterpretation. This doesn't really matter however. I could post a hundred times that number of quotes expressing the same view by intelligent people from a vast range of disciplines. This would prove nothing about consciousness of course, but it would at least show clearly that virtually everybody who explores consciousness in the first rather than the third person ends up reaching the same conclusion about it. It is up to GR to show that they are wrong, and I do not see where he does this. Rather, it's as if he has never come across this view.

As we've discussed previously, Rosenberg indeed acknowledges that a relationship obtains between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject such that the existence of one already presupposes the existence of the other.
Yes I realize that. But it seems to me he sees this as an epistemilogical issue rather than an ontological one. That is, he does not say that that the existence of one depends on the existence of the other, just that our knowledge of one depends on the knowledge of the other, which is a lesser and uncontentious claim.

Also, I must again contest your use of the word 'assumption.' An assumption is a claim that is taken for granted to be true, without the benefit of logical or empirical support. Rosenberg very clearly provides reasons for believing that his claims about the individuation of experiencing subject are true. Whether one finds them to be contentious or not, one cannot write them off as assumptions.
In my view if one holds a view for which there is no proof then it is an assumption. If one has half a proof it is still an assumption. I do not see where he shows that consciousness is individuated so to me he seeems to assume it. What he writes suggests that he has taken a quick introspective glance and made his mind up. But a quick glance shows that the sun orbits the earth. It appears to me that he has undertaken no research at all into this issue. If he'd even mentioned that there is an alternative view it would have helped.

In any case, the relevant point about the boundedness and unity of experiencing subjects to take away from this chapter is that these conditions are not arbitrary, but in some sense are actually existent conditions in nature. Recall Rosenberg's discussion of the manner in which we individuate physical phenomena at the middle level of nature:
This is why I keep finding myself unsure what he is saying. If he is saying that consciousness appears to be individuated at a particular level, that of ordinary day to day human experience for instance, then I wouldn't have objected, for this is clearly correct. Is this what he is saying? My impression is that his 'middle level of nature' extends across all the other levels on this issue.

Note that there does not seem to be any strong sense in which nature privileges a cell's status as an individual in itself, or as merely part of a larger individual. We, as observers, are the ones who draw the conceptual boundaries that determine whether a cell is to be considered as an individual or not.
This is my very point. The individuation of consciousness is, or at the least may be, conceptual and not fundamental. This is why, to risk another foray into 'mysticism', all 'mystics' advise that the truth about reality cannot be fully understood except non-conceptually. This is closely related to what Wu Wu Wei says in the first of those quotes. All people who say that consciousness is not ultimately individuated also say this.

Contrast this with the manner in which we find ourselves as experiencing subjects to be individuated. We do not decide how to draw the relevant boundaries; in a very real sense, these boundaries are enforced upon us by nature.
Are you quite sure about this? I agree that as we grow up we develop a clear sense that our consciousness has a boundary, on one side of which is 'me' and on the other 'them'. But does this bit of folk-psychology prove anything? It is a view that Schroedinger politely but repeatedly criticised for most of his life and which I and many others would flatly deny. Spencer-Brown, for instance, states that the boundary between 'me' (or you) and the rest of the universe is ultimately illusory, an act of self-reference.

As a consequence, there must be some sense in which these boundaries are actually existent in and 'recognized by' nature; if they did not enjoy some kind of privileged existence in nature, there would be no mechanism by which they could force themselves upon us.
I don't disagree that humans feel the presence of these boundaries. But I think Sartre would have argued that we enforce them on ourselves, albeit unwittingly, and so would Buddhists and all like minded people. This relates to the issue of bare differences. It is argued by many that the difference between me and you is a bare one, a conceptual distinction, an illusion that can be seen through if one troubles to investigate it.

Again I must stress that I'm not trying to convince you on this, just suggesting that this issue is not dealt with adequately by GR. Before ploughing ahead as if it were a fact that consciousness is ontologically or fundamentally individuated into 'selfs' he needs to show that all those who do not agree are wrong.

To accept the inherent boundedness and unity of experience, we need go no further than this. It seems to me that one can believe that experience is inherently individuated in this way and also believe that there is a still more basic, underlying sense in which experience is not individuated (call this belief U). To the extent that I understand your viewpoint and Rosenberg's, I would have to say that the specific framework Rosenberg will go on to develop does not seem to be particularly amenable to U. However, the observations and arguments in this particular chapter do not seem completely incompatible with U, and if one were so inclined, one could probably construct a kind of Liberal Naturalism similar to Rosenberg's that accommodates the 'individuated at one level but unindividuated at another' view.
Here you've expressed the problem clearly. What GR writes is ambiguous, and this is why I am unclear as to his position. It seems to be inconsistent with U, but maybe he intends to say only that C is individuated at a 'middle level' and not at all levels. I cannot decide which, and therefore have to put my reservations on hold until later. When I read the book the first time they were still on hold when I finished it, which is why I'm here.

Having said that, I'm not sure that belief in U rests on very firm footing. The individuation of experience discussed by Rosenberg is a very straightforward observation about the character of our conscious lives, and one is hard pressed to find fault with it. It may be that there are certain meditative practices that lead one to experience a certain all-encompassing unity about nature that seems to transcend the boundaries of normal experience, but it's not clear to me at all that such experiences really dissolve the conditions of boundedness and unity pointed out by Rosenberg. They could very well just be a novel type of phenomenal quality (or a conglomerate thereof) that is nonetheless housed in the same general kind of bounded, unified experiential field that is shared by everyone; for me, this seems like the most likely scenario.
There is no way of demonstrating that U is the case nor of demonstrating that it is not the case. (Note that this does not mean that the truth about it cannot be known). In my view this means that there is no justification for someone who is writing a book on consciousness to ignore the possibility of U as if its falsity was a foregone conclusion. GR expores consciousness in the third-person, so he has no right to comment, even by ommission, on the findings of people who explore it in the first-person, especially since consciousness is a first and not a third person phenomena.

