Newtonian force as a covariant or contravariant quantity

  • #51
Yes, so with this perspective... regarding energy [and action] as primary

it is probably best to think of
force in units of "Joules per meter" (rather than Newtons or kg*m/s^2)
and
momentum in units of "action per meter" (rather than kg*m/s)

(Electric field in units of Volts/meter suggests that it is a covector.)
("g" "acceleration due to gravity" [or better "gravitational field" \vec g] should probably be "(Joules/kg) per meter"... is there a "gravitational volt"?)
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
With respect to the idea that integration is about forms, one of the things that I found confusing at first was the concept of integration being used. This article talks a bit about the various definitions, and the definition relevant to forms is the signed definite integral. http://www.math.ucla.edu/~tao/preprints/forms.pdf. Tao remarks "The concept of a closed form corresponds to that of a conservative force in physics (and an exact form corresponds to the concept of having a potential function)." And "Because Rn is a Euclidean vector space, it comes with a dot product ... which can be used to describe 1-forms in terms of vector fields (or equivalently, to identify cotangent vectors and tangent vectors) ... However, we shall avoid this notation because it gives the misleading impression that Euclidean structures such as the dot product are an essential aspect of the integration on differential forms concept, which can lead to confusion when one generalises this concept to more general manifolds on which the natural analogue of the dot product (namely, a Riemannian metric) might be unavailable."
 
Last edited:
  • #53
stevendaryl said:
This is a very interesting topic. In Newtonian physics, there are two different ways to define "force":

  1. F^i = m \dfrac{dU^i}{dt}, where U is velocity/
  2. F_i = -\partial_j \Phi, where \Phi is potential energy.

The first would lead you to think of force as a vector, and the second would lead you to think that it is a co-vector. From experience with General Relativity, one learns to suspect that if there is a confusion between vectors and co-vectors, then that means the metric tensor is secretly at work. Using the metric tensor g_ij you can certainly resolve the tension by writing:

m g_{ij} \dfrac{dU^i}{dt} = F_j

But that's a little unsatisfying, because there is a sense in which there is no metric tensor for Newtonian physics. Why do I say that? Well, if you formulate Newtonian physics on Galilean spacetime, there are two different notions of distances between points:
  1. The time between events.
  2. For events taking place at the same time, the distance between events.

The latter notion of distance between events is undefined in Galilean spacetime for two events that are not simultaneous. So that makes me wonder: what is the covariant notion of spatial distance in Galilean spacetime? It's not a tensor, so what is it?
Well, it seems to me that calling either Newtonian or galilean models of space and time "spacetime" is not very rigorous and a bit of a stretch of the terminology if we look at the mathematical dfinitions, they are just collection of points rather than proper (pseudo)Riemannian manifolds like say Minkowski spacetime is. Sure nowaday everybody calls them spacetimes , but they simply look like parametrizations of either 3D Euclidean space (Newtonian "spacetime") or 3D affine space (galilean "spacetime").
Once one realizes this it seems straightforward (just by reading Tao's quote that atyy links above), that one can easily go from the covector to the vector form and viceversa, there'll be physical situations that mathematically naturally correspond to the vector or the covector form like have been commented for force, momentum, acceleration, etc, but it seems besides the point to try to decide whether a physical quantity is "really" a pure vector or a covector, it depends on how it mathematically acts or it's acted upon in the specific physical situation one uses it.
 
Last edited:
  • #54
stevendaryl said:
In Newtonian physics, time is both a coordinate and a parameter. It's a coordinate, because just as in SR, it takes 4 numbers to locate something in Galilean spacetime.

I'd say you need 3 numbers for each parametrized hypersurface.
 
  • #55
TrickyDicky said:
Well, it seems to me that calling either Newtonian or galilean models of space and time "spacetime" is not very rigorous and a bit of a stretch of the terminology if we look at the mathematical dfinitions, they are just collection of points rather than poper manifolds like say Minkowski spacetime is. Sure nowaday everybody calls them spacetimes , but they simply look like parametrizations of either 3D Euclidean space (Newtonian "spacetime") or 3D affine space (galilean "spacetime").

