Empirical and Definitional Content of Newton's Laws

AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on the definitional and empirical aspects of Newton's laws of motion. It argues that the first two laws primarily define mass and force, lacking empirical predictive power until a specific force law is introduced, such as Newton's law of gravitation. The third law is seen as providing empirical content through its implications for momentum conservation, but only when an inertial frame is established. The conversation highlights differing interpretations of the laws, particularly regarding their testability and the necessity of additional definitions for mass and force. Ultimately, the consensus leans towards viewing Newton's laws as fundamentally definitional until further specifications are made.
madness
Messages
813
Reaction score
69
I'd like to get a better insight into which aspects of Newton's laws are definitional and which are falsifiable. And moreover, of the definitional aspects, why these are good definitions.

Netwon's laws can be phrased as follows (from Wikipedia):

First law: In an inertial frame of reference, an object either remains at rest or continues to move at a constant velocity, unless acted upon by a force.

Second law: In an inertial frame of reference, the vector sum of the forces F on an object is equal to the mass m of that object multiplied by the acceleration a of the object: F = ma.

Third law: When one body exerts a force on a second body, the second body simultaneously exerts a force equal in magnitude and opposite in direction on the first body.

In the first law, neither force nor frame of reference have been defined. In the second law, force is given a relationship to mass and acceleration. We might presume that acceleration can be measured and needs no definition. However, mass and force are defined through this equation as far as I understand. Therefore, the first and second law can't yet make any empirical predictions, as we still have two unknown quantities for each measurement of acceleration. In other words, the first two laws (along with the definition of an inertial frame) define mass and force. The third law implicitly tells us that bodies can apply forces to each other (which wasn't apparent from the first two laws), but more explicitly it adds a constraint of reciprocity between the forces of interacting bodies. This still doesn't seem to provide any empirical content given that force and mass are underdetermined from measurements of acceleration according to these laws. However, once we finally posit a functional form for force, for example via Netwon's law of gravitation, it looks as though we have something empirically testable - that is, using measurements of acceleration, we can falsify the theory. So would it be correct to state that Newton's 3 laws are purely definitional, and that only with the additional specification of further laws defining the forces do they become testable? If so, can we claim that this choice of definitions is a good one, as opposed to some other choice?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
madness said:
So would it be correct to state that Newton's 3 laws are purely definitional, and that only with the additional specification of further laws defining the forces do they become testable?
There is a considerable amount of differing opinions on the topic in the literature, so I think you have some flexibility in your preference. I have never seen anyone go as far as to say that all three together are definitional with no experimental content.

My personal preference is to consider the first law as defining an inertial frame, and the second law as defining a force. Then the third law is experimentally testable and contains the physical content of Newton’s laws
 
  • Like
Likes hutchphd and madness
Dale said:
There is a considerable amount of differing opinions on the topic in the literature, so I think you have some flexibility in your preference. I have never seen anyone go as far as to say that all three together are definitional with no experimental content.

My personal preference is to consider the first law as defining an inertial frame, and the second law as defining a force. Then the third law is experimentally testable and contains the physical content of Newton’s laws

As far as I can see, the third law only becomes empirically testable once a force law has been introduced (e.g., Netwon's law of gravitation). Even then, Newton's law of gravitation appears to entail Newton's third law by symmetry. Before a force law has been introduced, it seems that Newton's third law acts more as a constraint on the possible kinds of force laws that one could postulate.
 
madness said:
However, mass and force are defined through this equation as far as I understand.
That's a matter of interpretation. One could also assume force to be already defined, for example in terms of Hooke's Law.
 
madness said:
As far as I can see, the third law only becomes empirically testable once a force law has been introduced (e.g., Netwon's law of gravitation).
I have never seen any reference that makes this claim. Have you?
 
A.T. said:
That's a matter of interpretation. One could also assume force to be already defined, for example in terms of Hooke's Law.