I suppose what I'm expressing here, besides pointing out some ambiguities in GR's argument, is a general annoyance at people who write books on consciousness without ever doing any research into what it actually is while blithely ignoring the extensively documented findings of people who do. If this other view (U - and all its scientific and philosophical implications) is wrong then sooner or later someone is going to have to prove it, otherwise this view must be considered along with all the others, and not just ignored.

If it were a view held by half a dozen crackpots then fair enough, but we're talking about thousands and thousands of apparently intelligent and sane people and an extensive body of self-consistent explanatory literature. One does not have to become a solitary mystic, practice meditation or even abandon reason in order to examine the scientific and philosophical plausibility of this other view through this literature.
 
Last edited:
  • #18
Canute said:
Yes I realize that. But it seems to me he sees this as an epistemilogical issue rather than an ontological one. That is, he does not say that that the existence of one [phenomenal properties] depends on the existence of the other [the experiencing subject], just that our knowledge of one depends on the knowledge of the other, which is a lesser and uncontentious claim.

The analogy he uses for explaining the relationship between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject is the relationship between the front and back of a wall. The front and back of a wall are distinct things, but the existence of one presupposes the other. Clearly this is more of an ontological necessitation rather than an epistemological one. When Rosenberg develops his theory in the second half of the book, the manner in which he treats phenomenal and experiential properties makes it quite explicit that he considers them as ontologically necessitating each other. In his framework, one literally cannot be actually existent without the other.

In my view if one holds a view for which there is no proof then it is an assumption. If one has half a proof it is still an assumption. I do not see where he shows that consciousness is individuated so to me he seeems to assume it.

The proof is in the first person observation. In order to disagree, you would have to introspect your own experience and find that conditions 1) and 2) listed in the original post of this thread do not properly describe it.

This is why I keep finding myself unsure what he is saying. If he is saying that consciousness appears to be individuated at a particular level, that of ordinary day to day human experience for instance, then I wouldn't have objected, for this is clearly correct. Is this what he is saying?

Yes, that is essentially what he is saying. In this chapter, he is concerned with
1) making the observation that human consciousness is individuated at a middle level of nature, in the sense of the word 'individuated' described in the original post;
2) establishing that this individuation is different in important respects from the kind of individuation we impose on physical phenomena at the middle level;
3) analyzing how 1) and 2) come to bear on the problem of reconciling our understanding of consciousness with our understanding of nature.

My impression is that his 'middle level of nature' extends across all the other levels on this issue.

I don't know where you might get that impression. If the term 'middle level of nature' applied to all levels of nature, what would be the point of qualifying it by saying 'middle'?

This is my very point. The individuation of consciousness is, or at the least may be, conceptual and not fundamental.

If the individuation of experiencing subjects were conceptual, then it should be just as fluid and interest relative as the manner in which we individuate, say, a cell. But this is clearly not the case. No amount of reconceptualizing on my part will allow me to subjectively experience what you subjectively experience, for example.

Are you quite sure about this? I agree that as we grow up we develop a clear sense that our consciousness has a boundary, on one side of which is 'me' and on the other 'them'. But does this bit of folk-psychology prove anything?

I don't think it's folk-psychology at all. Are you suggesting that it's just a naive, misguided belief on my part that I cannot directly experience the phenomenal qualities of your own subjective experience? Are you suggesting that if you were brought up another way, you could peer inside my mind and literally experience what I experience?

I don't disagree that humans feel the presence of these boundaries. But I think Sartre would have argued that we enforce them on ourselves, albeit unwittingly, and so would Buddhists and all like minded people. This relates to the issue of bare differences. It is argued by many that the difference between me and you is a bare one, a conceptual distinction, an illusion that can be seen through if one troubles to investigate it.

I highly doubt that this is an illusion that can be seen through with the proper investigation, since (again) that would imply that through the proper investigation, you could come to gain access to my subjective experiences.

Again I must stress that I'm not trying to convince you on this, just suggesting that this issue is not dealt with adequately by GR. Before ploughing ahead as if it were a fact that consciousness is ontologically or fundamentally individuated into 'selfs' he needs to show that all those who do not agree are wrong.

I think you may be operating under a conception different from Rosenberg's as to what is meant by the individuation of consciousness. What do you take this phrase to mean, and is it consistent with the manner in which Rosenberg defines it?

There is no way of demonstrating that U is the case nor of demonstrating that it is not the case. (Note that this does not mean that the truth about it cannot be known). In my view this means that there is no justification for someone who is writing a book on consciousness to ignore the possibility of U as if its falsity was a foregone conclusion.

On page 80, in the section entitled "Overview of the Boundary Problem," Rosenberg says:

Bertrand Russell once said that the aim of philosophy is to start with something so obvious as to not be worth mentioning and to end up with something so absurd that no one will believe it. My development of the boundary problem for experiencing subjects is in the spirit of Russell.

In other words, Rosenberg wishes to start with straightforward, uncontentious claims and see what follows from them. Even if there exists some basis for believing in U, it seems to me that it is not of the straightforward, uncontentious variety.

For instance, even if certain meditative experiences have something valuable to tell us about consciousness, it is rather rare for one to experience such a state for one's self, and consideration of the problems surrounding consciousness should tell us that we cannot rely on verbal reports to convey the full sense of any given experience to others. Even disregarding this problem, we can still come to the conclusion that it is highly unlikely that such experiences are really violations of the boundary conditions Rosenberg establishes in this chapter. In order to qualify as such, the relevant meditative experiences would have to give the meditator access to the subjective experiences of another, or give another direct access to the meditator's own subjective experiences. I do not contest that meditative experiences have what might be described as a certain boundless or unusually unified quality to them, but these senses of the word do not seem to agree with the way in which Rosenberg defines and uses them.