The Newtonian spacetime (as in the Malament article referenced http://www.socsci.uci.edu/~dmalamen/bio/papers/GRSurvey.pdf#page=37) certainly requires more work since there the metric tensor is degenerate (unlike in Minkowski spacetime and in GR-spacetimes). However, by providing additional structure [a connection] (which one gets for free with a nondegenerate metric), one is able to formulate Newtonian gravity in a 4-D spacetime setting.

Part of the philosophy behind such attempts is that
one is asking does one really need to regard the metric as fundamental? Or should it be the connection or its curvature tensor? Or the causal structure? ... Then, what else is needed to recover what you take for granted?
For example, there is the Ehlers-Pirani-Schild Construction
http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10714-012-1352-5?LI=true
http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10714-012-1353-4
which quotes an old theorem by Weyl "The projective and conformal structures of a metric space determine uniquely its metric."

A simpler case of the Galilean spacetime that I've been mentioning is actually well defined projectively as a Cayley-Klein Geometry, which includes Euclidean, Minkowski, and De-Sitter and Anti-Sitter spacetimes and their "Galilean limits", as well as the more-familiar non-euclidean hyperbolic and elliptical spaces. Yes, some stretching of definitions was needed to accept hyperbolic geometry as a legitimate geometry... and that's what projective geometry did. The Cayley-Klein formulation shows how similar those 9 geometries are to each other. In fact, one can relax definitions in order to describe all 9 in a unified way. That's what I am trying to do, with an eye to relativity.

Degenerate structures are actually not as bad as they sound.
From a projective-geometry viewpoint, our familiar Euclidean geometry has some degenerate structures. For example, there is no natural length scale in Euclidean geometry... one has to choose one... unlike in say elliptic/spherical geometry.
 
  • #56
atyy said:
This article talks a bit about the various definitions, and the definition relevant to forms is the signed definite integral. http://www.math.ucla.edu/~tao/preprints/forms.pdf.
Thanks for the link to the Tao article --it's great! Unlike a lot of material on differential forms, it's not written in Martian.
 
  • #57
TrickyDicky said:
Well, it seems to me that calling either Newtonian or galilean models of space and time "spacetime" is not very rigorous and a bit of a stretch of the terminology if we look at the mathematical dfinitions, they are just collection of points rather than poper manifolds like say Minkowski spacetime is. Sure nowaday everybody calls them spacetimes , but they simply look like parametrizations of either 3D Euclidean space (Newtonian "spacetime") or 3D affine space (galilean "spacetime").

Galilean spacetime is absolutely a 4-dimensional manifold, so it isn't any kind of stretch to apply the term "spacetime". It's a manifold without a metric, but it's certainly a manifold.
 
  • #58
TrickyDicky said:
Once one realizes this it seems straightforward (just by reading Tao's quote that atyy links above), that one can easily go from the covector to the vector form and viceversa

But in the absence of a metric, you CAN'T go from one to the other. That's why to me 4-D Galilean spacetime is interesting, because it is an example of a manifold without a metric.
 
  • #59
stevendaryl said:
But in the absence of a metric, you CAN'T go from one to the other. That's why to me 4-D Galilean spacetime is interesting, because it is an example of a manifold without a metric.

It has a metric... but it's degenerate.
In terms of raising/lowering indices, you can go one way... but not the other.
 
  • #60
TrickyDicky said:
I'd say you need 3 numbers for each parametrized hypersurface.

And you need one number to say which hypersurface. That's 4.
 
  • #61
stevendaryl said:
But in the absence of a metric, you CAN'T go from one to the other. That's why to me 4-D Galilean spacetime is interesting, because it is an example of a manifold without a metric.
It is just \mathbb{R}^{4} with the standard topology and with a preferred set of coordinates (because of the preferred frames). The standard euclidean metric tensor is valid. If you are describing the same set but with some other topology then you have to show that it is a topological manifold with respect to that topology before even proceeding.
 
