wle said:
You've lost me. What are ##A##, ##B##, and ##x## supposed to be in the context of Kolmogorov probability theory and what do they have to do with the assumptions ##v(A + B) = v(A) + v(B)## and ##v(AB) = v(A) v(B)## for commuting quantum observables ##A## and ##B## in the Kochen-Specker theorem?
Is it really so hard to understand? The assumptions of the Kochen-Specker theorem require that the valuations of quantum observables follow the same rules as the valuations of classical random variables. Since the valuation of a classical random variable is given by ##v(A) = A(x)## and a the product of classical random variables is defined by ##(AB)(x) := A(x)B(x)##, the requirements of Kochen-Specker follow (same for addition). Kochen-Specker says that one cannot represent quantum observables on a classical probability space without having to redefine multiplication of addition of random variables.
I don't think you've justified that. You haven't proved that the assumptions behind the Kochen-Specker theorem are equivalent to or follow from the axioms of Kolmogorov probability theory, and proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem don't claim any such thing.
I (or rather Kochen and Specker themselves) have proven that not all quantum observables can be represented as classical random variables on a classical probability space. This is also not my personal claim, but it is standard knowledge that can be looked up in pretty much every book on quantum mechanics.
Likewise, theorems that don't use all of Kolmogorov's axioms are not necessarily restricted to Kolmogorov probability theory. Kolmogorov probability theory requires that the joint event ##A \wedge B## exists for all events ##A## and ##B##, like you say. Bell's theorem, for example, does not require that all possible joint events exist.
Of course, Bell's theorem requires that, because it wants to make statements about
all possible events. Otherwise it can only make statements like: "Among the events
that are commuting with ##A## and ##B##, none can be a common cause" or "No theory of local hidden variables
for events commuting with ##A## and ##B## can reproduce all predictions of QM". Of course, for a classical probability theory, this is the same as Bell's theorem, since all classical random variables commute. But it would be a weak result for QM, since it doesn't allow to conclude the non-existence of a common cause or non-locality in QM, since in QM, there are also events not commuting with ##A## and ##B##.
Why should that make a difference? If you accept that quantum correlations can be simulated by two computers communicating with each other faster than light, then you can certainly ask if two computers could simulate quantum correlations without communicating faster than light.
Two computers of course cannot do that, since they are classical objects. You need quantum objects to generate quantum statistics. The analogy with computers makes no sense here.
This is why I say your insistence on Kolmogorov probability theory isn't relevant.
Of course, it is highly relevant. It is really super trivial: Concepts that only work in Kolmogorov probability theory cannot be applied outside of Kolmogorov probability theory. Apparently, you deny this simple fact.
It is not difficult to program a computer to output random results in accord with the Born rule, and two computers allowed to communicate FTL could be programmed to simulate arbitrary quantum correlations. If you insist that we can only reason about causality, Reichenbach's principle, etc. within a certain mathematical framework, and that framework doesn't accommodate something I can simulate on a computer, then I'd say it's not a good framework to begin with.
You can of course simulate quantum physics on a computer, but you cannot have computers behave like quantum objects. There is no logical problem here. My whole point is that quantum theory is not a classical probability theory. This is really standard and well-known and it makes no sense to doubt it. Hence, concepts that require classical probability theory, just don't work anymore in the context of quantum mechanics. This is a fact of life. Of course, you can prefer Bohmian mechanics, but then you can only use the old concepts to make statements about Bohmian mechanics and
not about quantum theory.
It's the same if you look at the historical origins behind Bell's theorem. Essentially, Bell was aware that nonlocal hidden variable models like the de Broglie-Bohm interpretation could reproduce the predictions of quantum physics, and he was interested in the question of whether a local hidden variable model could achieve the same thing.
Yes and of course he proved that no local
hidden variable model can make the same predictions as QM. One cannot prove the theorem without the assumption of hidden variables. Hence, the theorem says nothing about theories without hidden variables, such as QM.
So, similarly, if your framework for discussing causality doesn't accommodate the de Broglie-Bohm interpretation then it is not relevant to understanding Bell's theorem, at least not in the way Bell thought about it.
First of all, it is not
my framework, but the generally accepted framework of physics. What I am saying is generally agreed upon by all working physicists. Of course, dBB theory can be formulated within this framework. Then you just can't prove Bell's theorem anymore. However, dBB theory can also be formulated as a classical probability theory and hence, Bell's theorem applies. This is only possible, since dBB theory doesn't have all the quantum observables as random variables, since the KS theorem prohibits it. Not even Bohmians deny this.