GR expores consciousness in the third-person, so he has no right to comment, even by ommission, on the findings of people who explore it in the first-person, especially since consciousness is a first and not a third person phenomena.

I have to admit that I really am dumbfounded by this assertion. In what sense does Rosenberg explore consciousness from the 3rd person? The whole point of the book is to come up with a theory that simultaneously respects the first person evidence of experience and finds a way to place it seemlessly in nature, without winding up at conceptual tensions or paradoxes. If Rosenberg were exploring consciousness from the 3rd person, this book would just be a sequel to Consciousness Explained, which it most clearly isn't.
 
  • #19
hypnagogue said:
The analogy he uses for explaining the relationship between phenomenal properties and the experiencing subject is the relationship between the front and back of a wall. The front and back of a wall are distinct things, but the existence of one presupposes the other. Clearly this is more of an ontological necessitation rather than an epistemological one.
I appreciate that you're taking Rosenberg's part in this discussion, but are you aware that you're making just the same assumption as he does? Why do you say that a fundamental distinction between observed properties and experiencing subject is an ontological necessity?

When Rosenberg develops his theory in the second half of the book, the manner in which he treats phenomenal and experiential properties makes it quite explicit that he considers them as ontologically necessitating each other. In his framework, one literally cannot be actually existent without the other.
I understand this. I'm suggesting that there is another view which the author needs to discount before he can assume that (ontologically-speaking) these are two different things .

The proof is in the first person observation. In order to disagree, you would have to introspect your own experience and find that conditions 1) and 2) listed in the original post of this thread do not properly describe it.
The disproof is in first-person observation according to the counter-view. We cannot just toss a coin to decide who is right, it requires consideration of the arguments and the evidence.

I don't know where you might get that impression. If the term 'middle level of nature' applied to all levels of nature, what would be the point of qualifying it by saying 'middle'?
You yourself have just said above that the distinction in question obtains at a fundamental level, not just a middle level. In fact you suggested that it is an ontological necessitation. Which of these two views is the one that GR is proposing?

If the individuation of experiencing subjects were conceptual, then it should be just as fluid and interest relative as the manner in which we individuate, say, a cell. But this is clearly not the case. No amount of reconceptualizing on my part will allow me to subjectively experience what you subjectively experience, for example.
I don't know why you say these two things. We know very well that things that are not ontologically individuated can be individuated as epiphenomena, kitchen tables and pianos for instance, or waves on the ocean surface. Your second sentence is true, but the common experience we are discussing here is one of non-conceptualising rather than re-conceptualising, so this is not relevant as an objection.

I don't think it's folk-psychology at all. Are you suggesting that it's just a naive, misguided belief on my part that I cannot directly experience the phenomenal qualities of your own subjective experience? Are you suggesting that if you were brought up another way, you could peer inside my mind and literally experience what I experience?
I called it folk-psychology a bit tongue-in-cheek because Dennett and his ilk would call it that. He argues that experiences are not incorrigible. But no, of course I cannot experience what you experience as an individual being. Pianos and kitchen tables must occupy different spaces if they are to exist. However at the simplest level they are made of the same substance as everything else is made out of, as GR himself argues. By separating them ontologically you're making the assumption that Schroedinger complains about in the extract I quoted.

I highly doubt that this is an illusion that can be seen through with the proper investigation, since (again) that would imply that through the proper investigation, you could come to gain access to my subjective experiences.
This is an oversimplification of 'U', one which robs it of its subtlety. As an objection it is based on the very premise that U holds to be false, namely the ontologically distinct existence of separate selfs. In order to break down this distinction it is necessary, by the logic of the situation, to cease having experiences as a separate self, thus to cease being a separate self. It follows that as separate selves we cannot have each others experiences.

I think you may be operating under a conception different from Rosenberg's as to what is meant by the individuation of consciousness. What do you take this phrase to mean, and is it consistent with the manner in which Rosenberg defines it?
I take 'individuation of consciousness' to mean that there is no fundamental connection between individual consciousnesses. As Rosenberg proposes monism I assume this implies that individual consciousnesses reduce ultimately to some single fundamental substance which is not consciousness.

In other words, Rosenberg wishes to start with straightforward, uncontentious claims and see what follows from them. Even if there exists some basis for believing in U, it seems to me that it is not of the straightforward, uncontentious variety.
It is not an uncontentious claim. I'm contending it. :smile: I cannot show that it is a false claim, and I wouldn't expect you to believe it is one without some evidence, but it's perfectly easy to show that it's contentious. What he means by 'uncontentious' seems to be - less contentious than other claims that he happens to think are more contentious. As consciousness is proving so hard to explain do you not think it might be some fundamental and apparently innocent and uncontentious assumption just like this one that might causing all the trouble?

For instance, even if certain meditative experiences have something valuable to tell us about consciousness, it is rather rare for one to experience such a state for one's self, and consideration of the problems surrounding consciousness should tell us that we cannot rely on verbal reports to convey the full sense of any given experience to others.
This is odd. I find you normally so even-handed. Meditative experiences are just experiences. They can be 'non-ordinary', but only to someone who doesn't ordinarily have them. The are mystical only in that they cannot be reported. Meditation, contemplation, the 'Jesus prayer' that Les Sleeth talks about, in the end they are all about introspection, but with the application of a methodology. Without introspection we wouldn't know we were here let alone conscious.

Certainly we cannot rely on verbal reports. How could I report to you what experiencing hearing my piano sounds like? How is GR is able to conclude that consciousness is experienced as individuated if he has not introspected and has not relied on verbal reports? How we ever going to understand consciousness if introspection and verbal reports are both disallowed?

