Completeness axiom as having no holes in the set

  • Thread starter Thread starter Bipolarity
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Axiom Holes Set
Bipolarity
Messages
773
Reaction score
2
Completeness axiom as having "no holes" in the set

My textbook describes the completeness axiom as essential to showing that there are no "holes or gaps" in the real numbers. That is, for any two reals A and B, there exists a real C such that A<C<B.

Of course, we all know that the actual statement of the completeness axiom is that any bounded set of real numbers has a least upper bound.

I was wondering, how can we use the explicit statement of the completeness axiom to show that there are no "holes or gaps" in the reals? Is it possible or did my textbook just use this as an intuitive explanation for the completeness axiom?

Thanks all!

BiP
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org


Bipolarity said:
My textbook describes the completeness axiom as essential to showing that there are no "holes or gaps" in the real numbers. That is, for any two reals A and B, there exists a real C such that A<C<B.

Of course, we all know that the actual statement of the completeness axiom is that any bounded set of real numbers has a least upper bound.

I was wondering, how can we use the explicit statement of the completeness axiom to show that there are no "holes or gaps" in the reals? Is it possible or did my textbook just use this as an intuitive explanation for the completeness axiom?

Thanks all!

BiP

The intuitive textbook explanation is rubbish. Even the rational numbers satisfy that between any two points A and B, there exists a rational C such that A<C<B. And of course, the rational numbers are not complete. So the completeness axiom is not needed at all to show this fact.

Of course, the intuition that complete space has "no holes" is a good intuition. But you should be very careful with specifying what exactly is a "hole".
 


micromass said:
The intuitive textbook explanation is rubbish. Even the rational numbers satisfy that between any two points A and B, there exists a rational C such that A<C<B. And of course, the rational numbers are not complete. So the completeness axiom is not needed at all to show this fact.

Of course, the intuition that complete space has "no holes" is a good intuition. But you should be very careful with specifying what exactly is a "hole".

It must then be the case that I did not comprehend what my textbook meant to be a "hole". So what is the "hole" ? My textbook doesn't explain it, perhaps you might know.

Also, if a set of numbers is complete, then does it necessarily mean that it satisfies the A<C<B property that I outlined above?

BiP
 


Bipolarity said:
It must then be the case that I did not comprehend what my textbook meant to be a "hole". So what is the "hole" ? My textbook doesn't explain it, perhaps you might know.

It's just intuition. I don't think it is meant to be very formal. Maybe you could rigorously define what a "hole" is though.

The idea is the following: consider the following sequence

3,~3.1,~3.14,~3.141,~3.1415,...

This is a sequence of numbers and it appears that as you go through the sequence, you get closer to a certain number. However, if we work in the rationals, then the limit of this sequence (i.e. the number \pi) is not contained in the rationals. So you can get very close to \pi, but you can never actually be \pi. Thus we say that the number \pi is a missing number (or hole). So a missing number is a number that is not in the set but where you can get close to. The completeness axiom states exactly that there are no missing numbers.

Also, if a set of numbers is complete, then does it necessarily mean that it satisfies the A<C<B property that I outlined above?

No: consider [0,1]\cup [2,3]. This is complete, but it doesn't satisfy the above property.
 


Yes the holes the real numbers do not have are equivalently cuts, or limits, or least upper bounds. Just having numbers everywhere is being dense, not complete.
 
Back
Top