Sure, there are laws which define force in specific scenarios, such as Hooke's law, Newton's law of gravitation, or Maxwell's laws of electromagnetism. Yet Newton's laws are taken to be true for all forces. In this sense they feel like a framework for defining concepts of mass and force - the mass of an object is assumed to be the same across all kinds of force, in which case the goal is to find theories which describe forces in various situations using the definitions in Netwon's first two laws. Newton's third law tells us that we should only look for theories of forces which obey a certain symmetry.

We could instead start with Hooke's law, then arrive at a concept of mass and intertial frame using Newton's first two laws. Perhaps by comparing objects of different masses we might even arrive at a uniquely specifying account of the mass of each object by that definition. Then we could assume that Hooke's law is specific only to one particular scenario, but that Newton's 3 laws are more general, and start to search for theories of forces in other scenarios.

To my mind the two approaches look like the same thing.
 
Dale said:
I have never seen any reference that makes this claim. Have you?

No, but it seems like something which can be reasoned directly from the laws themselves. The first two laws tell us that F=ma. If we assume that we can only measure a (or even also position and velocity), then Newton's third law doesn't make any testable predictions. Only when we write down an equation for the dependence of F on position (and other variables) does something testable emerge.
 
madness said:
No, but it seems like something which can be reasoned directly from the laws themselves.
That isn’t the standard here on PF. We require that all posts be consistent with the professional scientific literature. Your personal reasoning is not acceptable if it is inconsistent with the literature.

Here is an example I like.

https://www.worldscientific.com/doi/pdf/10.1142/9789810248154_0001

Calkin does not seem to share your opinion.
 
Dale said:
That isn’t the standard here on PF. We require that all posts be consistent with the professional scientific literature. Your personal reasoning is not acceptable if it is inconsistent with the literature.

Fair enough, no need to get your knickers in a twist!

Dale said:
Here is an example I like.

https://www.worldscientific.com/doi/pdf/10.1142/9789810248154_0001

Calkin does not seem to share your opinion.
If I understand correctly, what your reference tells us is that for an isolated pair of particles the ratio of accelerations should be constant according to Newton's third law. Indeed that would imply some empirical content in the 3rd law.
 
  • #10
madness said:
for an isolated pair of particles the ratio of accelerations should be constant according to Newton's third law
Yes, and regardless of the nature of the interaction.
 
  • #11
madness said:
In the first law, neither force nor frame of reference have been defined.

For mass and force Newton provided definitions. But they are not very useful.

He introduced frames of references in a different chapter prior to the laws of motion. It is quite long-winded and cannot be summarized in a handy definition. It is mainly about an absolute frame of reference (defined by the fixed stars) and moving frames of reference that cannot be distinguished from the absolute frame by experimental observations. This is quite similar to inertial frams of reference as we know them today. If you read the laws of motion without this background, inertial frames are indeed not yet defined with the first two laws.

madness said:
In other words, the first two laws (along with the definition of an inertial frame) define mass and force.

The first two laws (in the wording you mentioned them above) are not sufficient for an implicit definition of mass, force or inertial frames. The third law and some additional restrictions (e.g. principle of relativity and isotropy) are required as well.

madness said:
The third law implicitly tells us that bodies can apply forces to each other (which wasn't apparent from the first two laws), but more explicitly it adds a constraint of reciprocity between the forces of interacting bodies. This still doesn't seem to provide any empirical content given that force and mass are underdetermined from measurements of acceleration according to these laws.

Newton supported the 3rd law with experimental observations showing that momentum is conserved. This is empirical content.

madness said:
However, once we finally posit a functional form for force, for example via Netwon's law of gravitation

The law of gravitation is based on the definition of force. It is not part of the definition.

madness said:
So would it be correct to state that Newton's 3 laws are purely definitional, and that only with the additional specification of further laws defining the forces do they become testable?

It is definitional in the sense that it distinguishes forces from fictious forces. But conservation of momentum is not definitional. That can be tested by experiments.
 