Also, it seems a little unfair, under the circumstances, to blame proponents of U for the fact that experiences cannot be verbally reported more than very sketchily, or for the fact that such reports cannot be objectively verified. This is just the way things are.

Even disregarding this problem, we can still come to the conclusion that it is highly unlikely that such experiences are really violations of the boundary conditions Rosenberg establishes in this chapter. In order to qualify as such, the relevant meditative experiences would have to give the meditator access to the subjective experiences of another, or give another direct access to the meditator's own subjective experiences.
I hope I've addressed this point above.

I have to admit that I really am dumbfounded by this assertion. In what sense does Rosenberg explore consciousness from the 3rd person? The whole point of the book is to come up with a theory that simultaneously respects the first person evidence of experience and finds a way to place it seemlessly in nature, without winding up at conceptual tensions or paradoxes. If Rosenberg were exploring consciousness from the 3rd person, this book would just be a sequel to Consciousness Explained, which it most clearly isn't.
This is not quite what I meant, although at the moment I do see this book as a sequel to Consciousness Explained. In my opinion it's a far better book than Dennett's, full of ideas that make Dennett's look naive, and likely to be much closer to the truth. But like Dennett Rosenberg explores consciousness as a concept, as an abstract entity, not by exploring his own first-person consciousness, the only one to which he has experimental access. (Heidegger would have said that he is exploring 'beings' rather then 'Being', a method he identifies as the most common and persistent error made in western metaphysics. He's another who would have found GR's 'uncontentious assumption' contentious.)

It is true that GR acknowledges the first-person nature of consciousness. But having acknowledged it he then explores it as if it were a third-person phenomenon. This is his choice, and there's no reason not to explore it in this way. But it seems to me unrigorous to assume that the findings of people who explore it also the other way, subjectively, as if those findings, which are extensively documented, were not worth mentioning.

PS. I'm happy to keep debating this point but I'm also happy to move on. I'm still very interested in his ideas on causation and so forth, and am not trying to prove that his theory/hypothesis is wrong (not yet anyway), especially since I don't yet understand it fully. I'm just pointing out that he made an crucial assumption that many would contest.
 
  • #20
I haven't had many chances to sit down with the book, and I've been trying to work through chapter 3, but I finally finshed chapter 4 today, and I had a couple of comments.

First, I agree with loseyourname's first post here. We know the exact boudnary conditions of our own consciousness: that which is available for global control. For example, if there is a red spot in the corner of my field of vision, it has access to global control in that I can choose to talk about it, stomp my foot or hold my breath in response to it. This is true of anything we deem an experience, from a fleeting thought to a sharp pain. And anything that isn't available for global control is not an experience. It is a necessary and sufficient condition. Not causation, not information, it is precisely global access that defines what is part of our experience.

But Rosenberg works from the outside in, assuming anything could be conscious and then reasoning his way down to a set that's both more manageable (eg, not every possbile subset of the universe), unarbitrary, and includes human consciousness. But it seems more appropriate to work from the inside out. We know global access is precisely the boundary of our own experience, so we should look for other systems where many different properties all have access to each other (this would look like a complete graph, for anyone who knows graph theory), or to some global center. Maybe he comes to this conclusion later, but it seems that he should have started here rather than with the completely unjustified assumption that anything can be conscious.

Second, as for the debate about a unified consciousness. Are these people claiming to have felt other people's (or thing's) experiences? Were they able to, for example, feel a distant person's pain, and then find out later that person was actually injured? Because if not, all they are having is a self-contatined experience that feels unifying, and they are still completely bounded within their subjective realm.
 
  • #21
StatusX said:
First, I agree with loseyourname's first post here. We know the exact boudnary conditions of our own consciousness: that which is available for global control. For example, if there is a red spot in the corner of my field of vision, it has access to global control in that I can choose to talk about it, stomp my foot or hold my breath in response to it. This is true of anything we deem an experience, from a fleeting thought to a sharp pain. And anything that isn't available for global control is not an experience. It is a necessary and sufficient condition. Not causation, not information, it is precisely global access that defines what is part of our experience.

I agree that in the human case, in general, that which is p-conscious is co-extensive with that which is available for global control. However, I wouldn't say that we know the exact boundary conditions, since we don't yet know the exact details of the neural underpinnings of global control. Also, there might be some fringe cases that could be exceptions to the rule, or at least might blur the lines a bit. For example, blindsighted people have (limited) access to visual information in the blindsighted portion of their visual field, but consistently deny that they have any conscious experience of this portion of the visual field. (Of course, it is arguable to what extent their access to visual information in the blindsighted area really constitutes global control. I myself would contend that this information access does not constitute global control, but this example does seem to blur matters somewhat, even if it ultimately is not a counterexample to your co-extensiveness principle.)

There is more to be said on the matter, though. Following the arguments in this chapter, if we took global control to be that aspect of nature that draws the boundary lines of experiencing subjects, we would also have to identify what it is about systems exhibiting global control that forms or reflects the basis for this individuation. That is, if we accept
1) the structure of consciousness mirrors the structure of some aspects of the physical brain (we need not make a commitment here as to the specific aspects of the brain or the nature of the causal relationship between the two), and
2) experiencing subjects are inherently individuated in nature,
then we need to find some respect in which the relevant aspects of the brain are likewise inherently individuated in nature. That is, we need to establish a sense in which these aspects of the brain are naturally individuated in a way that is not essentially arbitrary or interest relative, but rather is in some sense 'recognized' and respected by nature, analogous to the way that our boundedness as experiencing subjects is also respected by nature. If we cannot do this, then we arrive upon something of a contradiction between 1) and 2); at least one of them must be abandoned. But so far as they go, these seem to be some of the most reliable and unassailable claims we can make about consciousness from the third- and first-person perspectives.

