Chapter 7: Paradoxes for Liberal Naturalism

  • Thread starter hypnagogue
  • Start date
In summary: Rosenberg considers the Boundary Problem to be a particularly challenging paradox for a Liberal Naturalist account of consciousness. The Boundary Problem is the question of how we can account for the fact that we can identify the properties of one conscious entity (e.g. myself) while failing to identify the properties of another (e.g. my dog). In other words, how can we say that I have experience of red, without being able to say that my dog has experience of red? Rosenberg takes the view that the Boundary Problem is a manifestation of the problem of individuation. He argues that the Boundary Problem is a problem because it assumes an ontological separation between entities that does not actually exist. The problem
  • #1
hypnagogue
Staff Emeritus
Science Advisor
Gold Member
2,285
3
Thus far, we have considered some conceptual tensions surrounding consciousness that an antiphysicalist, Liberal Naturalist framework must address-- how do we solve the Boundary Problem, and how viable is panexperientialism? In this chapter, we turn to further tensions that seem to present us with outright paradoxes. Rosenberg's intent here (as before) is not to resolve these paradoxes, but rather to consider the challenges they present and look for clues as to what direction of inquiry would make for fruitful investigation. He asks that we take the same attitude and not attempt to draw strong conclusions or brush the problems off as mere artifacts of cognitive limitations or delusions. By the end of the book, Rosenberg will have presented a detailed outline of his version of Liberal Naturalism, and will be able to use it to address these paradoxes and untangle their seemingly intractable knots without resorting to deflationary tactics.

1. The unity of consciousness
The human qualitative field is filled with rich and complex phenomenal events. There is a sense in which these qualia are distinct, but there is another, subtler sense in which they enjoy some sort of coherent unity of presentation. For instance, in the qualitative visual field, we can distinguish the color, shape, and motion of a falling ball as distinct phenomenal properties, but there is also a sense in which these phenomenal properties are bound together and 'overlap' to form a single qualitative object or event. More generally and subtly, we can observe that even phenomenal events occurring in different sensory modalities-- e.g. auditory and visual-- seem to share the same phenomenal space, to be painted on the same canvas, to belong integrally to the same whole.

Rosenberg identifies both a challenge and a paradox arising from considerations of the unity of consciousness. The challenge of unity is to give a clear articulation of what the unity of consciousness actually is. We have definite intuitions that the qualitative field is in some sense unified, and these intuitions have even played a part in guiding e.g. the neuroscientific endeavor to frame and then solve the binding problem of percepts. However, it is difficult to give a precise characterization that resonates with our intuitions of exactly what we mean when we say that consciousness is unified.

The paradox of unity pits our intuitions about the unity of consciousness against the physical, composite description of the brain. We tend to view the brain, and physical systems in general, as composite systems-- systems that are straightforwardly composed of smaller elements and their relationships to each other. The relevant metaphor here is that of a brick wall, where the wall is the composite system whose existence is determined entirely by its components (the bricks) and their various relationships to each other; in turn, the bricks enjoy an independent existence that does not presuppose the existence of the whole wall. In this way, we view the fundamental particles as composing atoms, atoms as composing organic molecules, organic molecules as composing nerve cells, and so on. At each level, the components of the composite system are separable from the whole-- even if we break the system of relationships that creates the whole, we will still be left with the composite parts.

However, the unity condition of consciousness seems to resist such a reductive treatment. Rosenberg argues that it is implausible for a given phenomenal event (e.g. a headache) to exist independently from the entirety of the experiencing subject to which it belongs. Likewise, it is implausible to suppose that the qualitative visual field is composed of 'tiny colored dots' that exist independently of the whole experience. Rather, the elements of our experience seem to already presuppose the existence of the whole experiential manifold, and holistically depend on it to achieve their own existence. Thus, the elements of experience are inseparable from the whole-- were we to break the conditions that support the whole of experience, we would not be left with component qualia floating around disparately. We can state the paradox of unity succinctly, then, as follows: How can a single system be both composite and non-composite?

Rosenberg notes that a functionalist treatment seems well suited to describing the unity of consciousness. After all, functional systems have discernible functional entities as elements, but these elements depend on the context of the whole system to achieve their meaning; they cannot be fully specified without reference (be it explicit or implicit) to the entire system of which they are a part. In other words, they cannot be characterized as 'bricks in the wall.' In this way, functional systems capture something of the holistic nature of consciousness in a way that composite physical systems do not.

However, while a functionalist perspective may prove invaluable in describing consciousness, it cannot be the whole story for a Liberal Naturalist paradigm. As touched on in chapter 6, a conventional functionalist analysis will suffer to varying degrees from problems of functional teleology, interest relativity, and norms. These are the sorts of things that are created by human observers and imposed upon nature, rather than things that nature itself recognizes and responds to. Perhaps we can work around this problem by defining what it means to be a causal role, and a canonical context for a causal role, in such a way that these do not fall prey to functional teleology, interest relativity, and norms, but rather are objective phenomena to which nature is sensitive.

2. The subjective instant
Some sets of phenomenal events in consciousness seem to occur simultaneously. These collections of simultaneous events constitute the subjective instant, or what William James called the specious present. However, these simultaneous phenomenal events correspond with physical brain events that are asynchronous. Even more pressing is the observation that, to the subject of experience, the simultaneity of phenomenal events seems to be a privileged, absolute fact, whereas the laws of special relativity show us that there is no privileged reference frame from which we can decide that a given set of physical events in the brain occur simultaneously in an absolute sense. Succinctly stated, the paradox here is that there seems to be a system to which the laws of relativity both do and do not apply.

The temptation here is to write off the subjective instant as an illusion and give complete deference to the relativistic account of spacetime. However, it is not clear that physics has an entirely firm handle on the matter of time and its apparent 'flow.' An appeal is often made to the direction of causation, as implied by the second law of thermodynamics, to account for the apparent directionality of time. This is an attractive proposition, but it is not clear that physics alone affords us a complete account of causation. If the physical facts do not completely fix the facts about causation and the directionality of time, perhaps some light can be shed on the paradox of the subjective instant via a deeper theory of causation and its relationship to the apparent temporal flux.

3. The knowledge paradox
If physicalism is false, and if the world is causally closed under physics, it appears as if there is no room for p-consciousness to make a causal contribution to brain events. But clearly, our knowledge claims about p-consciousness (e.g. "I know that I am conscious right now") are driven by physical brain events. If p-consciousness is irrelevant to the causal dynamics of the brain, then, it seems that it can play no role in producing our knowledge claims about it. In short, it seems as if our knowledge claims about p-consciousness should bear no relevance to the phenomenon itself; we should have no way to really know that we are p-conscious, even though we claim that we are.

It appears as if the knowledge paradox forces the Liberal Naturalist to be caught on the dual horns of interactionist dualism and epiphenomenalism. We can escape the conundrum of the knowledge paradox if we deny the causal closure of the physical and claim that non-physical p-consciousness really does directly influence the physical dynamics of the brain. The resulting interactionist dualist ontology presents significant further problems, however, and there is no strong evidence that the world is not causally closed under physics. If we reject interactionism, we can bite the bullet and propose that p-consciousness is epiphenomenal on brain events. On this view, p-consciousness is lawfully correlated with brain events, but still does not make any contribution to their causal dynamics. Epiphenomenalism is not much better than interactionism, as it still presents us with significant problems. While knowledge claims about p-consciousness would be true under epiphenomenalism, it seems they would not be justified. Rather, they would be more like lucky coincidences, since there would be no mechanism by which we could attain reasons for making these claims. Our physical brains would cause us to utter that we are p-conscious, and mere serendipity would have it that we were in fact correct. If the laws enforcing the epiphenomenal correlation between brain events and p-conscious events were to somehow be shut off, we would go on (falsely) claiming that we are p-conscious, none the wiser.

