Index Notation & Dirac Notation

  • #101
stevendaryl said:
Well, whatever it is that you want to call the expression \langle \Phi|O|\Phi \rangle, it's an assumption that it's equal to the average value of observable O in the state described by |\Phi\rangle.

But it is not an assumption different from the assumption that it is the expectation value of the observable.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #102
atyy said:
I don't agree. The expectation and the average value are the same by definition in probability. One is the formal term, the other is the informal term.
Nitpicking a bit: Both have formal definitions, and they're different. There are theorems ("laws of large numbers") that prove that the average converges in at least two different ways to the expectation value.

I was ignoring that there's a formal definition of "average". My point was that regardless of what mathematical terms we define, the physics is in the assumptions that tell us how the math is related to the real world. I consider this a supremely important fact; it's the very foundation of the philosophy of mathematics and science. Because of this, I find it rather odd that pretty much everyone but me (definitely not just you) are going out of their way to avoid mentioning these correspondence rules explicitly. Instead they seem to prefer to connect mathematics to reality simply by using the same term for the real-world thing and the corresponding mathematical thing. This is what people do with "proper time" in the relativity forum. I don't like it because it hides what we're really doing.

Edit: Even though "average" and "expectation value" are essentially the same in pure mathematics (because of the laws of large numbers), there's a difference between these concepts and the real-world average, i.e. the average of the measurement results in an actual experiment. The assumption that the real-world average is equal to a number given by a mathematical formula, is a fundamental assumption. This correspondence rule is a hugely important part of the definition of the theory.

atyy said:
I do agree that it is an additional assumption to say that probability is operationally defined as relative frequency.
Probability is typically defined something like this: Let ##X=\{1,2,3,4,5,6\}##. I'll use the notation ##|E|## for the number of elements of ##E##. For each ##E\subseteq X##, define ##P(E)=|E|/|X|##. For each ##E\subseteq X##, the number ##P(E)## is called the probability of E. Note that there's no connection to the real world whatsoever. The probability measure P is just an assignment of numbers in the interval [0,1] to subsets of some set X. Now we can turn this piece of pure mathematics into a falsifiable theory about the real world with a few simple assumptions. Some of them are common to all probability theories. But at least one assumption is part of the definition of the specific probability theory. In our case, that assumption can be that the elements of the set X correspond to the possible results of a roll of a six-sided die.

stevendaryl said:
Well, whatever it is that you want to call the expression \langle \Phi|O|\Phi \rangle, it's an assumption that it's equal to the average value of observable O in the state described by |\Phi\rangle.
atyy said:
But it is not an assumption different from the assumption that it is the expectation value of the observable.
If "average" refers to the average of the results of actual measurements, then I would say that it's definitely a different assumption. Not only that. It's a very different kind of assumption.

There's a mathematical definition that associates the term "expectation value" with that number. There's a mathematical definition that associates the term "average" with something else. There are theorems that tell us how the average converges to the expectation value. But all of this is pure mathematics. The physics is in the correspondence rules, not in the mathematics, and in this case, the correspondence rule is the assumption that the expectation value is equal to the real-world average (not just the "formal average", i.e. the number that the laws of large numbers are making claims about).
 
Last edited:
  • #103
Fredrik said:
Nitpicking a bit: Both have formal definitions, and they're different. There are theorems ("laws of large numbers") that prove that the average converges in at least two different ways to the expectation value.

I was ignoring that there's a formal definition of "average". My point was that regardless of what mathematical terms we define, the physics is in the assumptions that tell us how the math is related to the real world. I consider this a supremely important fact; it's the very foundation of the philosophy of mathematics and science. Because of this, I find it rather odd that pretty much everyone but me (definitely not just you) are going out of their way to avoid mentioning these correspondence rules explicitly. Instead they seem to prefer to connect mathematics to reality simply by using the same term for the real-world thing and the corresponding mathematical thing. This is what people do with "proper time" in the relativity forum. I don't like it because it hides what we're really doing.