If we suppose that global control is the relevant aspect of brains that mirrors consciousness, then, we need to propose some manner in which global control is not just a useful human concept, but is something that might directly figure into the workings of nature itself. But the general sense of the term "global control" seems to pick out a high-level abstraction, and it would be difficult (and unprecedented) to imagine how nature could delineate such a thing. A better approach would seem to be to address some aspect of global control that is not an abstraction and is plausibly recognized by nature. Possible candidates might be something like synchronized electrical activity as alluded to in loseyourname's last post, or perhaps even more generally, the nature of the causal mesh that instantiates global control. (Of course, even having identified such a plausible candidate, we would then have to come up with some explanation as to exactly how it is that nature regards this phenomenon as an inherently unified/bounded thing.)

But Rosenberg works from the outside in, assuming anything could be conscious and then reasoning his way down to a set that's both more manageable (eg, not every possbile subset of the universe), unarbitrary, and includes human consciousness. But it seems more appropriate to work from the inside out. We know global access is precisely the boundary of our own experience, so we should look for other systems where many different properties all have access to each other (this would look like a complete graph, for anyone who knows graph theory), or to some global center. Maybe he comes to this conclusion later, but it seems that he should have started here rather than with the completely unjustified assumption that anything can be conscious.

Your concerns here are anticipated by Rosenberg and will be addressed head-on in chapters 5 and 6. But staying within the confines of chapter 4 for now, Rosenberg has not yet assumed that just anything actually can be conscious. All the scenarios and thought experiments he explores in this chapter seek to establish epistemic possibilities, not metaphysical possibilities; at this point, he is interested in seeing to what extent our concepts and theories can be stretched, rather than making any claims about whether or not things like economies or atoms might actually be conscious.

Interestingly, you seem to anticipate some of Rosenberg's work later in the book when you mention directed graphs. When you speak of a system of global control as a directed graph, what exactly do you conceive of as instantiating the nodes and edges?
 
  • #22
hypnagogue said:
If we suppose that global control is the relevant aspect of brains that mirrors consciousness, then, we need to propose some manner in which global control is not just a useful human concept, but is something that might directly figure into the workings of nature itself. But the general sense of the term "global control" seems to pick out a high-level abstraction, and it would be difficult (and unprecedented) to imagine how nature could delineate such a thing. A better approach would seem to be to address some aspect of global control that is not an abstraction and is plausibly recognized by nature. Possible candidates might be something like synchronized electrical activity as alluded to in loseyourname's last post, or perhaps even more generally, the nature of the causal mesh that instantiates global control. (Of course, even having identified such a plausible candidate, we would then have to come up with some explanation as to exactly how it is that nature regards this phenomenon as an inherently unified/bounded thing.)

I agree, it would have to be something fundamental. And since nature seems be cast in the language of mathematics, it should probably be some fundamental mathematical property. That is why I suggested a very rough analogy to complete graphs. Complete Graphs are graphs in which every node is connceted to every other node. I was reminded of them when I thought about how every physical correlate of experience must be connected in some way to every other. Complete graphs are relatively fundamental (in graph theory if not in mathematics in general), and they are naturally individuated in that you can find a complete graph as a subset of a larger graph, and it is unambiguous that that subset is complete. If the nodes are some physical substrate (neurons, or atoms, or chinese people), and the edges are some kind of causal connection, then maybe every complete graph in nature can experience.

I know this is oversimplifying things, and the relevant connections and substrates are very vaguely defined, it's just the first thing that popped into my head. Still, whatever the boundary requirement turns out to be, it will arguably involve some graph theory, because connections are what's important (and you mentioned he'll talk about this later), and it will have to be mathematically fundamental. I'll see how I feel about this idea when we get to Rosenberg's main proposal in part 2, and after he's explained more about causation.

I still think that a theory of consciousness should be the simplest possible one that includes our own consciousness. He has decided to start from all possible boundary principles and find the simplest ones that include our own boundary principles, where I would have started from our own and generalized them in the most straightforward way. They may (and should) reach the same conclusion, but I'll have to watch for any unreasonable assumptions he might make about non-human consciousness.
 
Last edited:
  • #23
StatusX said:
First, I agree with loseyourname's first post here. We know the exact boudnary conditions of our own consciousness: that which is available for global control. For example, if there is a red spot in the corner of my field of vision, it has access to global control in that I can choose to talk about it, stomp my foot or hold my breath in response to it. This is true of anything we deem an experience, from a fleeting thought to a sharp pain. And anything that isn't available for global control is not an experience. It is a necessary and sufficient condition. Not causation, not information, it is precisely global access that defines what is part of our experience.
I'm not sure quite what is meant here by 'global control'. Do you mean just that an experience is not an experience unless we are conscious of it?

Second, as for the debate about a unified consciousness. Are these people claiming to have felt other people's (or thing's) experiences? Were they able to, for example, feel a distant person's pain, and then find out later that person was actually injured? Because if not, all they are having is a self-contatined experience that feels unifying, and they are still completely bounded within their subjective realm.
I hope I answered these two questions earlier. On the latter point note that in the 'non-dual' or 'Middle Way' view the distinction between subjective and objective breaks down at a fundamental level of analysis or experience. They represent two distinct aspects of phenomena at one level, but these aspects are not distinct at a meta-level, where this duality is reduced to what in Advaita would be called 'Unicity'.

This is consistent with the growing view in physics that on analysis the phenomena that make up the physical world consist of relations, not of some fundamental 'stuff'. That is, phenomena are relations in a constant state of realignment, with no noumenal 'carrier' that underly these relations.

Thus, for instance, any analysis of time, space, matter, self and so on fails to show that they have any absolute existence but rather that they have just a relative one. My impression is that this is not scientifically contentious. (In M-theory for instance it seems that there is a sense in which time and space do not exist, or are arbitrary concepts).