  • #62
By "metric", I think stevendaryl is referring to the physically-motivated metric that will model the situation.
 
  • #63
stevendaryl said:
Galilean spacetime is absolutely a 4-dimensional manifold, so it isn't any kind of stretch to apply the term "spacetime". It's a manifold without a metric, but it's certainly a manifold.
Might be a manifold but I was referring (I added the qualification in my post now to make it more clear) to the word "spacetime" as defined in Wikipedia: "For physical reasons, a spacetime continuum is mathematically defined as a four-dimensional, smooth, connected Lorentzian manifold (M,g)." Which seems to imply it needs a Lorentzian metric to qualify as a Spacetime.
In any case my point wasn't exactly about terminology, see my answer to your other post below.
 
  • #64
stevendaryl said:
But in the absence of a metric, you CAN'T go from one to the other. That's why to me 4-D Galilean spacetime is interesting, because it is an example of a manifold without a metric.

The fact is what you say is true for general manifolds. But I think in Euclidean or in general flat manifolds there exists a canonical identification between vectors and covectors even in the absence of a metric, just as long as one uses a canonical basis, by virtue of the equivalence of their tangent and cotangent spaces with the manifolds itself:the galilean spacetime manifold is a vector space R^4 even in the absence of a metric tensor, right?
 
Last edited:
  • #65
stevendaryl said:
And you need one number to say which hypersurface. That's 4.

Well by that formula any parametrized object is a manifold with n+1 dimensions because you need one more number to specify where you are looking at. That IMO goes against the concept of manifold as an intrinsically defined object with no need to go to an ambient space.
 
  • #66
TrickyDicky said:
Well by that formula any parametrized object is a manifold with n+1 dimensions because you need one more number to specify where you are looking at.

Yes, any parametrized object, you can treat the parameter as another dimension. But there is a much more intimate connection between the dimensions in the case of time, which is that equations of motion explicitly relate what's happening on one time slice to what's happening on another time slice---that's what an "equation of motion" is.

That IMO goes against the concept of manifold as an intrinsically defined object with no need to go to an ambient space.

No, it doesn't. A manifold is any object that is locally like R^n.
 
  • #67
stevendaryl said:
Yes, any parametrized object, you can treat the parameter as another dimension. But there is a much more intimate connection between the dimensions in the case of time, which is that equations of motion explicitly relate what's happening on one time slice to what's happening on another time slice---that's what an "equation of motion" is.

No, it doesn't. A manifold is any object that is locally like R^n.

I've been trying to think of some sense in which Galilean spacetime is less of a real manifold than Minkowsky spacetime, but I don't think that there really is one. If you're thinking that in Minkowsky spacetime, there is some kind of symmetry (Lorentz transforms) mixing space and time, I don't see why the Galilean transform doesn't count.
 
  • #68
stevendaryl said:
I've been trying to think of some sense in which Galilean spacetime is less of a real manifold than Minkowsky spacetime, but I don't think that there really is one. If you're thinking that in Minkowsky spacetime, there is some kind of symmetry (Lorentz transforms) mixing space and time, I don't see why the Galilean transform doesn't count.

But I'm not saying that Galilean "spacetime" is not a manifold, I was objecting to calling it spacetime if by spacetime we understand a manifold with Lorentzian metric.
 
  • #69
stevendaryl said:
Yes, any parametrized object, you can treat the parameter as another dimension. But there is a much more intimate connection between the dimensions in the case of time, which is that equations of motion explicitly relate what's happening on one time slice to what's happening on another time slice---that's what an "equation of motion" is.
No, it doesn't. A manifold is any object that is locally like R^n.
Sure, again, I'm not arguing here that the Galilean model is not a manifold, here I was talking about the parametrized 3-space versus the 4-manifold and which looks more natural. I guess both views are ok, I just find it more natural to use the former, which is the one we are used to from classical mechanics, the 4-manifold representation is more of a modern retelling in the light of what we know about relativity and Lorentzian manifolds.
 