The knowledge paradox is a deep problem for Liberal Naturalism, and on the surface, it seems as if the Liberal Naturalist is forced to choose between two highly problematic views. But perhaps the paradox does not turn on the nature of p-consciousness so much as it turns on our understanding of causation and its relationship to physics. A deeper theory of causation might allow the Liberal Naturalist to maintain that physicalism is false without being forced into either interactionist dualism or epiphenomenalism.

4. The superfluity of consciousness
Suppose that we reject interactionism and embrace epiphenomenalism. The resulting ontology casts p-consciousness as a nomological dangler, a phenomenon that exists despite having no relevance to the causal mesh of the world. Such a view undermines our convictions that nature is parsimonious, and invites speculation that perhaps the world is teeming with phenomena that are superfluous to our scientific understanding of it. This speculation not only does damage to convictions about nature's parsimony, but also undermines any hopes for scientific realism. If nature abounded with entities that are superfluous to our understanding of it, then we could never hope to even approach anything like ontological truth. Our scientific theories would remain useful for predicting the outcomes of experiments, but they would likely not tell us anything about what the world is really like. Occam's razor would become a purely pragmatic consideration rather than a useful metaphysical tool for science and philosophy. The superfluity of consciousness under epiphenomenalism, then, introduces a paradoxical tension between what we take ourselves to know about the world and what we should take ourselves to know about the world. It seems as if we have good reason to think that we know something of the world's ontological nature, but if epiphenomenalism is true, we should not hold any confidence that we do.

5. The grain problem
The grain problem arises from considering the incongruence between the structural complexity of phenomenal events in p-consciousness and the structural complexity of their physical, neural correlates. For instance, observe that a uniform patch of color in the qualitative visual field has a simple, homogenous structure, whereas the neural events that correlate with it have a high degree of varying structural complexities and nuances. We cannot inspect a uniform patch of phenomenal color more closely and reveal further layers of structural complexity corresponding to the structural complexities of the correlated neural events. In short, qualia are very coarse-grained with respect to their finer-grained neural correlates.

The grain problem is pressing for physicalism, but not necessarily so for Liberal Naturalism, which is not obligated to suppose that the physical is the ultimate basis for the experiential. But we are still left with the question of what does form the basis for experience, and how it does this in such a way as to resolve the grain problem. Once again, functionalism seems a promising candidate.

As previously discussed, functional entities derive their meaning from the specific kind of causal role they play in a larger functional context. Importantly, we need not specify lower level structural details in order to define a functional object or its causal role. The only relevant details of the functional specification are the abstract, higher-level patterns of causation that constitute the functional system as a whole, and the causal contributions that each functional component of the system makes to the system as a whole. For instance, we can regard a computer program as a functional system in this way. What essentially defines the computer program is just its abstract functional pattern of information processing. The lower-level structures of the program-- the physical or logical systems that implement it-- are irrelevant to the description of the program itself, and can be abstracted away. It does not matter if we implement a given program on a PC computer or on an abacus, so long as we guarantee that its characteristic high-level patterns of information processing are preserved.

In this way, functional systems are encapsulated at their own level of nature. The ontological nature of functional systems, insofar as we view them purely as functional systems, has no finer grain. We can now immediately see a parallel between the coarse-grained nature of functional being and the coarse-grained nature of qualia, a parallel that seems to invite a treatment of the grain problem by way of a functionalist account of p-consciousness. However, we must note again that while an appeal to functionalism may be critically important, it cannot tell the whole story. And, as before, we cannot give the whole answer without a closer analysis of what causation is and how it individuates and stratifies phenomena in nature.

Summary
Let us take stock of where we are right now. We have considered a number of puzzles and paradoxes surrounding p-consciousness, including the boundary problem, the unity of consciousness, the subjective instant, the knowledge paradox, the superfluity of consciousness, and the grain problem. Each of these deep conceptual problems raises questions about causation in some manner or another. It seems likely, then, that there is some fundamental deficiency in our understanding of causation that is inexorably leading us to systematic confusions about p-consciousness and its relationship with the physical.

With this observation, we conclude Part I of the book. In Part II, Rosenberg will turn his focus to causation, critiquing conventional views of causation and constructing his own novel theory. Once Rosenberg's theory of causation is in place, he will come full circle and return better equipped to questions about p-consciousness and its relationship to the physical.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I find the ultimate conclusion of this chapter to be a deeply insightful and deeply important one. Even if one takes issue with Rosenberg's analysis of causation in Part II of the book, the arguments of this chapter make a very compelling case that almost all of our deep conceptual difficulties about p-consciousness touch on the issue of causation in some manner or another.

This is the sort of key observation that can begin to elevate us from the quagmire of confusion that considerations about consciousness often place us in. We have, in a sense, brought the apparently disparate problems of consciousness together by unearthing a common problematic thread. The idea that most of our deepest confusions about consciousness arise due to a poor understanding of causation, and that we can resolve all of them in one fell swoop by developing a more sophisticated theory of causation, is the sort of eye-opening breakthrough that studies of consciousness have been crying out for for some time.
 
  • #3
You say that "qualia are very coarse-grained with respect to their finer-grained neural correlates." I had always thought it the other way around. In visual processing, for instance, I understood that the qualitative experience of seeing is more finely grained than the information sent from the our retinas. Is this wrong? Or is this a different issue?

By the way, I just noticed your signature quote from Whitehead. It seems very appropriate here, where all the way through the chapter we are being asked to choose whether consciousness is this or that, composite/non-composite, epiphenomenal/dual interactionist, causal/non-causal, subject to /not subject to relativity, and so on. I'd suggest that perhaps "It is trying to treat them as whole truths that plays the devil."
 
  • #4
Canute said:
You say that "qualia are very coarse-grained with respect to their finer-grained neural correlates." I had always thought it the other way around. In visual processing, for instance, I understood that the qualitative experience of seeing is more finely grained than the information sent from the our retinas. Is this wrong? Or is this a different issue?

If qualitative experience were more finely grained than its neural correlates, neuroscience would be in big trouble! But there is no reason for believing that this is the case, and every reason for believing the opposite.

The question about information sent from the retinas is irrelevant here, because the nerve pathways from the retina are not plausibly the neual correlates of visual experience. The neural correlates of experience are defined roughly as those neuron assemblies/neural events whose activation systematically corresponds with the occurence of a given experience. The nerve pathways leading from the retina are not plausibly the neural correlates of visual experience, then, because blindsighted people have normally functioning optic nerves but lose some of their qualitative visual field. The neural correlates of visual experience are generally accepted to exist much farther downstream in the processing of visual information, in the highest brain regions of visual processing. When you consider that the shallow structural content of a uniform patch of color in the visual field is likely correlated with a specific kind of functional activity of thousands or even millions of neurons in the brain's higher visual processing regions, it is not hard to see the basis of the grain problem.