However in the analytical/philosophical description of reality given in Buddhist doctrine the term 'phenomena' is taken to include all corporeal and mental 'things' or 'events' ('dhamma' in the original Pali), all but one of which can be analysed to show that they are epiphenomena, have only a dependent existence. Only one 'dhamma' is not epiphenomenal and this is never anyalysed philosophically, since it cannot be an object of philosophy but is rather an object of realisation. ("The Tao that can be talked is not the eternal Tao" - Lao-Tsu). It is only at the level of this fundamental dhamma that the terms subjective and objective cease to have meaning.

I know nothing about graph theory, but translated into those terms I imagine that this is equivalent to saying that the nodes of a graph are defined by their relations and that they have no inherent existence apart from those relations. In a way one might say that this is taking the principles of special relativity to the extreme and saying that not only is the existence of motion, time, extension and so on only relative, but so also is the existence of the phenomena that are subject to motion, temporality, extension and so on.

This is what interested me about GR's bare differences. Bare analysis of corporeal and mental phenomena shows that objects and events consist of only bare differences. This conclusion can only be avoided by assuming, as did Kant, Descartes and so on, a 'noumenal' substance underlying these differences. However this noumenal substance cannot be found anywhere in the world, and there is thus no evidence to show that phenomena have any underlying noumenal carrier. Only when one uses a qualified analysis of phenomena , one that includes a time dimenension, can phenomena be analysed in terms of relations without the need to posit a noumenal element to them.

What this means is that graph theory (if I'm guessing right about what it is) is very relevant here, but it cannot be assumed that the nodes are ontologically existent objects rather than just sets of relations. Just as in Buddhist philosophy a phenomenon cannot exist singly, a node cannot exist except in dependence on other phenomena. These other phenomena constitute its causes and conditions and would include other single nodes, other sets of nodes, the coordinate system, the consciousness that is conceiving of the graph etc.

This is the background to my earlier comments on Rosenberg's treatment of bare differences and the individuation of selves. I like his approach, (for what that's worth), and it is similar in many ways to the kind af analysis of phenomena undertaken in Buddhist practice, but to me it is not sufficiently radical. He assumes that mental phenomena are not constituted by bare differences, and assumes that selves are ontologically individuated. If he dropped these assumptions and took his ideas to their natural conclusion then a quite different approach to exploring and explaining consciousness and phenomena becomes possible. For instance, it then becomes possible to model the universe by way of Spencer-Brown's calculus of indications or 'marks', (perhaps, if I'm not muddled about this, with the marks being equivalent to the nodes of graph theory).

Again I must stress that I'm not arguing for the truth of this view, just for its plausibility, and suggesting that perhaps Rosenberg should have noted and discounted this view rather than ignored it.
 
  • #24
Canute said:
I'm not sure quite what is meant here by 'global control'. Do you mean just that an experience is not an experience unless we are conscious of it?

I'm trying to relate it to a functional role, so I used a word less loaded than "conscious." But I think you get what I mean. When you have an experience, from a blurred color in the corner of your field of vision to a slight ache in your back, it has the capacity to affect any other part of your (conscious) brain. You could choose to think about it, talk about it, or compare it to another experience. Every conscious activity is causally interconnected. On the other hand, things like automatic functions (heartbeat, digestion), latent unconscious desires, blindsight vision, and other people's pains are not readily available, and we do not experience them. I don't pretend this is a precise defintion, but it qualitatively captures the functional side of experience.

This is consistent with the growing view in physics that on analysis the phenomena that make up the physical world consist of relations, not of some fundamental 'stuff'. That is, phenomena are relations in a constant state of realignment, with no noumenal 'carrier' that underly these relations.

You have two boxes. On each of the boxes are four buttons labelled 0, 1, 2 and 3. Inside the first box is a square. It's state is determined by which of its four sides is facing up (1, 2, 3 or 4). When you push one of the buttons, the square is rotated clockwise by n*90 degrees, and then a digital display reports what state it's in. In the other box, there is a counter that can take on the values 1,2,3 and 4. When you press a button, you advance the counter by n, (it loops back to 1 after 4), and then it reports its state. You "experiment" on the two boxes by pushing different buttons and noting the resulting state. Is there anyway to guess which box is which?

Of course there isn't, because you are only capable of examining functional roles. No amount of experimentation will be able to tell you what the rules are acting on. But that doesn't mean the rules are all there is. Clearly, in this case anyway, there is something they are acting on, it's just impossible to know what.

It is hard to imagine the rules could exist without some grounding, but we can't discount it out of of hand. However, it is clear that not every natural phenomenon is composed of bare differences, since experiences are not. So we could try to relate the intrinsicness of the physical to that of consciousness, which I think is what Rosenberg is going to do. It is interesting that the same problems of experimental verification arise for both.

This is the background to my earlier comments on Rosenberg's treatment of bare differences and the individuation of selves. I like his approach, (for what that's worth), and it is similar in many ways to the kind af analysis of phenomena undertaken in Buddhist practice, but to me it is not sufficiently radical. He assumes that mental phenomena are not constituted by bare differences, and assumes that selves are ontologically individuated. If he dropped these assumptions and took his ideas to their natural conclusion then a quite different approach to exploring and explaining consciousness and phenomena becomes possible. For instance, it then becomes possible to model the universe by way of Spencer-Brown's calculus of indications or 'marks', (perhaps, if I'm not muddled about this, with the marks being equivalent to the nodes of graph theory).

To claim that experiences are just bare differences is to be ignoring the facts. It also eliminates any hard problem. Experiences are not completely accounted for by their functional role, because there is still something it is like to actually have them that is not strictly functional, and is not composed of bare differences. If you think this is false, you'll have to at least explain why it is so strongly intuitive.
 