  • #70
stevendaryl said:
No, it doesn't. A manifold is any object that is locally like R^n.
There are more conditions than just that for a topological space to be a manifold. Anyways it seems like it is just turning out to be an issue of semantics regarding whether galiliean space - time is a "space - time". From what I'm seeing it seems to be a commonly used terminology and I don't see any reason to object it regardless. Also one can take a look at this: http://ls.poly.edu/~jbain/spacetime/lectures/11.Spacetime.pdf
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #71
TrickyDicky said:
But I'm not saying that Galilean "spacetime" is not a manifold, I was objecting to calling it spacetime if by spacetime we understand a manifold with Lorentzian metric.

Oh. Well, that's a matter of taste. Since the manifold includes both space and time, it seems to me that it should be called "spacetime".
 
  • #72
WannabeNewton said:
There are more conditions than just that for a topological space to be a manifold.

I don't think so. The definition of an n-dimensional manifold is a topological space such that every neighborhood is homeomorphic to the Euclidean space of dimension n.
 
  • #73
There are various definitions of topological manifolds and they all take conditions on top of locally Euclidean. One very common definition is a topological manifold must also be Hausdorff and second countable. Other definitions pertaining to separability but not Hausdorff are also present. In GR we take manifolds that are Hausdorff and second countable as well as locally Euclidean. The condition you stated is not enough.
 
  • #74
Also it is not every neighborhood. There exists A neighborhood for every point on the manifold that is homeomorphic to an open subset of R^n
 
  • #75
I think that's also what Stevendaryl means.
 
  • #76
Then it should be clarified because there is a huge difference between saying each point has a neighborhood homeomorphic to R^n and saying every non empty element of the topology is homeomorphic to R^n.
 
  • #77
So what's the consensus on force as a covector if one considers things like friction? Is energy still a useful concept?
 
  • #78
It's probably fine.
Not all covectors are the "d" of some potential function...
so, presumably friction will be of that type.

This lecture note
http://bazzim.mit.edu/NR/rdonlyres/Aeronautics-and-Astronautics/16-61Aerospace-DynamicsSpring2003/53F21B11-4F88-4870-967A-0C05AD85B104/0/lecture10.pdf
from
http://bazzim.mit.edu/oeit/OcwWeb/Aeronautics-and-Astronautics/16-61Aerospace-DynamicsSpring2003/LectureNotes/index.htm
will probably be useful.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #79
robphy said:
It's probably fine.
Not all covectors are the "d" of some potential function...
so, presumably friction will be of that type.

This lecture note
http://bazzim.mit.edu/NR/rdonlyres/Aeronautics-and-Astronautics/16-61Aerospace-DynamicsSpring2003/53F21B11-4F88-4870-967A-0C05AD85B104/0/lecture10.pdf
from
http://bazzim.mit.edu/oeit/OcwWeb/Aeronautics-and-Astronautics/16-61Aerospace-DynamicsSpring2003/LectureNotes/index.htm
will probably be useful.

Perhaps more an aesthetic question - but is this natural or kludgey?

Could one try to argue that in classical GR one should take the Einstein equations as primary, rather than the Hilbert action, because the differential equations are unique, but the Lagrangian formulations of GR are not?
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #80
atyy said:
Perhaps more an aesthetic question - but is this natural or kludgey?

Could one try to argue that in classical GR one should take the Einstein equations as primary, rather than the Hilbert action, because the differential equations are unique, but the Lagrangian formulations of GR are not?

Lagrangians are never unique. You can always add terms to the Lagrangian that have no effect on the equations of motion.
 
  • #81
I certainly can't see why force and momentum would be "naturally" covectors, I just see that in certain physical situations they act as covectors, but just as naturally they act as as tangent vectors in other situations, basically by definition in F=ma, and p=mv, they are both proportional to clearly tangent velocity and acceleration vectors. Now of course just by using a metric tensor one can turn even velocity to a covector, but that's the point that has been made by several people here already, as long as one has a metric tensor it makes no sense to tell apart quantities as vectors or covectors in general. I don't think that is what Burke or the WP is trying to say at all. Burke was simply a very visual physicist that tried to see physics as geometrically as possible and from that POV he tried to make clear how ech physical quantity was acting geometrically in each situation.. It makes perfect sense that if one considers how a field of force acts on something to obtain a scalar (work), that force is acting as a covector field.

