I Entanglement and FTL signaling in professional scientific literature

  • #201
PeroK said:
It's not in the standard model. Where is the mathematical description of that interaction?

All that is experimentally detected is a correlation. Not a communication, not an interaction, not an influence. Only a correlation.

Haha, well I think you boxed yourself in on this one. The standard model predicts the results depend on Alice and Bob's choices, and there are no other input variables to the formulae like cos^2(Alice- Bob). The outcome of Alice's choice allows me to exactly predict the result that distant Bob sees. Cause, meet effect!

Further, a critique complaining of it being "only" a correlation fails, as all scientific experiments depend on correlations where certain inputs are held constant. The issue is that with entanglement, there is no earlier predecessor variable which you can identify as a candidate "common cause", which you would certainly like to have. But that is not a flaw in my description. In other words: for the results to represent "only" a correlation - as you assert above: there would need to exist a such a prior common "root" cause. But according to Bell: there can be no prior common cause explaining your hypothetical "correlation"!

My explanation is as accurate as it gets, and it really shouldn't be controversial in the least if you read it without attempting to tear apart things word by word. My point is not that the mystery disappears with this explanation, it doesn't. My point is that there are facts and logical deductions we can agree upon, and we should start there. Obviously, it is not an accident or coincidence that Alice (or Bob) cast the resulting 2 individual particles (coming from a 2 particle entangled system) into a state consistent with Alice's measurement choice. That's true in every Bell test.

And finally: as I have quoted extensively, the existence of quantum nonlocality is generally accepted within the leaders of the physics community. Which is what we should be referencing in this Quantum Physics thread, as this is the PF standard. Further discussion that debates generally accepted physics should rightfully be discussed in a different forum. This is but one example of generally accepted physics, demonstrating that quantum nonlocality has been demonstrated in Bell tests:

Paul Kwiat et al (2022): ...the original purpose of Bell tests, providing a measurable criteria for separating local and nonlocal theories, has been largely fulfilled..."
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #202
DrChinese said:
Either Alice's measurement casts Bob's particle into a state synchronized with Alice, or Bob's measurement casts Alice's particle into a state synchronized with Bob.
But, as has already been pointed out, neither of these can be right, because they are both asymmetric, but the situation is symmetric between Alice and Bob. So whatever is going on "behind the scenes" would need to be symmetric between them as well.

DrChinese said:
How is there any other conclusion?
Nobody really knows at present, but that's not at all the same as any other conclusion being impossible. This is simply something we don't fully understand. But part of what we do understand is that the situation is symmetric between Alice and Bob: we know the measurements commute. So any resolution, it seems to me, would have to be consistent with that.
 
  • Like
Likes Fra, PeroK and martinbn
  • #203
DrChinese said:
If Alice and Bob choose the same measurement basis (say 0 degrees for a spin measurement): the results are perfectly correlated (or anti-correlated as the case may be). This is true for any angle (0 degrees, 1 degree, 2 degrees, etc). Yet the outcomes cannot be predetermined (since the predetermination would by definition need to be independent of both Alice's and Bob's choice, since Bell showed us there are no possible states consistent with quantum predictions).
Say Alice measures the spin of her photon at some angle and observes "up". Is the following statement true:

"If bob performs the same measurement on his photon, there is a 100% chance he will observe 'up', but if Alice had not measured her particle, there would be less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'"
 
  • #204
Morbert said:
"If bob performs the same measurement on his photon, there is a 100% chance he will observe 'up', but if Alice had not measured her particle, there would be less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'"

FWIW, I think that if what I posited in post 162 is not a palatable line of thinking, then the answer should be yes, there is a less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'. If the answer is otherwise, then there is no weirdness going on, right?
 
  • #205
DrChinese said:
all scientific experiments depend on correlations where certain inputs are held constant. The issue is that with entanglement, there is no earlier predecessor variable which you can identify as a candidate "common cause", which you would certainly like to have.
I agree.
DrChinese said:
But according to Bell: there can be no prior common cause explaining your hypothetical "correlation"!
I disagree. Bell only excludes the kind of common cause that follows his ansatz; which is a hidden correlation of "ignorance type". Why would this be exhaustive??

I don't see the problem with a "hidden variable" that explains the correlation only, but where the interaction at either detector does NOT depend on the hidden variable, but just on the preparation (as QM describes, but not necessarily "explains"). (conceptual arguements for this is interpretation dependent so i omit them)

/Fredrik
 
  • #206
DrChinese said:
there is no earlier predecessor variable which you can identify as a candidate "common cause"
Sure there is: the entangled state that was prepared. The issue some people have is that that isn't the kind of "variable" they are looking for as a common cause.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK
  • #207
DrChinese said:
In my mind, the description I present is an accepted fact; and it matters not whether Alice's measurement occurs before Bob's. Of course, it is equally true from Bob's perspective vis a vis Alice. Only Alice and Bob's measurement choices contribute to the observed outcomes. If Alice and Bob choose the same measurement basis (say 0 degrees for a spin measurement): the results are perfectly correlated (or anti-correlated as the case may be). This is true for any angle (0 degrees, 1 degree, 2 degrees, etc). Yet the outcomes cannot be predetermined (since the predetermination would by definition need to be independent of both Alice's and Bob's choice, since Bell showed us there are no possible states consistent with quantum predictions). Either Alice's measurement casts Bob's particle into a state synchronized with Alice, or Bob's measurement casts Alice's particle into a state synchronized with Bob. How is there any other conclusion? Either are best described as a quantum nonlocal influence (or collapse, or context or whatever you want to label it).
The "other conclusion" is that this point of view violates the mathematical properties of QED (or any other microcausal realtivistic QFT): There cannot be any causal influence between space-like separated events. Thus the much less spectacular but consistent conclusion is that the correlations are due to the entanglement of the state prepared before any of the two measurements have been performed. This property of entangled states, i.e., maximal indeterminism of the measured single-photon properties with strong correlations between the outcome of their space-like separated measurements is what distinguishes QT (including microcausal relativistic QFTs) from classical ("local realistic") theories, and all experimental findings are in favor of QT.