  • #25
Thanks for the explanation. (Although I didn't quite see what you were getting at with the box example).

StatusX said:
To claim that experiences are just bare differences is to be ignoring the facts. It also eliminates any hard problem. Experiences are not completely accounted for by their functional role, because there is still something it is like to actually have them that is not strictly functional, and is not composed of bare differences. If you think this is false, you'll have to at least explain why it is so strongly intuitive.
I haven't explained myself very well on this one. To be clear I should say straight away that I'm not an eliminativist. What I'm doing is suggesting a separation between the experience and the experiencer or knower. Then experiences (experiences of differences) can be bare while the experiencer is not.

This relates directly to Schroedinger's observation on the nature of self posted earlier, that "If you analyse it closely, you will, I think, find that it is just a little bit more than a collection of single data (experiences and memories), namely, the canvas upon which they are collected. And you will, on close introspection, find that what you really mean by "I," is that ground-stuff on which they are collected."

This is also Sartre's conclusion, that consciousness and self are not the same thing, and that the self is a part of the phenomenal world while consciousness is not. Self includes the experiences had by the self, perhaps one might say that self is the experiences had by the self, and these experiences can be constituted by bare differences. That is, mental and corporeal phenomena may reduce to conceptual or non-fundamental distinctions. However the ground-stuff on which these phenomena are collected is ontologically real, not an epiphenomenon.

This is not far from Rosenberg's view, I think, and it does not disable his argument on physicalism. However it is a more radical phenomenology. In effect it is epiphenominalism, but with phenomena epiphenomenal on the 'ground-stuff' rather than than the materialist version, which I'd argue was inconsistent and back to front. (It's close to 'anomalous monism', but not the same). This 'ground-stuff', in my metaphysic, is the unconditioned or non-dependent 'dhamma' (thing or state) from which dependent or relative phenomena arise, the 'substance' underlying reality.

Here's a bit from Sartre that helps flesh out what I mean here. (I'm not endorsing all Sartre's views on consciousness by the way, which to me seem to amount to nihilism). It's from the conclusions in 'The Transcendence of the Ego'.

"The phenomenologists have plunged man back into the world; they have given full measure to man's agonies and sufferings, and also to his rebellions. Unfortunately, as long as the I remains a structure of absolute consciousness, one will still be able to reproach phenomenology for being an escapist doctrine, for again pulling a part of man out of the world and, in that way, turning our attention from the real problems. It seems to us that this reproach no longer has any justification if one makes the me an existent, strictly contemporaneous with the world, whose existence has the same essential characteristics as the world. It has always seemed to me that a working hypothesis as fruitful as historical materialism never needed for a foundation the absurdity which is metaphysical materialism. In fact, it is not necessary that the object precede the subject for spiritual pseudo-values to vanish and for ethics to find its bases in reality. It is enough that the me be contemporaneous with the World, and that the subject-object duality, which is purely logical, definitively disappear from philosophical preoccupations. The World has not created the me; the me has not created the World. These are two objects for absolute, impersonal consciousness, and it is by virtue of this coonsciousness that they are connected. This absolute consciousness, when it is purified of the I, no longer has anything of the subject. It is no longer a collection of representations. It is quite simply a first condition and an absolute source of existence."
 
Last edited:
  • #26
Canute said:
(Although I didn't quite see what you were getting at with the box example).

I'll have to do a little reading before I can address the rest of your post, but for now, let me just explain this. I was trying to point out that science can only describe our universe up to an isomorphism. It could be strings of some "energy-stuff", computer circuits, or a huge wooden abacus at the bottom, for all we know. As long as they all have the same extrinsic properties, all our measurements will be the same. Now, whether our experiences would be the same in all of these worlds is debatable, and I think we'll get into that in later chapters.
 
Last edited:
  • #27
Canute said:
This is also Sartre's conclusion, that consciousness and self are not the same thing, and that the self is a part of the phenomenal world while consciousness is not. Self includes the experiences had by the self, perhaps one might say that self is the experiences had by the self, and these experiences can be constituted by bare differences. That is, mental and corporeal phenomena may reduce to conceptual or non-fundamental distinctions. However the ground-stuff on which these phenomena are collected is ontologically real, not an epiphenomenon.

I don't really understand your view. You say consciousness and the self are not the same thing, but then that perhaps the self is the experiences had by the self. But I've always considered consciousness to be those experiences, so I'm confused about what you really mean.

Also, I'm not sure you mean the same thing I do when you say "bare differences". A bare difference arises when the difference between two objects is taken as a fact, and not based on any further facts. They aren't different because some intrinsic aspect of them differs, they are just different and that's that. I was a little confused when Rosenberg made the jump from the bare difference between on and off states to the claim that every fact about the Pure life world can be derived from these bare differences, because you obviously also need the rules of the game.

But given all the bare differences and functional roles of experiences, there are still more facts that can't be derived, namely, what the experiences feel like. So I don't really understand how you could claim experiences consist only of bare differences. We don't just know that red and green are different. We say they are different because they look different. It is their intrinsic nature that instantiates the difference. I think this is also what Rosenberg means by bare differences, but I could be wrong.
 
  • #28
I must admit that I'm still not quite clear about the 'bare difference' concept. I understand the 'not based on further facts' thing, but still find it a bit ambiguous. I'll try to restate my reservations as to how Rosenberg applies the concept, and if I've misunderstood him please put me right.

If one created a pure Life world in which on/off was replaced by red/green then red/green would be a bare difference. Once one introduces a perceiving consciousness that can distinguish between red and green then the difference between them ceases to be bare. But once one introduces a perceiving consciousness that can distinguish between on and off (say by perceiving pixels on a screen) the difference between on/off ceases to be a bare one also.