By the way, I just noticed your signature quote from Whitehead. It seems very appropriate here, where all the way through the chapter we are being asked to choose whether consciousness is this or that, composite/non-composite, epiphenomenal/dual interactionist, causal/non-causal, subject to /not subject to relativity, and so on. I'd suggest that perhaps "It is trying to treat them as whole truths that plays the devil."

Actually, Rosenberg asks in the beginning of the chapter that we not be tempted to draw premature conclusions, such as choosing one pole of a paradoxical tension over another. We are not being asked to choose anything here; rather, we are being presented with what seem to be the only choices available, given some background assumptions (the falsity of physicalism, plus prevailing notions on the ontological primacy of the physical, the nature of causation as it is generally understood, etc.). Rosenberg's work in Part II can be understood in part as re-evaluating those background assumptions, particularly about causation and its relationship to the physical, and coming to resolve the paradoxes of this chapter by showing that either a) we are not forced to choose one horn of the paradox over the other (e.g. for the knowledge paradox), or b) with a deeper theory, we can come to accept both sides of the apparent paradox without arriving at a contradiction (e.g. for the unity of consciousness).
 
  • #5
Page 117 said:
“Nature does not know about the existence of implicit reference systems against which one can define a functional role for things.”
This is an unwarranted assumption which my intuition tells me is false. On what basis can he categorically deny nature the ability to know?

Page 120 said:
“…there is no clear evidence that such [causal] gaps exist”
Page 305 Chapter 7 note 5 said:
“I am making the usual assumption that the randomness in QM is either a discovery that causation is probabilistic or a stopgap to be filled by hidden physical variables. I am purposely not treating it as a discovery that there are causal gaps in the physical world.”

Will someone please explain why QM randomness is not clear evidence that causal gaps exist in physics? If causation is probabilistic, then the question is left begging about how quantum events are determined. This would tell me that physics is closed neither causally nor explanatorily. If quantum randomness is a “stopgap to be filled by hidden physical variables” then physics is not explanatorily closed and we can say nothing about causal closure. In my view, quantum randomness should be taken as proof that causality is not closed in physics.

Page 121 said:
”The ultimate expression of this [knowledge] paradox is the conclusion that the Liberal Naturalist is committed to epiphenomenalism or interactionism, neither of which is acceptable because they rule in only the most implausible external connections between consciousness and behavior.”

In defense of interactionism, I would say that this same argument could have been made to deny the possible existence of radio by any thinker prior to the work of Hertz and Maxwell. I think ruling out interactionism at this point is premature and unwarranted, and that to do so would be throwing the baby out with the bath.

Page 125 said:
“Functional objects are defined relative to a canonical reference system by the causal role they play within that system.”

How is the canon established? It seems to me that some consciousness is required either to establish the canon or to notice it and take advantage of it in case it is emergent.

Page 125 said:
”These interactions invoke other objects at the same level, are governed by a multidimensional signaling system, and, by relying on the semantics of the signaling system, implicitly invoke the referent systems they partially constitute.”

How can ‘semantics’ be meaningful in the absence of consciousness?

Like Hypnogogue, I, too, “find the ultimate conclusion of this chapter to be a deeply insightful and deeply important one”. However, I have less patience restraining myself from proposing what seems to me an obvious, simple, answer to all the paradoxes and problems discussed in this chapter. The single, simple, hypothesis of the primordial existence of a single conscious individual (even one with severely limited consciousness) leads straightforwardly to the logical conclusion that reality should be exactly as we experience it and that the paradoxes and problems of Chapter 7 have obvious straightforward answers. Maybe after everyone has finished reading the book, someone can look into this approach.

Paul
 
  • #6
hypnagogue said:
2. The subjective instant
Some sets of phenomenal events in consciousness seem to occur simultaneously. These collections of simultaneous events constitute the subjective instant, or what William James called the specious present. However, these simultaneous phenomenal events correspond with physical brain events that are asynchronous. Even more pressing is the observation that, to the subject of experience, the simultaneity of phenomenal events seems to be a privileged, absolute fact, whereas the laws of special relativity show us that there is no privileged reference frame from which we can decide that a given set of physical events in the brain occur simultaneously in an absolute sense.[

Since the contituents of the brain are not movign at relativistic velocities
with respect ot each other, this problem does not arise. There is no
reason why the brain should not be its own refernce frame.
 
  • #7
Tournesol said:
Since the contituents of the brain are not movign at relativistic velocities
with respect ot each other, this problem does not arise. There is no
reason why the brain should not be its own refernce frame.

I agree with you on this point; it's not clear to me why the problem, construed in terms of relativity, should not reduce to the fact that the brain as a whole simply sits in its own reference frame for as long as it exists. (The problem might have more bite if we considered a functional analogue of the brain where we could have functional constituents accelerating with respect to each other.)

Still, there is the problem of how it is that asynchronous brain events (asynchronous wrt to the skull's reference frame) can correlate with an experienced simultaneity of phenomenal events.
 
Last edited:
  • #8
Paul Martin said:
Will someone please explain why QM randomness is not clear evidence that causal gaps exist in physics? If causation is probabilistic, then the question is left begging about how quantum events are determined. This would tell me that physics is closed neither causally nor explanatorily.

It would tell us that physics isn't closed explanatorily. Whether or not it
is closed causally would depend on he existence of hidden variables.

If quantum randomness is a “stopgap to be filled by hidden physical variables” then physics is not explanatorily closed and we can say nothing about causal closure. In my view, quantum randomness should be taken as proof that causality is not closed in physics.

There is certainly an explanatory gap, and therefore no non-dogmatic reason
to reject the causal efficacy of the mental.

How is the canon established? It seems to me that some consciousness is required either to establish the canon or to notice it and take advantage of it in case it is emergent.

I would guess that the point here is that there are no absolute and objective
facts about functionallity; to decide that two systems are functionaly equivalent we have to decide what aspects of functionallity we are interested
in (if they are physically ientical,the point is trivial, and if they are not, there
will be some difference that needs to be neglected as irellevant).

How can ‘semantics’ be meaningful in the absence of consciousness?

It doesn't obviously require phenomenality.

Like Hypnogogue, I, too, “find the ultimate conclusion of this chapter to be a deeply insightful and deeply important one”. However, I have less patience restraining myself from proposing what seems to me an obvious, simple, answer to all the paradoxes and problems discussed in this chapter. The single, simple, hypothesis of the primordial existence of a single conscious individual (even one with severely limited consciousness) leads straightforwardly to the logical conclusion that reality should be exactly as we experience it and that the paradoxes and problems of Chapter 7 have obvious straightforward answers. Maybe after everyone has finished reading the book, someone can look into this approach.

Who is this individual ? Me or you ? :wink:
 
  • #9
Hypnagogue

I see my mistake about the 'graininess' of retinal information and consciousness. As you suggest, I was mistaking the retinal pattern for the neural correlate. This 'grain' problem, now I see what the problem is, is a new one on me, and very interesting. I'll ponder on it.
 
  • #10
Hi Tournesol,

Thank you for answering.

Tournesol said:
There is certainly an explanatory gap, and therefore no non-dogmatic reason to reject the causal efficacy of the mental.

Just as I thought. From what you said, Rosenberg’s choice “of purposely not treating it as a discovery that there are causal gaps in the physical world” is a dogmatic position. I suspect that until science can abandon this dogma and begin to take the possibility of a fundamental mentality seriously, they will fail to come to a complete understanding of reality.