This is in so far a "interpretation independent statement", because it just uses the mathematical formulation of the theory and the empirical findings applying it to the corresponding experiments within a "minimal interpretation", i.e., the assumption that the "kinematics and dynamics" of the theory is complete, including the "probabilistic and only probabilistic" meaning of quantum states.
DrChinese said:
Pretty much every interpretation brings about the same conclusion: MWI (worlds split), Bohmian (action at a distance), RBW (acausal context), physical collapse interpretations (nonlocal collapse). Of course, a few give us crickets (silence) but that obviously begs the question.
You can add as many "interpretation" as you like, but you must stay consistent with the mathematical formulation of microcausal QFT. Otherwise you propose new theories. Particularly "non-local collapse" is very difficult to establish in accordance with the special-relativistic causality structure of Minkowski space.
 
  • Like
Likes physicsworks and PeroK
  • #208
The presumed nonlocality of entangled systems would have been a mystery if it happened in a fundamentally classical reality.
The issue, if such exists at all, is that nature is fundamentally non-classical. And we are not particularly good at dealing with emergent properties. At least not yet.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #209
Is the following statement true: "If bob performs the same measurement on his photon, there is a 100% chance he will observe 'up', but if Alice had not measured her particle, there would be less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'"
Grinkle said:
FWIW, I think that if what I posited in post 162 is not a palatable line of thinking, then the answer should be yes, there is a less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'. If the answer is otherwise, then there is no weirdness going on, right?
If the answer is yes then there is absolutely a nonlocal influence in the common sense of the words. But the answer is interpretation-dependent. Consistent histories let's us readily evaluate counterfactual claims like this, and would in fact imply the statement is false: even if Alice had not carried out her measurement, there would still be a 100% chance that Bob will measure 'up'. Other interpretations might be more conservative and deny any evaluation of counterfactuals, and under any interpretation where the statement is not considered true, it seems hard to conclude nonlocal influence.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #210
DrChinese said:
Pretty much every interpretation brings about the same conclusion: MWI (worlds split), Bohmian (action at a distance), RBW (acausal context), physical collapse interpretations (nonlocal collapse). Of course, a few give us crickets (silence) but that obviously begs the question.
vanhees71 said:
You can add as many "interpretation" as you like, but you must stay consistent with the mathematical formulation of microcausal QFT. Otherwise you propose new theories. Particularly "non-local collapse" is very difficult to establish in accordance with the special-relativistic causality structure of Minkowski space.
I had to look-up what "give us crickets" means: It is such a perfect silence that you can hear the crickets! And I have to agree, you are giving us exactly this sort of silence. Notice that "the mathematical formulation of microcausal QFT" is not an interpretation, and mumbling "minimal interpretation" without any clarifying explanations doesn't turn it into an interpretation either. When I tried to go a bit into the details (how the perfect locality that "microcausal QFT let's us expect" translates back to an interpretation)
gentzen said:
The minimal statistical interpretation is just fine, what is problematic is ...
you just shrugged it off
vanhees71 said:
Yes: Alice meets Bob for a cup of tea bringing her laptop with the measurement protocol to compare it with Bob's on his laptop ;-)).
But it was a mistake anyway for me to try to do your work. My own position is that QM is nonlocal, and that it is the randomness which is nonlocal. This is a widely shared position, Nicolas Gisin's book Quantum Chance convincingly argues for it, as do many of his articles and papers. And it is much easier to explain than performing the interpretative dance required for getting rid of this type of nonlocality in some specific interpretation.

vanhees71 said:
The "other conclusion" is that this point of view violates the mathematical properties of QED (or any other microcausal realtivistic QFT): There cannot be any causal influence between space-like separated events. Thus the much less spectacular but consistent conclusion is that the correlations are due to the entanglement of the state prepared before any of the two measurements have been performed.
This is fine, if you accept the remaining nonlocal randomness. If not, then just looking at the preparation can be insufficient.

DrChinese said:
It IS experimentally detected! The influence doesn't come from anywhere OTHER than Alice or Bob. Only Alice and Bob's choices matter, and the results are consistent with nothing else. As I mentioned, "crickets" is an interpretation as well, but it avoids this obvious point. :smile:
Indeed, the default interpretation of the experimental results is "nonlocality". Even if you don't like it, silence is not a convincing argument against that interpretation.
 
  • #211
Once more: The definition of "nonlocality" must be consistent with "microcausality" in any interpretation of standard relativistic quantum field theory. Otherwise you propose a new theory. Then one must find an experiment which can decide between the two theories.

The "minimal statistical interpretation" is a well-defined and consistent interpretation of standard Q(F)T and not just something I mumble about. It just uses the probabilistic interpretation of the quantum state, as it is defined in the mathematical formulation of Q(F)T and nothing else. It's "minimal" in the sense that it just refers to the empirical meaning of the formalism and nothing else.

A very concise comprehensive formulation of it is given in Ballentine, Quantum Mechanics. Unfortunately that's a book on non-relativistic quantum mechanics, i.e., you don't find much about microcausality (locality in the well-defined mathematical sense of relativistic QFT) vs. "non-locality" (in the sense of the possibility of long-ranged correlations between parts of entangled quantum systems that are measured at far distant places with measurement events space-like separated) and why there is no contradiction between the two.
 