I agree with your point, but not your nitpicking. The link you give always uses the term "sample average" in the theorems, not the unqualified "average". The main quirk with my terminology is that the unqualified "average" most usually means "mean", which is simply a particular expectation value, ie. the first cumulant. However, I meant it as a synonym for "expectation value". For example, in my colloquial way of using the word "average", the variance is the average of the squared deviation from the mean. Basically, in all my statements I am assuming (1) Kolmogorov axioms (2) relative frequency interpretation of probability, but that is even before quantum mechanics, ie. I assume it for Mendelian genetics and classical statistical mechanics. My assumption (2) is the same as what you are calling the "correspondence" between maths and physics.
 
  • #104
Fredrik said:
Nitpicking a bit: Both have formal definitions, and they're different. There are theorems ("laws of large numbers") that prove that the average converges in at least two different ways to the expectation value.

True. But they are in probability (the weak law) and almost surely (the strong law). To apply them you are going to have to make some assumption such as for all practical purposes if a probability is infinitesimally close to one you can take it as a dead cert. People tend to do that sort of thing unconsciously without even realizing it, such is the very intuitive understanding we all have of probability.

Fredrik said:
My point was that regardless of what mathematical terms we define, the physics is in the assumptions that tell us how the math is related to the real world. I consider this a supremely important fact; it's the very foundation of the philosophy of mathematics and science.

You are correct.

But in applied math, especially with regard to probability, people generally aren't that careful and you make all sorts of unconscious assumptions you generally aren't even aware of when applying it.

That's the reason QM can seem like applied math rather than physics. Its we have this very intuitive understanding of probability that gets us by.

I think most physicists, unlike applied math guys, haven't even done an advanced course on probability and statistical modelling and get by just fine. Pure math guys - that's another story - there are very subtle issues associated with a rigorous approach to probability such as the proof a Wiener process actually exists, is continuous but nowhere differentiable.

In QM as far as an axiomatic treatment is concerned I use Kolmogorov's axioms. Each interpretation, in applying it, has a slightly different take on how its done eg the ensemble interpretation is very frequentest in character, but Copenhagen is rather Bayesian.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #105
WannabeNewton said:
I understand where your state of distraught comes from. In statistical mechanics we take the partition function of a system at equilibrium with an external heat bath and calculate quantities like average pressure, magnetic susceptibility, average energy etc. which all clearly have very important physical applications and are put to use extensively everyday in calculations.

In QM, if I have a pure state, what use are the expectation values of all the observables relevant to the system? What can I actually do with these expectation values? Sure I can calculate them at whim but can I put actually them to use in other calculations of physical applications? Do they hold the same all-important place that they do in statistical thermodynamics? You probably remember them showing up in non-degenerate and degenerate first order time-independent perturbation theory but where else do they show up?

Are these questions more representative of your own?

Why do I solve the Schrodinger Equation for? Why are Energy levels important? etc. I know nothing about the theory behind QM. I know only how to calculate questions that come up.
 
  • #106
TheAustrian said:
Why do I solve the Schrodinger Equation for? Why are Energy levels important? etc. I know nothing about the theory behind QM. I know only how to calculate questions that come up.

Schroedinger's equation is the notional counterpart to Newton's second law. It is the equation of motion. In classical mechanics, the state of a particle is specified by its position and momentum. If you know the state at one time, Newton's second law tells you the state any other time. In quantum mechanics, the state is a unit vector (more strictly speaking, the state is a ray that can be represented as a unit vector), such as the wave function. If you know the state at any time between two particular measurements, Schroedinger's equation tells you the state at any other time between those two particular measurements.

Energy levels are important for two reasons. The first reason is that energy levels can be measured by spectroscopy, so checking that quantum mechanics predicts the energy levels observed is an important check that quantum mechanics is correct.

A second, more technical reason that energy levels are important is that they determine the time evolution of a wave function that is an energy eigenstate. The time evolution of any wave function can be written as the superposition of the time evolution of individual energy eigenstates. But this technical reason is just applied mathematics, not physics.
 
Last edited:
Back
Top