Tournesol said:
I would guess that the point here is that there are no absolute and objective facts about functionallity; to decide that two systems are functionally equivalent we have to decide what aspects of functionallity we are interested in (if they are physically ientical,the point is trivial, and if they are not, there will be some difference that needs to be neglected as irellevant).
We cannot safely neglect all such differences. The particular aspect of functionality I am interested in is the “carrier” function of a communication system. (Rosenberg develops this idea further in later chapters.) I think one absolute and objective fact about this functionality is that the carrier must deliver the same content or meaning to the receiver that the sender intended in order for the communication system to work. Another objective fact is that the receiver must be able to decode, or interpret, or understand, the received message in order for the system to be said to work. In the case of radio, for example, the receiver must be able to detect and extract the audio information from the EM carrier in a way consistent with the encoding done by the transmitter or the radio will not work. I agree that it doesn’t matter if this is done using vacuum tubes or transistors.

Tournesol said:
[’Semantics’] doesn't obviously require phenomenality.
It isn’t obvious what semantics really does require. I think it was Wittgenstein who claimed that semantics requires the entire history of interaction among all participants in the language to which the semantics is imputed. Or something like that. The idea is that language statements have meaning only between communicants which share a method of reducing intent to encoded messages.

To paraphrase Rosenberg on page 125, the “causal roles”, which define functional objects, are individuated by patterns of interactions which are governed by a signaling system. In particular, the interactions rely on the semantics of the signaling system. My question is how this semantics got developed. Was it like Wittgenstein claimed the semantics of human language developed over the millennia of usage? Or like the semantics of the DNA code was claimed to have developed over the eons by Darwinian processes? I agree that phenomenality is not obviously required. But for such a profound and “meaningful” entity as the “semantics of the signaling system” involved at the root of causation to exist, I think some sort of explanation is called for.

Tournesol said:
Who is this individual ? Me or you ?

From the smiley face, I take it that these are not serious questions. But from the wink on the smiley face, I think you might be interested in how I would answer them seriously. So I will.

In my view, this individual is both you and me. I think there is only one conscious individual in all existence. What seem to be individual conscious people (and other animals) are in reality complex vehicles which are “driven” by the one real conscious individual. Analogies with familiar systems show how this could be possible and plausible. A two-way communication system, similar to our radio system, could connect the conscious individual to each physical body. Some kind of mechanism like our multiplexing, or an algorithm like our time-sharing, could explain how a single individual could appear and act like multiple individuals. The one individual has free will and could exercise it through each body the same way human drivers can exercise their “free will” while driving a car or a bulldozer. I think this model provides easy answers to all profound questions. Thanks for asking.

Paul
 
  • #11
Paul

Other thoughts that come to mind in respect of this one consciousness are non-locality (we know that things can be everywhere at once, or that in some sense all points are the same point), and I vaguely remember something about all electrons being the same electron is certain theories. If time and space are arbitrary concepts, as some (most?) physicists argue, then there seems to be no theoretical problem with saying that there is one consciousness that is everywhere is time and space and which underlies all individual occurences of sentience/mind in time and space. Similarly there is one ocean but many waves.

On the thing about semantics and meaning within functional systems I'm not sure I've understood the issue fully. Excuse me if I've muddled it. However, I don't think that that consciousness can be shown to be necessary to such systems. You assume that the signal sent by one part of the system must be sent intentionally, and must be understood for what it is intended to be (a specific message) by a second part of the system. But for the two parts to function as a whole it is not necessary that the signals between them are intentionally sent, nor that they have any intended meaning, nor that they are interpreted in any particular way. The 'signal' between the parts may be sent involuntarily (it may be a discharge of waste, for instance, or a shedding of surplus electrical charge).

If another part of the system is caused to behave in a certain way by this signal and as a result forms a functional relationship with the first part this is just serendipity. Later on, when a dependency has formed between the parts, their now systematic functioning will seem to be based on a shared communication system, the electrical discharge (say) seen as intentional communication, and the signals between them can be analysed for meaning as if the parts were communicating by a common language. But it seems to me that there need be no meaning in the message, no interpretation of it by its receiver, no intention behind the sending of it, and no need for semantics. All that is required is some consistency of physical interaction, allowing a stable system or interdependency between the parts to develop. Or did I miss your point?

(This applies also to systems in which human beings are the parts, which has been a particular interest of mine. I used to collect management related aphorisms, and one of the best I found was "The trouble with communication is thinking that it's happened".)
 
Last edited:
  • #12
First, I agree that causation is central to the many paradoxes surrounding consciousness, and I'm looking forward to the second part of the book. I thought Rosenberg was going to get more into the knowledge paradox, the aspect of consciousnes I find most crucial, and interesting, but I'll have to wait until the next chapter. I think the other paradoxes in this chapter are much less serious, and not true paradoxes, just tough problems.

While we're on the subject, could someone explain exactly what the consequences of a single consciousness theory would be? I just don't understand how it is any different from a many consciousness theory, except for some differences in terms.
 
  • #13
StatusX said:
While we're on the subject, could someone explain exactly what the consequences of a single consciousness theory would be? I just don't understand how it is any different from a many consciousness theory, except for some differences in terms.
I'm not sure what you mean by consequences. In terms of Rosenberg's book the consequences would be that some of his arguments regarding the subject/object distinction, the boundedness of consciousness and so on would have to be reconsidered. It would also cast a whole new light on the brain-mind relationship, which would have to be rethought as the brain-mind-consciousness relationship. Generally the consequences would depend on the particular version of the 'one consciousness' theory being considered.
 
  • #14
Canute

You have not muddled the issue of semantics at all. Your post, to the contrary, brought out the essential details which, by my obscuring them, I muddled the topic all by myself.

Canute said:
I don't think that that consciousness can be shown to be necessary to such systems.
That’s a reasonable and obvious position to take. But for me, with my particular world view, I think consciousness can be shown to be necessary.

In my view there are two cases: In the overwhelming majority of functional systems, I think consciousness is only indirectly necessary, but in a tiny minority of cases, I think consciousness is directly necessary. I’ll try to explain but keep in mind that my explanation will be based on my particular world view which is based on the premise that the only thing real is a single consciousness with its thoughts.

The messages carried by signals in a communication system consist of information. I have divided the notion of information into two types which I call “upward” and “downward”. Downward information is information that is inherent in parts of a system by virtue of its constituents, their arrangements, their positions in space and time, etc. This information “flows” to other parts of the system and thereby directly “causes” the evolution of the system according to the laws of physics. This constitutes the overwhelming majority of cases of the specific behavior of functional systems. It is what you described in your post and what you characterized as serendipity.

Upward information, on the other hand, is information which “flows” to or from a conscious observer. In my view, there is only one such observer, but my idea works just as well if you impute consciousness to, say, human beings.

Note that downward information is symmetric in the sense that the sender and receiver are both the same kind of thing, viz. (physical) components of a system. But upward information is asymmetric in that the sender (or receiver) is the consciousness while the receiver (or sender) is part of a (physical) system. So we have three cases to explore.

I have already described the first case, of downward information, being largely what you described in your post and which is the principal (if not the exclusive) interest of science. Now for the other two (in my view more interesting) cases.

The case of information flowing from physical systems to consciousness begins with perception. The only complication or disagreement here is that I say that there is only and exactly one perceiver while most people say that each individual human can perceive. For the purposes of this post I will defer to them and it won’t matter to the argument.