  • Like
Likes physicsworks
  • #212
vanhees71 said:
Once more: The definition of "nonlocality" must be consistent with "microcausality" in any interpretation of standard relativistic quantum field theory. Otherwise you propose a new theory. Then one must find an experiment which can decide between the two theories.
Most interpretations have their origin in non-relativistic quantum mechanics, and the "minimal statistical interpretation" is no exception here. Some interpretations can be "upgraded" to interpretations of relativistic quantum field theory. But if nobody invests the work to do such an "upgrade," this doesn't imply that some existent interpretation had suddenly turned into a proposal for a new theory.

Even so I my guess is that the "minimal statistical interpretation" can in principle be "updated," it would be your task to explain to us how to do this, or to point to a reference where it has been done.

But I find the position to accept the nonlocal randomness more convenient for various reasons. One of those reasons is that explaining interpretations is already very hard, even without also having to take into account relativistic quantum field theory. A day only has so many hours, and other things are simply more important to me.
 
  • #213
gentzen said:
Most interpretations have their origin in non-relativistic quantum mechanics, and the "minimal statistical interpretation" is no exception here. Some interpretations can be "upgraded" to interpretations of relativistic quantum field theory. But if nobody invests the work to do such an "upgrade," this doesn't imply that some existent interpretation had suddenly turned into a proposal for a new theory.
That's indeed one of the problems. If you discuss the tension between relativistic causality (no faster-than-light causal effects) and "quantum non-locality" you can't argue within non-relativistic QT, where "actions at a distance" are just the normal description of the dynamics as in classical Newtonian mechanics. It's no surprise that there you get faster-than-light signal propagation.

Then the question is, where's the need for an "upgrade" of all kinds of interpretations, which don't solve any "real physical problem"? Why should anybody invent, e.g., a Bohmian theory for relativistic QFT? What could one learn from it?
gentzen said:
Even so I my guess is that the "minimal statistical interpretation" can in principle be "updated," it would be your task to explain to us how to do this, or to point to a reference where it has been done.
What do you want to "update"? It's just applied all the time when comparing the results of experiments testing Q(F)T with the predictions of that theory.
gentzen said:
But I find the position to accept the nonlocal randomness more convenient for various reasons. One of those reasons is that explaining interpretations is already very hard, even without also having to take into account relativistic quantum field theory. A day only has so many hours, and other things are simply more important to me.
As I said, if you want to understand the question of and relation between "locality" in the sense of relativstic spacetime descriptions versus "quantum nonlocality", you must employ a relativistic consistent description, and the only one we have is microcausal relativistic QFT. So that't the theory you have to apply.
 
  • #214
vanhees71 said:
What do you want to "update"? It's just applied all the time when comparing the results of experiments testing Q(F)T with the predictions of that theory.
The instant sharing of random numbers for space-like separated events is a nonlocal effect. Therefore, if an interpretation wants to be truly local, it has to explain why this doesn't count, or what we did wrong to accidentally introduce that nonlocality.
 
  • #215
There is no "instant sharing of random numbers for space-like separated events". If you want to reveal the correlations, you have to exchange this information in a "classical way" by comparing measurement protocols.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen, Fra and PeterDonis
  • #216
vanhees71 said:
within a "minimal interpretation", i.e., the assumption that the "kinematics and dynamics" of the theory is complete, including the "probabilistic and only probabilistic" meaning of quantum states.
This is not a "minimal interpretation". It's a claim that the minimal interpretation is the "correct" interpretation. Other interpretations do not agree with this. Not only that, other interpretations do not even agree that the two statements you give here are consistent: the MWI says that the kinematics and dynamics are complete but says quantum states are not probabilistic; they are an exact and complete description of the physical state of the system and they always evolve by unitary dynamics. "Physical collapse" theories, OTOH, say that quantum states are indeed "probabilistic and only probabilistic", but deny that the "kinematics and dynamics" of the theory (meaning standard QM) are complete.
 
  • #217
vanhees71 said:
you have to exchange this information in a "classical way" by comparing measurement protocols.
This certainly goes into the direction I had in mind. However, there are many ways to exchange information in a classical way. One way would be to agree on an exact sequence of measurement settings in advance. Another way would be to try use completely random measurement settings, and share those settings later using a classical communication channel.

But let me stop here. It is fine for me now. I am not overly keen on performing such interpretational dances. Because I fear that in the end they will just confuse everybody, without solving any actual substantive problem. At least not until somebody comes along (in a Frauchiger-Renner way) and makes a mistake of this sort. But even then, he probably won't understand the message of such a dance.
 
  • #218
vanhees71 said:
you have to exchange this information in a "classical way" by comparing measurement protocols.
No, it's not enough to share the protocols. You have to share enough information for Alice and Bob to be able to compare their exact meaurement directions as they were actually realized. In any real experiment, measurement directions cannot be picked with infinite accuracy, so there will be some "error" or "noise" in the actual data; that "error" or "noise" is part of the information produced by the measurements and it can only be known by comparing the results after the fact using classical channels.
 
  • #219
gentzen said:
there are many ways to exchange information in a classical way.
There is only one, though, that ensures that all of the information produced by the measurements is shared by both parties. See my post #218 just now.
 
  • #220
PeterDonis said:
No, it's not enough to share the protocols. You have to share enough information for Alice and Bob to be able to compare their exact meaurement directions as they were actually realized. In any real experiment, measurement directions cannot be picked with infinite accuracy, so there will be some "error" or "noise" in the actual data; that "error" or "noise" is part of the information produced by the measurements and it can only be known by comparing the results after the fact using classical channels.
Of course, all this must be contained in the measurement protocols, and of course there are systematic on top of the statistical uncertainties in any measurement.
 