So I'm suggesting that it is not the un-bareness of the difference between red and green that is of significance. This is no more significant than the difference between on and off. What is significant is that fact that red and green, (or on and off) can be be perceived/experienced as different. This is not to disagree with Rosenberg's overall argument, it is more of a re-wording than a change, but it avoids the implied reification of some differences and the un-reification of others.

By this view the difference between red and green is not a difference of a different kind to the difference between on and off, and neither difference is more or less bare. What counts is whether there is a consciousness experiencing these differences. If there is then they are not bare, if there is not then they are.

The reason I'm being pedantic in this way is that this avoids the danger of taking the 'bareness' or otherwise of a difference to be intrinsic to the quantity that differs, or to the dimension along which the difference is measured. Every difference is bare until a conscious distinction is made between the poles of the difference, (until the difference is conceived/experienced).

Putting it this way it still follows that physicalism is false, since it cannot account for the experience of qualitative differences. But it avoids the (probably inadvertent) implication that some types of difference are in themselves bare and others not, when all that matters is whether we experience them or not, and whether we distinguish between the poles of the difference or not.

This, to me anyway, helps to disentangle the ontology of these differences. It allows one to say that such differences are not bare if as a 'self' we experience a qualitative difference between them, while avoiding any suggestion that non-bare differences are fundamental in any ontological sense. That is, it allows us to assign the discrimination of, and experience of, these differences to the 'self', while still allowing a transcendent aspect to consciousness, a state in which these differences are illusory, a state in which those differences can be seen as a product of 'self'.

To quote Sartre again he writes, regarding emotions, (a difference between which I would assume to be not-bare by Rosenberg's definition), "The emotion, after all, remains attached to me. The emotion "sticks to" the me. If one draws the me into consciousness, one draws the emotion along with it." (His italics)

By saying that 'self' is an object of consciousness it allows for the existence of consciousness at a level beyond self, at the level of what Sarte calls the 'transcendent field', (what Zen master Hongzhi calls the 'empty field'), and which he (Satre) proposes is purified of "egological" structure and entirely transparent, thus beyond the conceptual distinctions made by the self.

At this transparent (empty) level of consciousness all distinctions are transcended. This is both Spencer-Brown's indefinable void and Sartre's non-temporal transcendental consciousnness, in which "each instant of our conscious life reveals to us creation ex nihilo" (Sarte), and which lies beyond or underneath the 'self', and in which no differences are bare, since if they are bare they are not being experienced and do not exist. At this level the self disappears, since the self must exist spread out in time and not as a momentary state, and all differences, including the difference between subject and object, (and past, present and future) dissolve. It is a state of consciousness in which even the difference between subject and object is a bare one, not entailed by further facts nor experienced as a difference.

This is what I meant by suggesting that the difference between red and green is ultimately a bare one. I wasn't suggesting that experiences do not exist, just that the self that perceives/conceives/experiences may be no less a phenomena in the world and no less an object of consciousness than is 'red' and 'off', or pianos and kitchen tables. Thus my comment that Rosenberg's phenomenology didn't seem radical enough to me.

Hmm. On re-reading that I'm not sure if it clarifies my point or confuses it even more. Unfortunately clarity is not one of my strengths. I'll leave it and see what you think.
 
Last edited:
  • #29
Canute said:
If one created a pure Life world in which on/off was replaced by red/green then red/green would be a bare difference. Once one introduces a perceiving consciousness that can distinguish between red and green then the difference between them ceases to be bare. But once one introduces a perceiving consciousness that can distinguish between on and off (say by perceiving pixels on a screen) the difference between on/off ceases to be a bare one also.

The red/green substitution you propose here isn't faithful to Rosenberg's use of the terms. He says the difference between phenomenal red and phenomenal green is not bare. But speaking about phenomenal red and green already presupposes the existence of the experiencing subject, or as you put it, the perceiving consciousness. It is no more coherent to talk about phenomenal red in the absence of experience than it is to speak of the front of a wall in the absence of its back. Since you seem to believe that properties experienced by a conscious subject are not composed of bare differences, it seems you ultimately agree with Rosenberg, and think you do not because of a misconception of the terms being used.
 
  • #30
Of course red and green do not exist without an experiencer, I assumed I didn't need to say that. And yes, I do agree with him on bare differences, as far he goes. I don't agree about individuation though. Never mind, I've said my piece.
 

FAQ: Chapter 4: The Boundary Problem for Experiencing Subjects

1. What is the "boundary problem" in relation to experiencing subjects?

The "boundary problem" refers to the philosophical question of where the boundaries of a subject's experience lie. In other words, what is the extent of a subject's consciousness and what falls within its scope?

2. How does the boundary problem relate to the study of consciousness?

The boundary problem is a central issue in the study of consciousness because it raises questions about the nature of subjective experience and what it means to be a conscious being.

3. What are some proposed solutions to the boundary problem?

Some proposed solutions to the boundary problem include the concept of a "self-model," which suggests that our sense of self is constructed through a combination of internal and external factors, and the idea of a "global workspace," which posits that consciousness arises from the integration of information from different brain regions.

4. How does the boundary problem impact our understanding of the mind-body problem?

The boundary problem is closely related to the mind-body problem, as it raises questions about the relationship between the physical brain and subjective experience. It challenges traditional dualist views that posit a clear separation between the mind and the body, and instead suggests a more complex and interconnected relationship.

5. What are some potential implications of the boundary problem for our understanding of consciousness?

The boundary problem has significant implications for our understanding of consciousness, as it challenges traditional views and raises new questions about the nature of subjective experience. It also has practical implications for fields such as neuroscience and psychology, as it impacts how we study and treat disorders of consciousness.

Similar threads

Replies
55
Views
9K
Replies
28
Views
6K
Replies
18
Views
6K
Replies
22
Views
4K
Replies
87
Views
13K
Replies
33
Views
5K
Replies
32
Views
4K
Back
Top