  • #12
Dale said:
Yes, and regardless of the nature of the interaction.
DrStupid said:
For mass and force Newton provided definitions. But they are not very useful.

He introduced frames of references in a different chapter prior to the laws of motion. It is quite long-winded and cannot be summarized in a handy definition. It is mainly about an absolute frame of reference (defined by the fixed stars) and moving frames of reference that cannot be distinguished from the absolute frame by experimental observations. This is quite similar to inertial frams of reference as we know them today. If you read the laws of motion without this background, inertial frames are indeed not yet defined with the first two laws.
The first two laws (in the wording you mentioned them above) are not sufficient for an implicit definition of mass, force or inertial frames. The third law and some additional restrictions (e.g. principle of relativity and isotropy) are required as well.
Newton supported the 3rd law with experimental observations showing that momentum is conserved. This is empirical content.
The law of gravitation is based on the definition of force. It is not part of the definition.
It is definitional in the sense that it distinguishes forces from fictious forces. But conservation of momentum is not definitional. That can be tested by experiments.

In response to both posts, I have one final question. It seems that Newton's third law only has testable content if we can independently verify that we are in an intertial frame of reference. Ratios of acceleration are not constant in a non-inertial frame, and nor is momentum conserved. Newton's three laws (in the form that I originally posted them) don't seem to provide a way to test whether we are in an intertial frame other than by checking if momentum is conserved. That would make the three laws purely definitional. On the other hand DrStupid mentioned an independent definition of intertial frames relative to the "fixed stars". If we allow for that, then we would have testable predictions from Newton's third law. Is this correct?
 
  • #13
madness said:
Newton's three laws (in the form that I originally posted them) don't seem to provide a way to test whether we are in an intertial frame other than by checking if momentum is conserved. That would make the three laws purely definitional.

Yes, you can define inertial frames this way. But you need to add that the frames of reference must be global because otherwise locally free falling frames of reference would be inertial too. That wouldn't fit well to the law of gravitation which says that gravity is an interactive force. With the definition of a global absolute frame of reference using the fixed stars Newton avoided this problem.
 
  • Like
Likes madness
  • #14
madness said:
Newton's three laws (in the form that I originally posted them) don't seem to provide a way to test whether we are in an intertial frame
The first law is often understood to do exactly that.
 
  • #15
Dale said:
The first law is often understood to do exactly that.

The first law would do that if we independently knew what the forces acting on a body were, but if both force and inertial frame are to be defined through Newton's 3 laws then it doesn't seem there are any testable predictions. Taken in isolation, Newton's first law only defines a relationship between inertial frame and force - using the 1st law alone, given an accelerating object we can't distinguish between the case where we are in a non-inertial frame or the case in which we are in an inertial frame with a force acting on the object.
 
  • #16
madness said:
Taken in isolation, Newton's first law only defines a relationship between inertial frame and force - using the 1st law alone, given an accelerating object we can't distinguish between the case where we are in a non-inertial frame or the case in which we are in an inertial frame with a force acting on the object.

I agree with you, but after a long discussion about this topic I got the impression that the idea that you need the 3rd law to identify inertial frames is not very popular in this forum. However, I didn't got a clear answer how to do it instead.
 
  • #17
I think the logic in a modern formulation is as follows, and I hope, we won't have a big battle about "reference frames" again.

Everything starts with a theory about space and time. In the case of Newtonian physics you have the assumption of "absolute time" and "absolute space". Time is just an oriented one-dimensional differentiable manifold, i.e., after introducing a chart, isomorphic to the real numbers, and absolute space is a Euclidean affine manifold. "Absolute" means that this structure is "rigid" in the sense that no physical process can ever change this spacetime structure.

Then Lex I says that by assumption there exists an inertial frame, and from this of course it follows that there are arbitrary many inertial frames all connected by Galilei transformations from one to another. An inertial frame is thereby defined by Lex I, i.e., that a free body (i.e., a body upon which no forces act) moves rectilinear and uniformly, i.e., with constant velocity.