  • #221
vanhees71 said:
all this must be contained in the measurement protocols
Ah, ok, by "protocols" you meant to include the things that have to occur after the measurements are complete. Got it.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #222
Morbert said:
a. Say Alice measures the spin of her photon at some angle and observes "up". Is the following statement true:

"If bob performs the same measurement on his photon, there is a 100% chance he will observe 'up', but if Alice had not measured her particle, there would be less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'"
PeterDonis said:
b. But, as has already been pointed out, neither of these can be right, because they are both asymmetric, but the situation is symmetric between Alice and Bob. So whatever is going on "behind the scenes" would need to be symmetric between them as well. ... But part of what we do understand is that the situation is symmetric between Alice and Bob: we know the measurements commute. So any resolution, it seems to me, would have to be consistent with that.
PeterDonis said:
c. Sure there is: the entangled state that was prepared. The issue some people have is that that isn't the kind of "variable" they are looking for as a common cause.
Fra said:
d. I agree. [Yay!]

I disagree. Bell only excludes the kind of common cause that follows his ansatz; which is a hidden correlation of "ignorance type". Why would this be exhaustive??

@Morbert:
a. I agree, Bob would then see a 50% "up" rate rather than 100% assuming Alice's results are unknown. If measured at different angles (but Alice IS known), the results follow the usual expectation value. @PeterDonis:
b. My statements ("Either Alice's measurement casts Bob's particle into a state synchronized with Alice, or Bob's measurement casts Alice's particle into a state synchronized with Bob.") ARE symmetric (or commute), and precisely fit the facts. There are no other facts you can state about the results OTHER than what I say.

c. The entangled state absolutely does NOT predetermine the outcomes of (all possible) measurement choices by Alice and Bob. Bell ruled that out for all possible type of hidden variables (see d. below for quotes). The best you could say is that it is responsible for the random element to the outcomes, which are otherwise unaccounted for in the quantum expectation value for matches.@Fra:
d. You are incorrect about Bell's hidden variable types - there was no limitation or exclusion on them at all. He said (1964): "Let this more complete specification be effected by means of parameters λ. It is a matter of indifference in the following whether A denotes a single variable or a set, or even a set of functions, and whether the variables are discrete or continuous." He does provide one assumption however, but it is not on type or form: "The vital assumption is that the result B for particle 2 does not depend on the setting a, of the magnet for particle 1, nor [vice versa] A on b."
 
  • #223
DrChinese said:
@Morbert:a. I agree, Bob would then see a 50% "up" rate rather than 100% assuming Alice's results are unknown. If measured at different angles (but Alice IS known), the results follow the usual expectation value.
I think there's where the disagreement is: Not all interpretations would agree that Bob would see a 50% up rate under these counterfactual scenarios, and under these interpretations, we cannot conclude a nonlocal influence.
 
  • #224
DrChinese said:
My statements ("Either Alice's measurement casts Bob's particle into a state synchronized with Alice, or Bob's measurement casts Alice's particle into a state synchronized with Bob.") ARE symmetric (or commute)
I think we disagree on what "symmetric" and "commute" mean.

DrChinese said:
The entangled state absolutely does NOT predetermine the outcomes of (all possible) measurement choices by Alice and Bob.
I didn't say it did. I only said it was a candidate for a "common cause". Nothing "predetermines" the outcomes--even the entangled state plus the measurements choices doesn't predetermine the outcomes since there is still a random element involved. But the entangled state is certainly part of what "contributes" (to use as neutral a word as possible) to the outcomes. So are the measurement choices of Alice and Bob. The entangled state is the "common" part of that, and the choices are the "non-common" part (since they can differ between Alice and Bob).

DrChinese said:
The best you could say is that it is responsible for the random element to the outcomes
That would depend on what interpretation of the quantum state is adopted.
 
  • #225
Morbert said:
Not all interpretations would agree that Bob would see a 50% up rate under these counterfactual scenarios
Which interpretations would not?
 
  • #226
PeterDonis said:
Which interpretations would not?
Consistent histories as presented Robert Griffiths (one of its founders). From Chapter 19 of "Consistent Quantum Theory"

"While relativistic quantum theory is outside the scope of this book, an analysis of non-relativistic versions of some of the paradoxes which are supposed to show the presence of superluminal influences indicates that the real source of such ghostly effects is the need to correct logical errors arising from the assumption that the quantum world is behaving in some respects in a classical way. When the situation is studied using consistent quantum principles, the ghosts disappear
[...]
Certain quantum paradoxes are stated in terms of counterfactuals: what would have happened if some state of affairs had been different from what it actually was. Other paradoxes have both a counterfactual as well as in an “ordinary” form. In order to discuss counterfactual quantum paradoxes, one needs a quantum version of counterfactual reasoning
[...]
The result is X+ with probability one. That this is reasonable can be seen in the following way. The actual measurement outcome X + shows that the particle had Sx = +1/2 at time t1 before the measurement took place, since quantum measurements reveal pre-existing values if one employs a suitable framework. And by choosing [x+] at t1 as the pivot, one is assuming that Sx had the same value at this time in both the actual and the counterfactual world. Therefore a later measurement of Sx in the counterfactual world would necessarily result in X+"


That last paragraph is not explicitly referencing the EPR experiment, but a similar scenario characterised by equation 19.12. I have constructed the analogous support for the EPR experiment below: Say Bob measures the spin-x of his particle and Alice either measures spin-x or doesn't measure spin-x of her particle. The support is
$$
\left\{\begin{array}{lll}
\left[x_B^+\right]&\otimes&\left\{\begin{array}{lll}\left[X_A^+,X_B^+\right]&&\\
&&\\
\left[X_A^0,X_B^+\right]&&\end{array}\right.\\
&&\\
\left[x_B^-\right]&\otimes&\left\{\begin{array}{lll}\left[X_A^-,X_B^-\right]&&\\
&&\\
\left[X_A^0,X_B^-\right]&&\end{array}\right.
\end{array}\right.
$$
where ##x_B^\pm## is the x-spin up/down of Bob's particle, ##X_A,X_B## are Alice's and Bob's apparatus for measuring spin-x, ##X^\pm## means up/down was measured and ##X^0## means the measurement was not carried out. If Alice measures spin-x and observes up, we know we are on the top branch of this support, and so we can use counterfactual reasoning to work out what would happen if Alice had not measured spin-x (the 2nd branch).

