I Help Needed: Understanding Hungerford's Algebra Book Proofs

mr.tea
Messages
101
Reaction score
12
I am trying to learn about free groups(as part of my Bachelor's thesis), and was assigned with Hungerford's Algebra book. Unfortunately, the book uses some aspects from category theory(which I have not learned). If someone has an access to the book and can help me, I would be grateful.

First, in theorem 9.1(2003 edition), he proves that the set of all reduced words, ##F(X)##, of a given set X is a group(under the operation defined), using "Van Der Waerden trick". At some point in the proof he says:" since ## 1 \mapsto x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}} ## under the map ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##, then it follows that ##\varphi## is injective". Can you please explain to me how did he get this conclusion?

Second, in the same proof, he found that this ##\varphi## is a bijection between a set and a group, and therefore concludes that since the group is associative then also the set is. Why is that?

Thank you.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
mr.tea said:
I am trying to learn about free groups(as part of my Bachelor's thesis), and was assigned with Hungerford's Algebra book. Unfortunately, the book uses some aspects from category theory(which I have not learned). If someone has an access to the book and can help me, I would be grateful.

First, in theorem 9.1(2003 edition), he proves that the set of all reduced words, ##F(X)##, of a given set X is a group(under the operation defined), using "Van Der Waerden trick". At some point in the proof he says:" since ## 1 \mapsto x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}} ## under the map ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##, then it follows that ##\varphi## is injective". Can you please explain to me how did he get this conclusion?

Second, in the same proof, he found that this ##\varphi## is a bijection between a set and a group, and therefore concludes that since the group is associative then also the set is. Why is that?

Thank you.
I cannot answer your first question, because I don't have the book and thus don't know, what exactly your ingredients are: Bartel's trick, the definition of ##|.|## or ##\varphi## and what had happened in the proof until this point. So I'll fold here.

The second question is easier to answer. Let's say we have a bijection ##\varphi : (G,\cdot) \longrightarrow X## from a group into and onto a set. Then we simply can define ##x_1 \circ x_2 := \varphi (\varphi^{-1}(x_1) \cdot \varphi^{-1}(x_2))## as a binary operation on ##X## and the group properties are ##1:1## transported from ##G## to ##(X,\circ )##.

Of course you'll still have to formally prove, that this definition provides associativity. First check whether it is well-defined, then that ##\varphi (g) \circ \varphi (h) = \varphi (g\cdot h)## and next ##(x \circ y) \circ z = x \circ (y \circ z)##.
 
Last edited:
mr.tea said:
First, in theorem 9.1(2003 edition), he proves that the set of all reduced words, ##F(X)##, of a given set X is a group(under the operation defined), using "Van Der Waerden trick". At some point in the proof he says:" since ## 1 \mapsto x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}} ## under the map ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##, then it follows that ##\varphi## is injective". Can you please explain to me how did he get this conclusion?
The map ##\varphi## is from the set ##F## of all reduced words to a subgroup of the group of all bijections of ##F##. It maps the word ##x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}## to the bijection of ##F## denoted by ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##. If ##\varphi## is not injective, then it would take a word ##x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}\not = 1## to the identity map of ##F##. But the image is the map ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##, which takes the element ##1## of ##F## to the element ##x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}##, and therefore is not the identity map of ##F##, so ##\varphi## is injective.
 
mr.tea said:
Second, in the same proof, he found that this ##\varphi## is a bijection between a set and a group, and therefore concludes that since the group is associative then also the set is. Why is that?
It is a bit more than that. The set also has an operation and the map is not just a bijection, but also respects the operation i.e. ##\varphi(ab)=\varphi(a)\varphi(b)##. So you have

##\varphi(a(bc))=\varphi(a)\varphi(bc)=\varphi(a)(\varphi(b)\varphi(c))=(\varphi(a)\varphi(b))\varphi(c)=\varphi(ab)\varphi(c)=\varphi((ab)c)##

In the middle it is used that the you have associativity in the image, hence ##\varphi(a(bc))=\varphi((ab)c)##. And since ##\varphi## is a bijection you have ##a(bc)=(ab)c##.
 
fresh_42 said:
I cannot answer your first question, because I don't have the book and thus don't know, what exactly your ingredients are: Bartel's trick, the definition of ##|.|## or ##\varphi## and what had happened in the proof until this point. So I'll fold here.

The second question is easier to answer. Let's say we have a bijection ##\varphi : (G,\cdot) \longrightarrow X## from a group into and onto a set. Then we simply can define ##x_1 \circ x_2 := \varphi (\varphi^{-1}(x_1) \cdot \varphi^{-1}(x_2))## as a binary operation on ##X## and the group properties are ##1:1## transported from ##G## to ##(X,\circ )##.

Of course you'll still have to formally prove, that this definition provides associativity. First check whether it is well-defined, then that ##\varphi (g) \circ \varphi (h) = \varphi (g\cdot h)## and next ##(x \circ y) \circ z = x \circ (y \circ z)##.

Thank you for your answer!

martinbn said:
If ##\varphi## is not injective, then it would take a word ##x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}\not = 1## to the identity map of ##F##. But the image is the map ##|x_{1}^{\delta_{1}}|\cdots |x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}| ##, which takes the element ##1## of ##F## to the element ##x_{1}^{\delta_{1}} \cdots x_{n}^{\delta_{n}}##, and therefore is not the identity map of ##F##, so ##\varphi## is injective.

I am sorry. Can you explain a bit more about this part?

martinbn said:
It is a bit more than that. The set also has an operation and the map is not just a bijection, but also respects the operation i.e. ##\varphi(ab)=\varphi(a)\varphi(b)##. So you have

##\varphi(a(bc))=\varphi(a)\varphi(bc)=\varphi(a)(\varphi(b)\varphi(c))=(\varphi(a)\varphi(b))\varphi(c)=\varphi(ab)\varphi(c)=\varphi((ab)c)##

In the middle it is used that the you have associativity in the image, hence ##\varphi(a(bc))=\varphi((ab)c)##. And since ##\varphi## is a bijection you have ##a(bc)=(ab)c##.

Thank you very much, now it's understandable.

Thank you.
 
Back
Top