It was Lange who put this into a non-circular way by showing that you need three free bodies with trajectories moving through a common point which are not along the same line to operationally define an inertial reference frame. To check that it really is one you have to verify that any fouth free body in any direction moves with constant velocity against the so established reference frame.

Lex II then quantifies forces and inertia in the usual way

Lex III is from a modern point of view following from the symmetries of the Galilei-Newtonian spacetime manifold, i.e., from homogeneity of absolute space leading to the necessity that the total momentum of a closed system must be conserved (following from Noether's theorems). In this context the absoluteness of time is also important, because it implies the typically Newtonian idea of "action at a distance". Only then Lex III can be valid for a closed set of point particles alone.

This becomes already clear when you think about Special Relativity theory (SRT). You can get to the idea of SRT by asking how a spacetime model must look like, where you do not necessarily have absolute time and absolute space but only assume the validity of Lex I in the above sense, i.e., the existence of an inertial reference frame and thus arbitrary many moving with constant velocity against each other and otherwise keep the space for any inertial observer as an affine Euclidean manifold. Then the analysis about how to transform from one inertial frame to another leads to either the Galilei transformations or the Poincare transformations. The symmetry group then let's you construct the mathematical structure of the spacetime model. In the case of Galilei transformations you get the fiber-bundel structure of absolute space and time, i.e., Galilei-Newton spacetime and for the Poincare group you get Einstein-Minkowski spacetime of SRT.

It is then an empirical question, which spacetime model fits better with the observations, and it's well known that Einstein-Minkowski spacetime "wins" particularly with respect of electromagnetic phenomena, and that's why Einstein was led to SRT by analyzing the quibble with the lack of Galilei invariance of Maxwell's electromagnetic theory as well as the many null results concerning the existence of an aether (Trouton Noble, Michelson-Morley,...).

Also there is some tension between SRT and Newton's Lex III. The resolution of this tension is that the 10 conservation laws from the spacetime symmetries still hold in SRT as in Newtonian physics but the interactions are localized through the mathematical description of Faraday's important idea of local laws in terms of fields (like in his case the electromagnetic field), i.e., the field is a fundamental entity of nature as is matter and it's a dynamical entity too. Today, the most successful theories are indeed local field-theoretical equations obeying the spacetime structure given by Einstein-Minkowski spacetime, of course in quantized form, i.e., in terms of local relativistic quantum field theory.

The only thing, as far as we know today, that models cannot describe is the gravitational interaction, which needs of course General Relativity.
 
  • Like
  • Love
Likes madness and etotheipi
  • #18
madness said:
The first law would do that if we independently knew what the forces acting on a body were
All that is required is to be able to identify non-interacting bodies. If you can independently know what forces are acting on a body then you can use the motion of interacting bodies to predict what the motion of non-interacting bodies would be.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #19
Well, but even Newton himself was aware of this somewhat "circular" definitions arising from his postulates. Already at his time there was a heavy debate about the question how an inertial frame can be operationally determined. Indeed, the problem with absolute space and absolute time is how to observe them, if apparently one can determine the motion of one body only relative to other bodies. Newton's answer is the famous bucket argument, i.e., that a rotating bucket filled with water shows a parabolic rather than a plane surface due to what we'd call inertial forces today in the rotating frame. On the other hand the question is, "rotating relative to what". And of course in this case the bucket was simply rotating relative to the Earth, which is to some approximation indeed an inertial frame (when taking of course the gravitational force of the Earth on the objects described relative to it into account, and indeed the parabolic shape of the corotating fluid in the bucket is a result of the inertial (centrifugal) force and the gravitational force). Of course on the other hand you can demonstrate, e.g., by the Foucault pendulum experiment that the Earth-fixed frame is of course not really an inertial frame.

At the end of course you always have somehow to operationally define an inertial frame (and thus in fact an entire equivlence class of inertial frames).
 
  • #20
Dale said:
All that is required is to be able to identify non-interacting bodies.