[edit] - Simplified support and scenario. Some of the support is implicit, but I think it is easier to read.
 
Last edited:
  • #227
Morbert said:
a similar scenario characterised by equation 19.12
Huh? That scenario, like all of the scenarios discussed in that chapter, is about a measurement on a single particle. None of them are about measurements on entangled pairs of particles.

Even if we leave that aside, the only scenario that even discusses counterfactuals where a measurement that is made in the "actual" world is not made in a counterfactual world is the one shown in equation 19.14.
 
  • #228
Morbert said:
I think there's where the disagreement is: Not all interpretations would agree that Bob would see a 50% up rate under these counterfactual scenarios, and under these interpretations, we cannot conclude a nonlocal influence.
As you asked the question, there is no counterfactual to consider. This can be experimentally realized, so there's nothing to consider in the way of interpretations. It's a fact.
 
  • #229
PeterDonis said:
I didn't say it did. I only said it was a candidate for a "common cause". Nothing "predetermines" the outcomes--even the entangled state plus the measurements choices doesn't predetermine the outcomes since there is still a random element involved. But the entangled state is certainly part of what "contributes" (to use as neutral a word as possible) to the outcomes. So are the measurement choices of Alice and Bob. The entangled state is the "common" part of that, and the choices are the "non-common" part (since they can differ between Alice and Bob).

So... the entangled state is NOT the common cause (nor a candidate for same) of the quantum outcomes/expectation precisely because it does NOT factor into the equation - only Alice and Bob's choices do. We agree that it is POSSIBLE that the entangled state holds the key to the random component we see in individual trials. But mathematically, it cannot contribute because the choices of Alice and Bob account for everything we can predict accurately. Which is everything except that random element. Of course, that random element could also be contributed by the environment.

Ultimately, it is meaningless to assert the "entangled state" (how the system is prepared) accounts for the results, when clearly the one critical prediction of QM for Bell tests does not incorporate it at all. There is not one iota of a hint that the superposition itself contains any information that contributes to the outcomes.

--------

And again, to address the idea that QFT is needed to understand the phenomena of entanglement vis a vis Bell tests: it doesn't! There is no difference between QM and QFT as regards to Bell test calculations (that I am aware of). As far as anyone knows, the theoretical constraints some think are contained in QFT ("microcausality") are not mentioned in any work I am aware of by teams investigating entanglement. Nor is this mentioned in any comparisons of common quantum interpretations. I say that's because it's completely irrelevant, why else?

------------

I have quoted top teams until I am blue in the face. So if anyone else can provide a suitable counter to those quotes in a generally accepted recent paper by a top team, I'm all ears. All I ever see is self quotes... where's the beef?

Quantum nonlocality is generally accepted physics. It's high time this forum explicitly accepted same, that's our stated standard. I hope that is not too radical to be said here. Saying this does not mean we know anything about the underlying mechanism. It does not mean there is instantaneous or spooky action at a distance. It does not mean that there are signals propagating FTL. It only means that there are elements of quantum systems that when measured, do not respect classical limits for any of a number of reasons (i.e. because local realism is refuted by Bell tests).
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #230
DrChinese said:
the entangled state is NOT the common cause (nor a candidate for same) of the quantum outcomes/expectation precisely because it does NOT factor into the equation - only Alice and Bob's choices do.
What equation are you talking about? The entangled state most certainly does "factor into" the QM equations that are used to predict probabilities.

DrChinese said:
the choices of Alice and Bob account for everything we can predict accurately
I don't understand how you can possibly say this given that we have to know the entangled state that was prepared in order to make accurate predictions.

DrChinese said:
it is meaningless to assert the "entangled state" (how the system is prepared) accounts for the results, when clearly the one critical prediction of QM for Bell tests does not incorporate it at all
I have no idea how you can say this given that, as above, we have to know the entangled state in order to make correct predictions.
 
  • #231
DrChinese said:
Quantum nonlocality is generally accepted physics. It's high time this forum explicitly accepted same, that's our stated standard
The issue is that you are using a term, "quantum nonlocality", whose meaning is not generally accepted: different sources use it to mean different things.

The actual experimental facts are that when we make Bell-type measurements on entangled pairs of particles, the observed correlations violate the Bell inequalities and match the predictions of standard QM. If that is what you mean by "quantum nonlocality", then yes, "quantum nonlocality" is generally accepted physics because it's an experimental fact. But other people, using "quantum nonlocality" to mean different things, might not agree that "quantum nonlocality" is generally accepted physics. That doesn't mean they disagree with you about the experimental facts or about what standard QM predicts. It just means they are using words differently.

The best procedure I know of for dealing with such situations is to taboo the problematic term, in this case "quantum nonlocality". If you mean "Bell inequality violations", say so. If someone else means something different, they can say what they mean. IIRC I've proposed a solution like this before but nobody adopted it.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn
  • #232
DrChinese said:
the theoretical constraints some think are contained in QFT ("microcausality") are not mentioned in any work I am aware of by teams investigating entanglement.
That's irrelevant unless those teams are arguing that those constraints don't apply, which AFAIK nobody is arguing.