An example of this case would be a driver of a car noticing a red traffic light. The driver perceives the red patch, but more than that, it is interpreted as a signal to stop the car. There is a vast gulf between the simple perception and the interpretation of the signal.

The case of information flowing the other way, i.e. from consciousness to a physical system is at the heart of the contention of this whole subject. That is, can conscious intent affect physical systems at all? And, if so how? My answer, which I hope will clear up the muddle I have made of the topic of semantics, is the following:

Since the laws of physics cannot be broken, any such influence will have to be via some gap in physical causality. There is such a gap: quantum “randomness”. If the physical system were rigged with some specific sensitivity, such as the apparatus for the Schroedinger’s Cat experiment, then by consciously choosing the outcome of certain quantum events, macro physical effects could be achieved without breaking the laws of physics. Let’s suppose, for the sake of this post, that such a sensitive structure is present in the brain (My bet is that it is the dimers’ orientations in the neuronal micro-tubules as described by Penrose and Hameroff).

Returning to the example of the driver of the car, when the information about the red light is perceived, processes, which might be a complex mix of physical, conscious, sub-conscious, and unconscious processes (whatever each of those things is), result in the intention to stop the car. This intention is part of consciousness, which for now I will agree is a brain state. The intention is acted out by the action of free will choosing the outcome of the triggering quantum states which results in a cascade of physical actions (which would seem puzzlingly serendipitous if that’s all you saw) ultimately resulting in the driver’s leg lifting and then the foot pressing on the brake pedal. (My view is not much different. I have the one consciousness “driving” the brain and body much like the human drives the car.)

Now, to tie this to semantics. Here, the downward information is more complicated so I’ll leave it to last. The semantics involved in the perception of the red light is the interpretation of that color in that place to “mean” ‘stop the car’. That meaning involves a complex history of other people, other cars, someone’s solution to the problem of traffic accidents at intersections, traffic laws, etc. etc. That “meaning” is the very definition of semantics.

In the other direction, the semantics of the signaling by the free will to step on the brake has got to be complex as well. It would involve Schroedinger-Cat-type-structures in the brain that would do all the triggering for a complex set of muscle movements. “Knowing” exactly which sensitive quantum event outcomes will produce the required action is nothing more than semantics. It is the knowledge that certain outcomes mean certain corresponding actions.

Now to understand why I say that consciousness is involved in the semantics of downward information, we have to make some further inferences from my initial premise of only a single consciousness. The first inference is that physical reality (just as Berkeley proposed) is a set of thoughts in this consciousness. We know (or strongly suspect) that this set of thoughts is consistent, i.e. that the physical world does not contain contradictions. We also know that the formal body of mathematics (to the best of our knowledge) is also consistent. And finally, we know that the physical world behaves (with the possible exception of quantum randomness) according to mathematical principles.

It seems obvious to me that the next inference we can make is that the one consciousness consciously and deliberately decided or chose to maintain consistency in the evolution (i.e. behavior) of the physical universe. This would be in the same sense in which one decides to play chess. Simply by making this choice, the effects of downward information serendipitously make a huge number of complex systems run their staggeringly awesome courses, from galaxies to economies to cells to atoms, seemingly unattended by consciousness. And, I think for the most part, these actions are all unattended by consciousness. The semantics comes in at the very beginning when the choice was made for the system to remain consistent and when the initial conditions were established. From then on it has been pretty much as Newton described it: a complex machine that was designed, built, wound up, and then left to run unattended.

This latter, serendipitous, picture describes almost all of the universe we see. There is only a relatively infinitesimal part of the picture, such as the actions of bulldozers and beavers, which have changed part of the physical system in response to deliberate conscious choice.

I hope that helps, and I hope it wasn’t too long.

Paul
 
  • #15
I would like to hear more of your ideas Paul but perhaps this thread is not the appropriate place. Could you start another one ?

I too think much in the same manner as you except my driver is only a passenger I interact with, like a co driver in a rally type situation making me aware of hazards in the road from a pre knowledge of having driven it with someone else before. I choose whether to accept his advice or not based on a unique developed "self" which has formed according to experiences and interactions with others since birth.

p.s...I do have both hands firmly on the wheel at all times ;)
 
  • #16
spicerack said:
I would like to hear more of your ideas Paul but perhaps this thread is not the appropriate place. Could you start another one ?
Thank you. I agree this is not the place. Rather than starting another thread, why don't you start by reading some of my essays at paulandellen.com/essays/essays.htm and let me know what you think by email? I don't think there is much interest in my ideas on this forum.

spicerack said:
I too think much in the same manner as you except my driver is only a passenger I interact with, like a co driver in a rally type situation making me aware of hazards in the road from a pre knowledge of having driven it with someone else before. I choose whether to accept his advice or not based on a unique developed "self" which has formed according to experiences and interactions with others since birth.

p.s...I do have both hands firmly on the wheel at all times ;)
I think our views are quite different. Read my essays and we can talk.

Paul
 
  • #17
Paul Martin said:
Will someone please explain why QM randomness is not clear evidence that causal gaps exist in physics? If causation is probabilistic, then the question is left begging about how quantum events are determined. This would tell me that physics is closed neither causally nor explanatorily. If quantum randomness is a “stopgap to be filled by hidden physical variables” then physics is not explanatorily closed and we can say nothing about causal closure. In my view, quantum randomness should be taken as proof that causality is not closed in physics.

I don't think you really understand QM. It is a completely causal theory. The previous state of the system causally (unitarily) sets up the eigenvalues, and our observations act causally on the set of eigenvalues to select one (or in some cases a continuous subrange). It is true that "we cannot know" which eigenvalue will be selected ahead of time but that is not a faliure of causality. It just is not true that in quantum physics "everything is random", any more than it is true that in relativity "everything is relative".
 
  • #18
Consequences of a single consciousness

StatusX said:
...could someone explain exactly what the consequences of a single consciousness theory would be? I just don't understand how it is any different from a many consciousness theory, except for some differences in terms.
I may not be able to explain it exactly, but I can tell you what I think.

If there is but a single consciousness, then it is clear that it is not closely tied to any particular brain. That would mean that it could have existed prior to the emergence of biological life. That would make it easy to explain cosmic origins and the emergence of life because a conscious agent could be posited and which would be in a position to do some choosing and designing and experimenting. And, we wouldn't have to explain the emergence of consciousness in biology because it isn't there.

If there are multiple consciousnesses, it seems likely that they are associated with live functioning brains. This would mean that there was no consciousness prior to the emergence of biological life, unless of course, there were a second kind of consciousness. That complicates things. In that case we would have two "hard problems" to unravel. If there isn't a second kind of consciousness, then we have the problem of explaining the origin of the cosmos, the emergence of biological life, and the emergence of consciousness in the absence of an agent able to choose, design, experiment, etc.

I think the problems in the multiple consciousness case are much harder than those in the single consciousness case.