If two non-interacting bodies were accelerating at a constant rate, how would you know whether they were acclerating due to a common force (e.g., gravity) or due to a non-inertial frame of reference?

Dale said:
If you can independently know what forces are acting on a body then you can use the motion of interacting bodies to predict what the motion of non-interacting bodies would be.

I'm not sure if I understand you here. Could you spell it out more clearly?@vanhees71 - Thanks for the informative post, there's a lot for me to unpack there. Are there any references for this kind of approach? I'm still not clear on which parts are simply ironing out mathematical details to provide non-circular definitions versus those parts that make testable empirical predictions.
 
  • #21
madness said:
If two non-interacting bodies were accelerating at a constant rate, how would you know whether they were acclerating due to a common force (e.g., gravity) or due to a non-inertial frame of reference?
If they are affected by Newtonian Gravity, then they aren't non-interacting, because Newtonian Gravity is an interaction force.
 
  • Like
Likes Vanadium 50, etotheipi and Dale
  • #22
A.T. said:
If they are affected by Newtonian Gravity, then they aren't non-interacting, because Newtonian Gravity is an interaction force.

I had taken non-interacting to mean not interacting with each other. Is the intended meaning that no force is acting on either of the bodies?
 
  • #23
madness said:
Sure, there are laws which define force in specific scenarios, such as Hooke's law, Newton's law of gravitation, or Maxwell's laws of electromagnetism.
Yes, just like you have definitions for specific types of energy: kinetic, potential etc.
- To test the Law of Energy Conservation you use specific energy definitions.
- To test Newton's Laws you use specific force definitions.
 
  • Like
Likes etotheipi
  • #24
madness said:
If two non-interacting bodies were accelerating at a constant rate, how would you know whether they were acclerating due to a common force (e.g., gravity) or due to a non-inertial frame of reference?
In this approach (the one I linked to above) the first law says that non-interacting bodies do not accelerate. In standard Newtonian physics gravity is an interaction so a non-interacting body cannot be accelerating due to gravity. In Newton-Cartan theory gravity is geometrized so a non-interacting body can be subject to gravity and is in free fall.

madness said:
I'm not sure if I understand you here. Could you spell it out more clearly?
Suppose that you are on Earth and using standard Newtonian physics where gravity is an interaction. You know that gravitational acceleration is 9.8 m/s^2 downward. So you can drop an uncharged and non-magnetic object and define an inertial frame as one where it accelerates downward at 9.8 m/s^2. It is not a non-interacting object in this situation, but since you know the force on it you can determine what a true standard Newtonian non-interacting object would do.
 
  • Like
Likes etotheipi
  • #25
A.T. said:
Yes, just like you have definitions for specific types of energy: kinetic, potential etc.
- To test the Law of Energy Conservation you use specific energy definitions.
- To test Newton's Laws you use specific force definitions.

Surely that would constitute a test of the conjunction of Newton's laws and those specific force definitions. A falsification would then only falsify Newton's laws OR those specific force definitions.
 
  • #26
On the textbook level the best discussion, though pretty short, is still found in A. Sommerfeld, Lectures on Theoretical Physics, Vol. 1 (Mechanics). There's also a nice discussion in Einstein's two textbooks on special and general relativity.
 
  • Like
Likes etotheipi
  • #27
vanhees71 said:
On the other hand the question is, "rotating relative to what".

Relative to the inertial frame or something that is at rest in an inertial frame.

vanhees71 said:
And of course in this case the bucket was simply rotating relative to the Earth, which is to some approximation indeed an inertial frame (when taking of course the gravitational force of the Earth on the objects described relative to it into account, and indeed the parabolic shape of the corotating fluid in the bucket is a result of the inertial (centrifugal) force and the gravitational force). Of course on the other hand you can demonstrate, e.g., by the Foucault pendulum experiment that the Earth-fixed frame is of course not really an inertial frame.

Newton was aware of it and it doesn't limit the validity of the bucket argument. On very large scales the rotation turns a spherical surface into an ellipsoid. Newton even calculated the oblateness of the Earth due to its rotation for the case of homogeneous density.
 