We don't argue that phenomena within the domain of Newtonian physics don't have to obey relativistic constraints because relativity is "not mentioned" in Newtonian physics. We understand that Newtonian physics is just an approximation to relativity valid in a limited domain, and we understand that, if we're talking about "theoretical constraints", the constraints of relativity apply in the Newtonian domain just as they do everywhere else, even if those constraints aren't "mentioned" in Newtonian treatments.

The position with respect to non-relativistic QM is the same: it's an approximation to QFT valid within a limited domain, and the theoretical constraints of QFT apply even if they aren't "mentioned" in non-relativistic QM treatments.
 
  • #233
DrChinese said:
@Fra:
d. You are incorrect about Bell's hidden variable types - there was no limitation or exclusion on them at all. He said (1964): "Let this more complete specification be effected by means of parameters λ. It is a matter of indifference in the following whether A denotes a single variable or a set, or even a set of functions, and whether the variables are discrete or continuous."
The assumption I was thinking of is the ansatz where you partition/index the sample space as per the hidden variable, and assume that the partitioning into hidden variable makes sense. This is exactly what I think constitutes an "ignorance type" mechanism. From my interpretation (abstract interacting agent view, this assumption generally makes no sense, but then I am not looking for the sort of realism bell did.)
I think of it so that the hidden variables can explain the correlation, but not the interaction. The way this is possible is that unlike ignorance HV, which in which the environment is potentially informed (due to decoherence), an isolated entangled pair is strictly forbidden to interact. It's also not possible to infere an interaction rule from such an interaction, as it would break the entanglement.

Instead the sort of HV I imagine, is from the "inside view" of one of the entangled systems, there maybe a uniqe "reality" there, but due to interactions works, this is not inferrable from the outside and thus really HIDDEN unlike the ignorance where the information just lost averaged out or lost by the observer, but it exists in the evironment.
DrChinese said:
He does provide one assumption however, but it is not on type or form: "The vital assumption is that the result B for particle 2 does not depend on the setting a, of the magnet for particle 1, nor [vice versa] A on b."
I have no problem with THIS assumption.

/Fredrik
 
  • #234
Fra said:
I have no problem with THIS assumption.
You realize that that assumption is a key one that leads to deriving the Bell inequalities--which are violated by actual experiments and by the predictions of QM--right?
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #235
PeterDonis said:
You realize that that assumption is a key one that leads to deriving the Bell inequalities--which are violated by actual experiments and by the predictions of QM--right?
Yes.
 
  • #236
PeterDonis said:
The issue is that you are using a term, "quantum nonlocality", whose meaning is not generally accepted: different sources use it to mean different things.

The actual experimental facts are that when we make Bell-type measurements on entangled pairs of particles, the observed correlations violate the Bell inequalities and match the predictions of standard QM. If that is what you mean by "quantum nonlocality", then yes, "quantum nonlocality" is generally accepted physics because it's an experimental fact. But other people, using "quantum nonlocality" to mean different things, might not agree that "quantum nonlocality" is generally accepted physics. That doesn't mean they disagree with you about the experimental facts or about what standard QM predicts. It just means they are using words differently.

The best procedure I know of for dealing with such situations is to taboo the problematic term, in this case "quantum nonlocality". If you mean "Bell inequality violations", say so. If someone else means something different, they can say what they mean. IIRC I've proposed a solution like this before but nobody adopted it.
"Nonlocality" in abstract, past 12 months: 1167. I guess many sources do know how to use the word, and they expect advanced readers to know it as well (without tearing the syntax of every sentence apart as we tend to do here). Paul Kwiat et al (2022): "...the original purpose of Bell tests, providing a measurable criteria for separating local and nonlocal theories, has been largely fulfilled..."

It doesn't make sense to me to make taboo the very term that is in fact generally accepted. We don't live in a local realistic world, we live in one in which there is evidence of nonlocality. And in fact, the title of this thread references the professional literature - which question we have been trying to answer. And the answer is that the professional literature accepts the existence of quantum nonlocality (demonstrated by entanglement, as an example, and there are other examples too), and denies the existence of FTL signaling possibilities (since quantum outcomes individually exhibit randomness).

-DrC
 
Last edited:
  • #237
Fra said:
Bell: "The vital assumption is that the result B for particle 2 does not depend on the setting a, of the magnet for particle 1, nor [vice versa] A on b."

I have no problem with THIS assumption.

And from the results of Bell tests, we know this assumption is false. In reality, they ARE mutually dependent. That is what I have been saying over and over. The ONLY inputs to the quantum expectation value for Bell tests are the a (Alice) and b (Bob) settings. And Bell rules out all other variables, sets, functions, interactions, preconditions, etc as contributing in any way to the statistical results. You cannot even hand create conditions where anything happens prior to Alice and Bob's measurements and get the right answer.
 
  • #238
DrChinese said:
And from the results of Bell tests, we know this assumption is false. In reality, they ARE mutually dependent. That is what I have been saying over and over. The ONLY inputs to the quantum expectation value for Bell tests are the a (Alice) and b (Bob) settings. And Bell rules out all other variables, sets, functions, interactions, preconditions, etc as contributing in any way to the statistical results. You cannot even hand create conditions where anything happens prior to Alice and Bob's measurements and get the right answer.
You seem to be ignoring here my most important objection, ie, the assumption that it makes sense to sum over the hidden variable? You need this to prove Bell inequality. I think such a partition is unphysical in the situation. It seems the argument here is which assumptions you object to. the objection I make I rarely see, for some reason. Perhaps because its not an argument that someone looking for old typ realism is likely to come up with I think.

I am not suggesting that there is a HV the predetermines the outcome independently of hte detector settings.