Paul
 
  • #19
selfAdjoint said:
I don't think you really understand QM.
You got that right. I'm here to learn.
selfAdjoint said:
...our observations act causally on the set of eigenvalues to select one (or in some cases a continuous subrange).
So our observations, in part, cause the selection. Okay.
selfAdjoint said:
It is true that "we cannot know" which eigenvalue will be selected ahead of time
So our observations help cause the selection but we can't predict the outcome. Okay.
selfAdjoint said:
but that is not a faliure of causality.
It isn't? I suppose you're right: it isn't a failure of causality, but it sure sounds like a gap in causality. If QM could explain how that eigenvalue got selected even though we still couldn't predict it, then I would say there would be no causal gap. It would be like the result of throwing a die. We can't predict the outcome, but we can certainly understand how the face is chosen as a result of the geometry of the die and the evolution of its position and momentum as it dissipates its kinetic energy bouncing around on the table. We know what causes the eventual orientation of the die even though we can't predict it. If you could explain at the same level how the observation "causes" the eigenvalue to be chosen, then I would admit that QM is causally closed. Until then, I see a clear causal gap in QM.
selfAdjoint said:
It just is not true that in quantum physics "everything is random"
I agree. I never said that in quantum physics "everything is random" and I don't believe anything I have ever said could be construed that way.

Paul
 
  • #20
Paul

Still considering your ideas above, but a note on my objection - I didn't mean to suggest that consciousness is not necessary to the formation/operation of complex functional systems, only that it can not be shown to be necessary, which is a slightly different thing.

In fact I also would argue that consciousness, for biological systems at least, would be the best explanation of the innate tendency towards survival, growth and increasing complexity that they exhibit. Staurt Kaufman writes ""There’s a price to pay in becoming more complex; the system is more likely to break, for instance. We need a reason why biological systems become more complex through time. It must be very simple and it must be very deep." (in ‘Complexity' – Roger Lewin p 132) What could be more simple and more deep than consciousness?
 
  • #21
selfAdjoint said:
I don't think you really understand QM. It is a completely causal theory. The previous state of the system causally (unitarily) sets up the eigenvalues, and our observations act causally on the set of eigenvalues to select one (or in some cases a continuous subrange). It is true that "we cannot know" which eigenvalue will be selected ahead of time but that is not a faliure of causality. It just is not true that in quantum physics "everything is random", any more than it is true that in relativity "everything is relative".
An observation acts causally? I can never quite get the hang of what QM says about this. Does it have to be a conscious observation? What causes the observation? Does this support the idea that consciousness is necessary to explain causation?

How does the observation of the new state of the system cause that state? Until we observe the system in that new state then it is not observable in that state. That is, it takes a finite time for information to travel from what is being observed to the observer. This means that to observe a selected eigenvalue that eigenvalue must have already been selected prior to the observation. How is this explained in QM?
 
Last edited:
  • #22
Canute said:
I didn't mean to suggest that consciousness is not necessary to the formation/operation of complex functional systems, only that it can not be shown to be necessary, which is a slightly different thing.
Sorry for missing that distinction. I agree. Furthermore, after thinking about it a little, I would say that nothing whatsoever can be shown. Things can be experienced and at best maybe suggested. But not shown.
 
  • #23
A little off topic and out of order but this is for information only. I thought it might be interesting.

Earlier I asked about the relationship between panexperientialism and microphenomenalism. I’ve done a bit a checking and microphenomenalism seems to be equivalent to panexperientialism, and also to panpsychism. (Perhaps some forms of these doctrines are not equivalent, but in their core assertions they appear to be).

Edward Barkin, in an article for the ‘Journal of Consciousness Studies’ (V.10 No. 8. 2003) writes of microphenomenalism (as proposed by Chalmers) - "Essentially, the idea is that a quantum particle such as an electron could be viewed as possessing intrinsic microphenomenal properties which underly its basic physical properties such as mass and charge."

Relevant to the discussion here is this comment - "Critics of this type of approach, such as Searle, harp on the panpsychism related worry that objects like electrons could not be meaningfully said to have mental ‘experience’ in any appropriate sense of the word; however, Chalmers is willing to deflate the idea of a mind appropriately and Bolender similarly points out that there is a useful distinction that can be made between a simple subject of experience and an actual mind."

He goes on to point out that such an idea has serious problems and proposes macrophenomenalism (phenomenalism for short). He writes "In light of the highly problematic nature of both materialism and dualism, phenomenalism could well eventually prove to be more plausible than either. "

He goes on "The history of Western philosophy is filled with discussion, in one guise or another, of what is often called the ‘transcendental’ subject and object. The terms invoke the idea of a hidden self behind the phenomenal self and a hidden object behind the phenomenal object. Although Kant positioned the transcendental ‘things-in-themselves’ as methodological concepts rather than as metaphysical entities, the tendency since Kant has often been to reify them and then debate their objective existence. Idealists have typically wanted to exclude the transcendental object from philosophical discussion on the grounds of its alleged non-existence, while materialists have generally wanted to exclude the trancendental subject on the same grounds.

The idea behind modern phenomenalism would be that neither the transcendental object or subject exists in any concrete sense. Instead, one would postulate various possible combinations of phenomenal objects, the most coherent, complex and structured of which could be viewable as constituting emergent conceptual minds such as our own. In this case, the universe could be seen as fundamentally rooted in phenomena or mind.

As a result, there would be a tendency to reify mental phenomena, as in Berkeleian objective substance monism. However, I would argue that to do so would be as much of a mistake as to reify physical entities, since even the most basic mental properties can be shown to have a conceptual, and hence relative, non-objective aspect. In this idea’s original context, mainstream Buddhist philosophy, one would say that the reason to avoid endowing anything, including a qualatitive state or a self, with the property of intrinsic, independent reality is that no object can be logically established without implicit or explicit reference to the causes and conditions which enable it to exist - including its parts and attributes and the very fact that a consciousness is required to mentally designate it a distinct entity in the first place. This principle is known as ‘dependent origination’ or ‘the interdependent nature of reality’.

I cannot find this article online but it’s worth a read. It is relevant to this thread in many ways, e.g. on the subject/object issue and the boundedness of consciousness issue. On the self Barkin writes - "Effectively, there is a new subject at every moment one isolates where an appearance of an object arises; and the self at any given moment is just another appearance that arises. Thus, the enduring subject-in-time self-coheres only insofar as the various isolated moments share phenomenal content and the self is being mentally designated as an object".

Panpsychism, the modern version of hylozoism, seems also to be equivalent to panexperientialism. In JCS again (Vol.10 No. 3, 2003) David Skrbina reviews the history of this view, in which all things have a mind, or mind-like quality. Although out of favour for a while the author writes "In the past few years, however, panpsychism has once more become the topic of serious philosophical debate."

He notes, and this seems relevant here, that panpsychism is not a theory of mind per se, but a meta-theory. Thus it could apply, as a framework, to virtually any conventional theory of mind. The article reviews the history of panpsychism from pre-Socratic times to the present.

"At present we can discern at least five active lines of enquiry: (1) the ‘quantum physics’ approach, as developed by Bohm, Seager, Hameroff, and others; (2) the information theory’ approach, arising from the work of Bateson, Wheeler, Bohm and Chalmers; (3) the ‘process philosophy’ view, as conceived by Bergson and Whithead, and developed by Hartshorne, Griffin, and others; (4) the ‘part-whole hierarchy’, as envisioned by Cardano and elaborated by Koestler and Wilbur; and (5) the ‘nonlinear dynamics’ approach, as originated by Peirce and developed by Skrbina… They hold out the hope to resolve otherwise intractible problems of emergentism and mechanism, especially when so many conventional approaches have reached a dead end. As Nagel, Searle, Strawson, and others have noted, the problem of mind and consciousness are so difficult, so intractible, that ‘drastic actions’ are warranted - perhaps even as drastic as panpsychism."