  • #28
madness said:
Surely that would constitute a test of the conjunction of Newton's laws and those specific force definitions. A falsification would then only falsify Newton's laws OR those specific force definitions.
You cannot falsify definitions.
 
  • #29
A.T. said:
You cannot falsify definitions.

As long as they are not self-contradicting.
 
  • #30
DrStupid said:
Relative to the inertial frame or something that is at rest in an inertial frame.
Newton was aware of it and it doesn't limit the validity of the bucket argument. On very large scales the rotation turns a spherical surface into an ellipsoid. Newton even calculated the oblateness of the Earth due to its rotation for the case of homogeneous density.
I said that Newton was well aware of all this and also about the circularity of his postulates. The point is that at the end you have to operationally define a reference frame that is (to a sufficient accuracy) inertial. You can only calculate the ellipsoidal shape of the idealized Earth due to its rotation by assuming (!) that it rotates relative to some inertial frame. Here a very good approximation for this inertial reference frame is the reference frame defined by the rest frame of the fixed stars.
 
  • Like
Likes etotheipi
  • #31
vanhees71 said:
I said that Newton was well aware of all this and also about the circularity of his postulates.

I do not see the circularity.

vanhees71 said:
You can only calculate the ellipsoidal shape of the idealized Earth due to its rotation by assuming (!) that it rotates relative to some inertial frame.

Why do I need to assume that? I can also calculate the shape assuming that the Earth doesn't rotate. The comparision of the result with experimental observations will show that my assumption was wrong and that the rest frame of Earth is in fact rotating.
 
  • #32
A.T. said:
You cannot falsify definitions.

You seem to have suggested that Newton's law of gravitation, along with Hooke's law etc., are definitions. It seems more plausible to me that Newton's 3 laws are the definitions, in which case these specific force laws are not definitions. We may have some freedom to choose which parts of the theory are definitions and which aren't, but in the end we need to put down a sufficient number of constraints in order to arrive at anything testable.
 
  • #33
Dale said:
In this approach (the one I linked to above) the first law says that non-interacting bodies do not accelerate. In standard Newtonian physics gravity is an interaction so a non-interacting body cannot be accelerating due to gravity.

It says they do not accelerate in an inertial frame. But we still have to figure out whether we are in such a frame. I don't see how we can identify these non-interacting bodies until we decide whether we are in an inertial frame of reference.

Dale said:
Suppose that you are on Earth and using standard Newtonian physics where gravity is an interaction. You know that gravitational acceleration is 9.8 m/s^2 downward. So you can drop an uncharged and non-magnetic object and define an inertial frame as one where it accelerates downward at 9.8 m/s^2. It is not a non-interacting object in this situation, but since you know the force on it you can determine what a true standard Newtonian non-interacting object would do.

Sure, we have agreed already that once you already have knowledge of the external force you can resolve these things. But that isn't given by Newton's laws.
 
  • #34
madness said:
It seems more plausible to me that Newton's 3 laws are the definitions, in which case these specific force laws are not definitions.

I would even say that the law of gravitation is a prime example of a law of nature - a generalisation of experimetal observations.
 
  • #35
I believe Newton called the 3 laws " Axioms"
 
  • #36
madness said:
I don't see how we can identify these non-interacting bodies until we decide whether we are in an inertial frame of reference.

In theory it would be clear if there is just a single body. In practice there is always the possibility of unknown interactions. But we try to describe nature as simple as possible. That includes not assuming hidden interactions as long as we can avoid it.
 
  • #37
hutchphd said:
I believe Newton called the 3 laws " Axioms"

I would translate "Lex" into law but I'm not an expert in Latin.
 
  • Like
Likes hutchphd
  • #38
madness said:
We may have some freedom to choose which parts of the theory are definitions and which aren't, but in the end we need to put down a sufficient number of constraints in order to arrive at anything testable.
Yes, and post #23 describes how Newton's Laws are testable in analogy to Energy Conservation.
 