/Fredrik
 
  • #239
DrChinese said:
You cannot even hand create conditions where anything happens prior to Alice and Bob's measurements and get the right answer.
We have QM, that describes this. It's the preparatation of the entangled pair that is the condition. And my logic is that the detector is "informed" about the preparation only, NOT about the hidden variable. Also no other part of the environment can be, as that would break the isolation and entangelement. This is why the statistics at both detectors must be independent of hidden variable; yet it explains the "correlation". I find this plausible as information not at hand, should not influence the interaction; as my conjecture beeing part of my interpretation is that interactions are a clash between "expectations".

I still think and agree something is missing here (ie. I am not happy with our understanding of QM), but for me its something different, than what I think Bell had in mind.

/Fredrik
 
  • #240
DrChinese said:
The ONLY inputs to the quantum expectation value for Bell tests are the a (Alice) and b (Bob) settings.
And the entangled state that was prepared. I don't understand why you keep leaving this out.
 
  • #241
DrChinese said:
@Morbert:
a. I agree, Bob would then see a 50% "up" rate rather than 100% assuming Alice's results are unknown. If measured at different angles (but Alice IS known), the results follow the usual expectation value. @PeterDonis:
b. My statements ("Either Alice's measurement casts Bob's particle into a state synchronized with Alice, or Bob's measurement casts Alice's particle into a state synchronized with Bob.") ARE symmetric (or commute), and precisely fit the facts. There are no other facts you can state about the results OTHER than what I say.
But it contradicts the very foundation of relativistic QFT, i.e., the microcausality constraint on local observables, i.e., there cannot be a mutual influence of A's and B's measurements if the "measurement events" (photon-detection events) are space-like separated.
DrChinese said:
c. The entangled state absolutely does NOT predetermine the outcomes of (all possible) measurement choices by Alice and Bob. Bell ruled that out for all possible type of hidden variables (see d. below for quotes). The best you could say is that it is responsible for the random element to the outcomes, which are otherwise unaccounted for in the quantum expectation value for matches.
Of course the entangled state doesn't predetermine any of the outcomes of the possible single-photon measurements, because the single-particle states are maximum-entropy mixed states, i.e., the single photons in the entangled two-photon states are ideally unpolarized. Nevertheless the preparation of the two-photon state as an entangled state implies the correlations as measured in all possible experiments. It's 100% (anti-)correlated if both A and B measure (or rather test for) linear polarization in the same direction.
DrChinese said:
@Fra:
d. You are incorrect about Bell's hidden variable types - there was no limitation or exclusion on them at all. He said (1964): "Let this more complete specification be effected by means of parameters λ. It is a matter of indifference in the following whether A denotes a single variable or a set, or even a set of functions, and whether the variables are discrete or continuous." He does provide one assumption however, but it is not on type or form: "The vital assumption is that the result B for particle 2 does not depend on the setting a, of the magnet for particle 1, nor [vice versa] A on b."
Separability means that the probabilities for the outcome of a joined measurement, given the value(s) of the hidden variable(s), ##\lambda##, commute, and that's indeed assumed in Bell's original paper (Eq. 2):

J. S. Bell, On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox, Physics
1, 195 (1964),
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195

Of course the reduced probabilities, i.e., the integral/sum over ##\lambda## is not "separable".
 
  • #242
DrChinese said:
As you asked the question, there is no counterfactual to consider. This can be experimentally realized, so there's nothing to consider in the way of interpretations. It's a fact.
Say Alice measures the spin of her electron at some angle and observes "up". Is the following statement true:

"If bob performs the same measurement on his electron, there is a 100% chance he will observe 'up', but if Alice had not measured her particle, there would be less than 100% chance that Bob will observe 'up'"
The bit in bold is the counterfactual. I can also rephrase the question in terms of ensembles:

Given an ensemble of identically prepared electron pairs in the appropriate Bell state, Bob measures spin-x = up 50% of the time and spin-x = down 50% of the time. However, for the subensemble of experimental runs where Alice measures spin-x = up, Bob measures spin-x = up 100% of the time. The counterfactual: If, for this subensemble of experimental runs, Alice had chosen not to perform a measurement, Bob would have instead observed spin-x = up 50% of the time, not 100%

The conclusion of superluminal influence rests on counterfactual reasoning like this, but if this reasoning is not correct, then we cannot yet conclude superluminal influence.

@PeterDonis I was applying the counterfactual reasoning outlined in chapter 19 for supports like 19.12 (or 19.14) to the scenario I posed to @DrChinese to show that, under the consistent histories interpretation, no superluminal influence is implied. I will go through steps in more detail/more explicitly when I get the chance.

[edit] - Changed photons to electrons to keep my scenario physical
 
Last edited:
  • #243
Suppose the two photons are prepared in the polarization-singlet state, then the single-photon states are given by the corresponding partial traces. The outcome is ##\hat{\rho}_A=\frac{1}{2} \hat{1}_A##, ##\hat{\rho}_B=\frac{1}{2} \hat{1}_B##, i.e., the photons are perfectly unpolarized. All that A and B find when measuring the linear-polarization state both in the same direction are unpolarized photons, i.e., they find with 50% chance H and with 50% chance V. Only when their measurement protocols are storing the results of this measurement (together with the accurate time stamps to be able to know, which photon pair's where prepared as an entangled state when doing their measurements) you are able to "post-select" the subenemble, where A found H, and then, comparing the measurement protocols, it will come out that, given A found H, B always found V, i.e., a 100% anti-correlation, and that's precisely what the preparation in the entangled state implies. This measurement protocol establishes a measured fact. You cannot conclude anything about something, which could have been measured, but hasn't been measured.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn and Morbert
  • #244
vanhees71 said:
the microcausality constraint on local observables, i.e., there cannot be a mutual influence of A's and B's measurements if the "measurement events" (photon-detection events) are space-like separated
The "microcausality constraint" is that spacelike separated measurements must commute. That doesn't rule out a "mutual influence" altogether; it just means that any such "influence" cannot depend on the order in which the measurements occur. Some might say that rules out any "influence" at all, but others might disagree.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #245
PeterDonis said:
And the entangled state that was prepared. I don't understand why you keep leaving this out.
A: There is no variable from the entangled state (other than I guess a selection of type of conservation rule) that is a part of the quantum expectation value. Further, Bell ruled out predetermined elements of the superposition/entanglement as being an explanation of the outcome statistics. That only leaves things that happen from the first measurement to the second measurement (and regardless of order or reference frame) as being part of the mechanism we wish to understand. That's the time during which we go from an entangled 2 particle system to 2 systems of 1 particle. We don't know what happens during this period, when both particles end up in sharply defined spin states (if that is what we are measuring).