Skyrbina ends with a quote from Empedocles:

"It thou shouldst plant these things in thy firm understanding and contemplate them with good will and unclouded attention, they will stand by thee forever every one, and thou shalt gain many other things from them;... for know that all things have wisdom and a portion of thought."
 
Last edited:
  • #24
selfAdjoint said:
I don't think you really understand QM. It is a completely causal theory. The previous state of the system causally (unitarily) sets up the eigenvalues, and our observations act causally on the set of eigenvalues to select one (or in some cases a continuous subrange).

Well, something seems to have selected one by the time it is observed.

It is true that "we cannot know" which eigenvalue will be selected ahead of time but that is not a faliure of causality.

It could be, for all we know. It might be hidden variables, it might be really random.
 
  • #25
Paul Martin said:
If there is but a single consciousness, then it is clear that it is not closely tied to any particular brain. That would mean that it could have existed prior to the emergence of biological life. That would make it easy to explain cosmic origins and the emergence of life because a conscious agent could be posited and which would be in a position to do some choosing and designing and experimenting.

But wouldn't be in a position to act naturally in the world, the way you and I do, since It would not be incarnated in a body. So you have to assume that,
contrary to the evidence there is a single Consciousness, and, contrary
to the evidence, consciousness of such a nature that it can act
directly and miraculously wihout a physical vehicle.

If there are multiple consciousnesses, it seems likely that they are associated with live functioning brains.

And if there is a single Consciousness that doesn't need physical vehicles,
why would it even seem that there are multiple consciousnesses ?

This would mean that there was no consciousness prior to the emergence of biological life, unless of course, there were a second kind of consciousness. That complicates things. In that case we would have two "hard problems" to unravel.

But we still have one Hard Problem if we posit a single universal Consciousness...and we still have one Hard Problem if we posit multiple
personal consciousnesses without a single universal Consciousness.

So, as far as answering the mind-body problem goes, the hypothesis of
a single consciouness doesn't seem to add anything ...

If there isn't a second kind of consciousness, then we have the problem of explaining the origin of the cosmos, the emergence of biological life, and the emergence of consciousness in the absence of an agent able to choose, design, experiment, etc.

...but we can explain a lot of other problems...so long as we attribute to universal Consciousness all sorts of things which have nothing to do with ordinary everyday consciousness...and we don't ask any awkward questions
like "who created God" ...sorry, I mean "Who created the universal Consciousness".
 
Last edited:
  • #26
Canute said:
An observation acts causally?

Interacts..obervation is not ghostly.

I can never quite get the hang of what QM says about this. Does it have to be a conscious observation?

There is no firm reason to suppose that.

How does the observation of the new state of the system cause that state? Until we observe the system in that new state then it is not observable in that state. That is, it takes a finite time for information to travel from what is being observed to the observer. This means that to observe a selected eigenvalue that eigenvalue must have already been selected prior to the observation. How is this explained in QM?

If observation means interaction with a piece of apparatus it is not a problem.
 
  • #27
Canute said:
cIn fact I also would argue that consciousness, for biological systems at least, would be the best explanation of the innate tendency towards survival, growth and increasing omplexity that they exhibit. Staurt Kaufman writes ""There’s a price to pay in becoming more complex; the system is more likely to break, for instance. We need a reason why biological systems become more complex through time.

Mechanical systems become more prone to break. Organic systems are characterised
by redundancy, homeostasis, etc.
 
  • #28
Tournesol,

I have responded to your post concerning the implications of a single consciousness in a new thread in the Metaphysics and Epistemology forum.

Paul
 
  • #29
Tournesol

Couple of comments on your posts. The reason that positing a single substrate underlying individual appearnaces of consciousness is that it changes the mind-brain 'hard' problem into a different problem, one that is not so intractible. It allows mind and brain to be approached in a different way, one in which mind-brain interaction is mediated by a common 'substance'. This is what James meant here:

"[t]he attributes "subject" and "object," "represented" and "representative," "thing" and "thought" mean then a practical distinction of the utmost importance, but a distinction which is of a FUNCTIONAL order only, and not at all ontological as understood by classical dualism." ('The Notion of Consciousness')

In this view the reason that we cannot solve the mind-brain problem is that we are basing our tentative solutions on an incorrect assumption.

You say the timing problem in QM (the timing of the observation relative to the collapse of the probability wave that is observed) is not a problem. I think you'll find that it is a serious and as yet unsolved problem.

The fact that biological systems are characterised by redundancy, homeostasis etc. is quite clear but not relevant. Kaufman's comment was specifically about such biological systems.
 
  • #30
Canute said:
Couple of comments on your posts. The reason that positing a single substrate underlying individual appearnaces of consciousness is that it changes the mind-brain 'hard' problem into a different problem, one that is not so intractible.

I fail to see how. The boundedness issue surely gets worse.

It allows mind and brain to be approached in a different way, one in which mind-brain interaction is mediated by a common 'substance'.

The common-substance idea seems quite separate from the single-consciousness idea. Materialism is monism too.

"[t]he attributes "subject" and "object," "represented" and "representative," "thing" and "thought" mean then a practical distinction of the utmost importance, but a distinction which is of a FUNCTIONAL order only, and not at all ontological as understood by classical dualism." ('The Notion of Consciousness')

Again, you can reject dualism without embracing idealism.

In this view the reason that we cannot solve the mind-brain problem is that we are basing our tentative solutions on an incorrect assumption.

I still fail to see how your alternative helps.

You say the timing problem in QM (the timing of the observation relative to the collapse of the probability wave that is observed) is not a problem. I think you'll find that it is a serious and as yet unsolved problem.

There may be a problem as to where exactly (and indeed, if) collapses occurs
between instrument and human observer, but there is still no reason to
think there is anything special about human observation.

The fact that biological systems are characterised by redundancy, homeostasis etc. is quite clear but not relevant. Kaufman's comment was specifically about such biological systems.

It is difficult to see how it could have been. Redundancy (etc) is the answer
to the question: "how does a system become more complex without becoming more fragile?"
 
  • #31
Tournesol said:
I fail to see how. The boundedness issue surely gets worse.
No, it doesn't get better or worse, it gets different. It would mean that individual consciousness is, at a base level, not bounded. Or rather, individual conscious is bounded, but that boundedness evaporates once that individuality is transcended. It would mean that ontologically, in the last analysis, all individual consciousnesses are the same consciousness, just as all the twigs on a tree are the same tree. [/quote]

The common-substance idea seems quite separate from the single-consciousness idea. Materialism is monism too.
The suggestion is that consciousness is the common substance. Perhaps you have an idea of a different common substance but it's hard to see what it might be. The idea of a single consciousness appears to be monism, and perhaps in Paul's version it is. However in my view monism is dualism in disguise and so gives rise to the same philosophical problems. When I say 'one consciousness' I mean that this is one way of characterising something that cannot properly be characterised as either one or many, but in many situations it can be considered as one for theoretical purposes.

Again, you can reject dualism without embracing idealism.
Idealism is dualism, in Berkeley's version anyway. It rests on a fundamental ontological distinction between perceiver and perceived. This is why he needed God in his theory as well as perceiver and perceived for it to work. This was James's point in that quote. He was suggesting that the poles of all such dualisms/antimonies/opposites reduce at a meta-level to something that is not dual.