  • #39
A.T. said:
Yes, and post #23 describes how Newton's Laws are testable in analogy to Energy Conservation.

I'm not sure an analogy to Energy Conservation makes the case.

The conjunction of Newton's laws and a choice of force law may be testable. But I'm not sure whether one could maintain testability without first specifying all 3 laws and the force law.
 
  • #40
DrStupid said:
I would translate "Lex" into law but I'm not an expert in Latin.
I was working from the chapter title Axiomata sive leges Motus where I think the translation holds good. But he does then enumerate the "laws". Alas I am devoid of any formal training in Latin.
 
  • #41
madness said:
It says they do not accelerate in an inertial frame. But we still have to figure out whether we are in such a frame. I don't see how we can identify these non-interacting bodies until we decide whether we are in an inertial frame of reference.
As I said before, this approach assumes that you can already identify non-interacting bodies. Then you simply look at their motion. If it is uniform motion then the frame is inertial per the 1st law. I.e. assuming you can identify non-interacting bodies then the 1st law defines inertial frames.

If you cannot identify non-interacting bodies then it will not work. For this reason the Newton-Cartan approach is nice because non-interacting bodies are easy to identify simply using an accelerometer, similar to the approach of GR.
 
  • #42
madness said:
I'm not sure an analogy to Energy Conservation makes the case.

The conjunction of Newton's laws and a choice of force law may be testable.
Energy Conservation is also only testable, if you define how to calculate specific forms of energy.
 
  • #43
Dale said:
As I said before, this approach assumes that you can already identify non-interacting bodies. Then you simply look at their motion. If it is uniform motion then the frame is inertial per the 1st law.

If you define non-interacting as being subject to no external force, then it seems fairly trivial that one could check whether they were in an intertial frame by measuring the acceleration of a known non-interacting body. But I don't find that very helpful or insightful because checking whether a body is non-interacting or checking whether we are using a non-inertial frame appear equally impossible on the basis of Newton's laws, at least before we define a functional form for the forces in the system.
 
  • #44
A.T. said:
Energy Conservation is also only testable, if you define how to calculate specific forms of energy.

Sure, the conjunction of the statements "energy = X" and "energy is conserved" is testable, as is the conjunction of Newton's laws and the specific laws for force.
 
  • #45
madness said:
Sure, the conjunction of the statements "energy = X" and "energy is conserved" is testable, as is the conjunction of Newton's laws and the specific laws for force.
And if you just call them all "statements", like you did for energy, then you don't have to worry which are "laws" and "definitions".
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #46
A.T. said:
And if you just call them all "statements", like you did for energy, then you don't have to worry which are "laws" and "definitions".

Perhaps, except that some of the "statements" are supposed apply to all possible forces and scenarios whereas others only in particular scenarios. In any case, my main concern was whether we really need all of the statements to get to something empirically testable. As far as I have understood, some posters have argued that Newton's 3 laws already get us to something testable, but it seems that this is only true if you also have one of the following extra facts: 1) Knowledge of which frames are intertial 2) Knowledge of some particles that are "non-interacting" 3) A definition for a specific force.
 
  • #47
A.T. said:
Energy Conservation is also only testable, if you define how to calculate specific forms of energy.

But in contrast to energy there is only one form of momentum with a very simple definition. That makes it quite easy to test conservation of momentum without any specific force law.
 
  • #48
DrStupid said:
I do not see the circularity.
Why do I need to assume that? I can also calculate the shape assuming that the Earth doesn't rotate. The comparision of the result with experimental observations will show that my assumption was wrong and that the rest frame of Earth is in fact rotating.
The circularity is that you need on the one hand an inertial frame which is operationally defined by the Lex I, for which you need the notion of a free particle, i.e., a particle which is not subject to the action of forces. To define forces you need Lex II which uses the definition of an inertial frame.