Only Alice and Bob's settings matter, that's the math. For polarization entangled photon pairs, the relevant term is: cos^2(theta) where theta is the difference between Alice's setting and Bob's setting.
 
  • #246
DrChinese said:
There is no variable from the entangled state (other than I guess a selection of type of conservation rule) that is a part of the quantum expectation value.
Yes, there is: the relative amplitudes of the terms in the entangled state. The only reason this doesn't appear in Bell's papers is that Bell assumed a particular entangled state (the singlet state) for which the ratio of amplitudes (or more precisely its squared modulus) is ##1## so it drops out of the formulas. But if we consider all possible entangled states of two qubits, the relative amplitudes of the terms in the particular entangled state we prepare will certainly contribute to the expectation value.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK
  • #247
PeterDonis said:
The "microcausality constraint" is that spacelike separated measurements must commute. That doesn't rule out a "mutual influence" altogether; it just means that any such "influence" cannot depend on the order in which the measurements occur. Some might say that rules out any "influence" at all, but others might disagree.
It rules out causal connections between space-like separated events, because the time evolution in the Heisenberg picture is described by the equation of motion,
$$\partial_t \hat{O}(x)=\frac{1}{\mathrm{i}} [\hat{O(x)},\hat{H}],$$
where
$$\hat{H}=\int_{\mathbb{R}^3} \mathrm{d}^3 y \hat{\mathcal{H}}(t_y,\vec{y}).$$
Plugging this in the said equation of motion together with the microcausality constraint, which by construction holds particularly for the commutators of any local observable and the Hamilton density, the only contribution in the time evolution can come from arguments ##x## and ##y## that are light-like or time-like separated. Thus the commutation at space-like distances rules out causal actions over space-like separated events.

It's of course also true that the measurement results, including the correlations between local measurements at time-like separated measurement events, are not "time ordered" in any sense. You can always find an inertial frame, where the measurements are completed simultaneously. The temporal order of space-like separated events is frame-dependent, and that's why they cannot be causally connected by definition, and that's why one assumes the microcausality constraint and last but not least that's why it's called microcausality contraint.
 
  • #248
vanhees71 said:
the only contribution in the time evolution can come from arguments and that are light-like or time-like separated
What "time evolution" are we talking about? It looks to me like this concept in QFT as you are describing it is frame-dependent.
 
  • #249
PeterDonis said:
Yes, there is: the relative amplitudes of the terms in the entangled state. The only reason this doesn't appear in Bell's papers is that Bell assumed a particular entangled state (the singlet state) for which the ratio of amplitudes (or more precisely its squared modulus) is ##1## so it drops out of the formulas. But if we consider all possible entangled states of two qubits, the relative amplitudes of the terms in the particular entangled state we prepare will certainly contribute to the expectation value.

Who cares if you *can* add variables in, that's a red herring. Bell tests don't do that! Reference:

https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9810080

"In a rather general form the CHSH inequality reads S(α, α′ , β, β′ ) = |E(α, β) − E(α ′ , β)| + +|E(α, β′ ) + E(α ′ , β′ )| ≤ 2. Quantum theory predicts a sinusoidal dependence for the coincidence rate Cqm++(α, β) ∝ sin2 (β − α) on the difference angle of the analyzer directions in Alice’s and Bob’s experiments."

I don't see anything other than settings for Alice and Bob. According to theory, and as far as can be determined from all experiments ever run: every individual entangled pair used in a Bell test is 100% identical in all respects to every other pair. This is canon. You'd have to agree with this, and as such, we are right back to where I started. Only Alice and Bob's settings matter. (And yes of course, you must be operating on entangled pairs - I am not questioning that particular point.)
 
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost and vanhees71
  • #250
DrChinese said:
Who cares if you *can* add variables in, that's a red herring.
I'm not talking about "adding variables". An entangled state of two qubits will have at least two terms, and those terms will have relative amplitudes that have physical meaning. Those "variables" are already there. There's no need to "add" anything.

DrChinese said:
Bell tests don't do that!
Bell test experiments and theoretical discussions, including the paper you reference, are all done using only a very limited number of all of the possible entangled states of the qubits involved. Those states, as I've already said, are constructed so the amplitudes of all the terms (or more precisely their squared moduli) are equal, so their ratios are ##1## and drop out of the formulas. That doesn't mean those "variables" aren't there; it just means the experiments and theoretical discussions are focused on particular states where those "variables" drop out of the formulas.

DrChinese said:
I don't see anything other than settings for Alice and Bob.
Of course not, because you're looking at the formula for states where all of the amplitudes of the terms are equal so their ratios drop out of the formulas.

If you want to see what happens when the amplitudes of the terms are not equal, try doing a similar analysis to the one that predicts violations of the CHSH inequality, but for this state:

$$
\ket{\Psi} = \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} \ket{H}_1 \ket{V}_2 + \sqrt{\frac{2}{3}} e^{i \varphi} \ket{V}_1 \ket{H}_2
$$
 
Back
Top