I still fail to see how your alternative helps.
At the moment we try to explain mind-brain as if they were the two fundamental substances or as if one of them were. This has so far proved impossible. If there is a third term involved a quite different kind of theory becomes possible and we are offered a means of escaping from the longstanding philosophical deadlock. (Philosopher Charles Peirce argued that for logical reasons three terms were required in order to explain anything - I think he was right).

There may be a problem as to where exactly (and indeed, if) collapses occurs between instrument and human observer, but there is still no reason to
think there is anything special about human observation.
I didn't suggest that there was anything special about human observation. I suggested that there is something paradoxical about the idea that something can be observed before it has been rendered observable by being observed.

It is difficult to see how it could have been. Redundancy (etc) is the answer to the question: "how does a system become more complex without becoming more fragile?"
Yes, but that is not the question Kaufman was addressing. A biological system generally becomes more liable to break as it becomes more complex. This was the issue Kaufman's was addressing, and the point of his comment. He was pondering on why biological systems become more complex under these circumstances, not on how. Perhaps this brings us full circle to Rosenberg's ideas about causation.
 
Last edited:
  • #32
Canute said:
The suggestion is that consciousness is the common substance. Perhaps you have an idea of a different common substance but it's hard to see what it might be. The idea of a single consciousness appears to be monism, and perhaps in Paul's version it is. However in my view monism is dualism in disguise and so gives rise to the same philosophical problems. When I say 'one consciousness' I mean that this is one way of characterising something that cannot properly be characterised as either one or many, but in many situations it can be considered as one for theoretical purposes.

If the underlying substrate is not one or many, it's certainly confusing to call it one consciousness!

Canute said:
Idealism is dualism, in Berkeley's version anyway. It rests on a fundamental ontological distinction between perceiver and perceived. This is why he needed God in his theory as well as perceiver and perceived for it to work. This was James's point in that quote. He was suggesting that the poles of all such dualisms/antimonies/opposites reduce at a meta-level to something that is not dual.

At the moment we try to explain mind-brain as if they were the two fundamental substances or as if one of them were. This has so far proved impossible. If there is a third term involved a quite different kind of theory becomes possible and we are offered a means of escaping from the longstanding philosophical deadlock. (Philosopher Charles Peirce argued that for logical reasons three terms were required in order to explain anything - I think he was right).

What you are discussing sounds like neutral monism, and in the last century is mostly identified with James and Russell. A very good historical look at efforts to develop this (in Western philosophy anyway) is in this Stanford Encyclopedia entry.

The benefit of the approach is that it tries to address the hard problem by proposing an underlying substrate which underlies both mind and matter, but of course the hard part is providing an explanation for how this works. I've thought in recent times that the challenges faced by these efforts is the degree to which they are based on a "substance" ontology. Explaining how one substance, neutral or otherwise, gives rise to a different one is not significantly easier than Descartes' trying to explain how mind and body interact in his dualism.

By moving to a process or event ontology, we might have a better chance to construct a theory of why the causal network of events can give rise to the phenomena we know as the physical and the experiential. Maybe they are different perspectives on the same causal chain. Rosenberg's effort is in this spirit.
 
  • #33
Canute said:
No, it doesn't get better or worse, it gets different. It would mean that individual consciousness is, at a base level, not bounded. Or rather, individual conscious is bounded, but that boundedness evaporates once that individuality is transcended. It would mean that ontologically, in the last analysis, all individual consciousnesses are the same consciousness, just as all the twigs on a tree are the same tree.

So consciousness is somehow not really bounded but somehow seems to be ?
That just seem muddled.

The suggestion is that consciousness is the common substance.

Common to what ? Mind and matter ? Isn't consc. the same thign as Mind ?

Perhaps you have an idea of a different common substance but it's hard to see what it might be.

The only substance for which there is any evidence is matter.

The idea of a single consciousness appears to be monism, and perhaps in Paul's version it is. However in my view monism is dualism in disguise and so gives rise to the same philosophical problems. When I say 'one consciousness' I mean that this is one way of characterising something that cannot properly be characterised as either one or many, but in many situations it can be considered as one for theoretical purposes.

That is very unclear.

Idealism is dualism, in Berkeley's version anyway. It rests on a fundamental ontological distinction between perceiver and perceived. This is why he needed God in his theory as well as perceiver and perceived for it to work. This was James's point in that quote. He was suggesting that the poles of all such dualisms/antimonies/opposites reduce at a meta-level to something that is not dual.

Dualism means there are fundamentally different *kinds* of things. The perceiver/perceived dichotomy only requires different individual things;
they may be of the same kind.

At the moment we try to explain mind-brain as if they were the two fundamental substances or as if one of them were. This has so far proved impossible. If there is a third term involved a quite different kind of theory becomes possible and we are offered a means of escaping from the longstanding philosophical deadlock. (Philosopher Charles Peirce argued that for logical reasons three terms were required in order to explain anything - I think he was right).

it is yet to become clear *how* the thord term resolves the alleged problem.


I didn't suggest that there was anything special about human observation. I suggested that there is something paradoxical about the idea that something can be observed before it has been rendered observable by being observed.

I don't see why there should be a problem about something being observable before it is observed, any more than there is a problem about somethig being edible before it is eaten.

Yes, but that is not the question Kaufman was addressing. A biological system generally becomes more liable to break as it becomes more complex.

I don't see any evidence for that.
 
  • #34
It seems the discussion here is dying down, and in any case, we've strayed a fair bit from the content of chapter 7. I'll work on getting a summary of chapter 8 up over the next few days.
 

FAQ: Chapter 7: Paradoxes for Liberal Naturalism

1. What is "Chapter 7: Paradoxes for Liberal Naturalism" about?

"Chapter 7: Paradoxes for Liberal Naturalism" is a section of a book or article that discusses the potential contradictions or challenges to the philosophy of liberal naturalism. It examines how certain paradoxes or dilemmas may arise when trying to reconcile the principles of naturalism with the values of liberalism.

2. What is liberal naturalism?

Liberal naturalism is a philosophical approach that combines the principles of liberalism, which prioritize individual rights and freedoms, with the principles of naturalism, which emphasize the scientific understanding of the natural world. It seeks to find a balance between these two perspectives and apply them to various aspects of society, such as politics, ethics, and social issues.

3. What are some examples of paradoxes for liberal naturalism?

Some examples of paradoxes for liberal naturalism include the tension between individual rights and societal well-being, the conflict between scientific facts and moral values, and the challenge of reconciling personal autonomy with social responsibility. These paradoxes highlight the potential contradictions that may arise when trying to apply both liberal and naturalistic principles to real-world situations.

4. How can these paradoxes be resolved?

There is no one definitive answer to resolving the paradoxes for liberal naturalism, as different philosophers and thinkers may offer different solutions. However, some proposed solutions include finding a middle ground between individual rights and societal well-being, acknowledging the limitations of scientific facts in shaping moral values, and promoting a balance between personal autonomy and social responsibility.

5. What are the implications of these paradoxes for society?

The implications of these paradoxes for society are complex and multifaceted. They may lead to debates and discussions about the role of individual rights and freedoms in relation to the common good, the influence of scientific knowledge on moral values, and the responsibilities of individuals in a society. They may also highlight the need for ongoing critical thinking and reflection when applying philosophical principles to real-world issues.

Back
Top