The resolution, also in view of the hitherto most comprehensive spacetime model, which is General Relativity, in my opinion is that you must start with a postulate on the spacetime model and then use it to find operational realizations of inertial reference frames. In Newtonian physics you start with absolute space and time, which however cannot be operationally defined, and indeed there's no way to distinguish different inertial frames, which is due to the fact that the symmetry group of Galilei-Newton spacetime is the 10D Galilei group of transformations. Having identified the symmetry group of the spacetime model you can reconstruct this model (this line of thought you can trace back to Riemann and Klein's Erlanger program in the mathematical foundation of geometry (or rather different kinds of gemoetries), which was worked out famously later by Noether in her famous 1918 paper on symmetries and conservation laws).

The next step in the development was famously Einstein's solution of the problem with the lack of Galilei invariance of Maxwell electrodynamics on the one hand and the failure to establish a preferred reference frame concerning electromagnetic phenomena on the other hand. Many physicists have been thinking before that this is the long-sought possibility for an operational approach to define Newton's absolute space and time as a kind of rest frame of the conjectured aether. This was disproven around this time (around 1900) by various experiments, including the most famous Michelson-Morley experiment but also the Trouton-Noble experiment.

Einstein just reinterpreted all these failed attempts by just assuming the full validity of the special principle of relativity but making it compatible with Maxwell electrodynamics. He found out that all you need to assume in addition is that the speed of electromagnetic waves is independent of the motion of the source of the waves relative to any inertial reference frame, and of course he used this to derive the Lorentz transformations and this finally lead Minkowski to construct the corresponding spacetime model, the Minkowski space as an affine pseudo-Euclidean 4D spacetime.

The last (yet) necessary adoption of the spacetime model then was Einstein's attempt to incorporate gravity into the relativistic picture lead him to the discovery of General Relativity in using the (weak and strong) equivalence principle. This lead to the reinterpretation of the gravitational interaction in terms of a pseudo-Riemannian manifold, where the inertial frames are only definable locally with the general covariance as a gauge symmetry, as we'd interpret it today in view of our experiences with gauge theories in the modern sense as a mathematical tool to localize global symmetries. In this case what's "localized" is the Lorentz group, and as long as one considers only the macroscopic physics of classical relativistic (continuum) mechanics and electrodynamics you are able to reconstruct Einstein's general relativistic spacetime model as a Lorentzian (pseudo-Riemannian manifold with a metric of signature (1,3) or equivalently (3,1)).

The operational definition of a local inertial reference frame from the point of view of GR is a freely falling body with a non-rotating tetrad (Fermi-Walker transported) defining this frame. The extension of this local inertial frame is determined by the scales over which tidal gravitational forces can be neglected. A nice example of such a local inertial reference frame is the International Space Station, which as far as I know is the best place to make microgravitation experiments, i.e., the best operationally defined local inertial reference frame we have today.
 
  • #49
vanhees71 said:
The circularity is that you need on the one hand an inertial frame which is operationally defined by the Lex I, for which you need the notion of a free particle, i.e., a particle which is not subject to the action of forces. To define forces you need Lex II which uses the definition of an inertial frame.

I still don't see a circularity but an axiomatic definition instead. The laws of motion alone might not be sufficient to distinguish rotating frames from non-rotation frames but there are other restrictions like isotropy that would be violated in the rotating frames. If you manage to invent interactive forces to describe rotating systems they would define a preferred direction.
 
Last edited:
  • #50
madness said:
I don't find that very helpful or insightful
That is fine. There are many approaches in the literature. Pick one that works for you. I like this one, but I also have seen others I like.

You may be interested in the Newton-Cartan approach where gravity is not an interaction so identifying non interacting bodies is a simple matter of attaching an accelerometer.

madness said:
some posters have argued that Newton's 3 laws already get us to something testable
Note that, in my case it isn’t “some posters” arguing, it comes from the literature. There is a lot of variety on this topic, which is an indication that it is mainly just a personal preference. So just find one that you like.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
Back
Top