To introduce the Galilean 4-spacetime here can only bring confusion (though it might be useful in other instances like introducing relativity spacetime from classical mechanics as have been commented earlier) in this context due to its apparently degenerate metric (but a well defined affine connection , that as commented by stevendaryl gives an easy account of the fictitious forces of Newtonian mechanics)
 
  • #82
I think Burke is trying to find the correct geometrical model of a physical quantity.
To do so, he asks what is the minimum needed structure to perform a certain calculation of physical quantities.

In particular, he asks if a metric is needed.
If not, then he seeks the metric-free formulation and regards that as more fundamental,
which then suggests the appropriate geometrical representations.
Then, if there happens to be a metric is available, he certainly does not want to blur the distinctions because of that... that is to say, for forces, force is always a 1-form... and he'll never hide any use of the metric.

Here are some quotes from Burke's Applied Differential Geometry that support my statement above
http://books.google.com/books?id=58SFj9x5RMEC&q=metric#v=snippet&q=metric&f=false

and quotes from Burke's Spacetime, Geometry, Cosmology
http://books.google.com/books?id=nDGuQgAACAAJ

(highlighting mine)
(apologies for the excessive quoting... but these might clarify [my interpretation of] Burke's approach.)

Burke ADG said:
p.xii
Now, to compare the volumes of two parallelopipeds does not require a metric structure. A linear structure is sufficient.

p.xiii
This emphasis on concrete applications and proper geometric structures helps us avoid the formal symbol manipulations that so often lead to nonsense or fallacious proofs of correct results. [Look at Figure 3.1 in Soper (1976) or the horrible calculus of variations manipulations and mistakes in Goldstein (1959).] Here we will be able to turn most of the
infinitesimals commonly seen in physics into the appropriate geometric objects, usually into either rates (tangent vectors) or gradients (differential forms). The distinction between these is lost in the metric-blinded symbol pushing of tensor calculus.

p.1
The mathematics of this book can be thought of as the proper generalization of vector calculus, div. grad. curl, and all that, to spaces of higher dimension. The generalization is not obvious. Ordinary vector calculus is misleading because the vector cross product has special properties in three dimensions. This happens because, for n = 3, n and (1/2)n(n -1) are equal. It is also important to divorce the formalism from its reliance on a Euclidean metric, or any metric for that matter.
...

Also, a metric allows some accidental identifications that obscure the natural properties of the geometric structures.


p.20
A blindness caused by the unnecessary use of metrics afflicts many physicists; so they do not distinguish between vectors and covectors. It does take practice to develop an eye that sees relations in a metric-free fashion.


p.271
Every classical field theory must have a force law. Electrodynamics is a very special classical field theory. Force is geometrically a 1-form. Think of it either as the rate of change of momentum or as the operator taking displacements into energy changes.

p.311
Not all forces come from the gradients of potentials. In general, we only have a force 1-form telling us how much it costs to "push the system" in different directions.
... [ abstract calculation involving differential forms]
Any force that is not derivable from a potential can be treated this way. If the force in configuration space is given by f dq, [then we lift it up to a force on the contact bundle of f alpha, and find the system motion from the preceding exterior differential system, equation 47.1.]


Burke SGC said:
p.97
Some forces are derived from potentials. Such forces are clearly potentials gradients, that is, 1-forms. The amount of work done by a system in moving along a path in configuration space can be found by counting the net number of contour lines crossed. Any force field that can be derived from a potential does no work on a system which moves around any closed path. Not every force field can be written as the gradient of a potential. The force field sketched in Figure 18.3 cannot be derived from a potential. At any single point, however, any 1-form could have come from any number of functions.

How is it that we have been able to think of force as a tangent vector? If we are dealing with a configuration space which has a natural Euclidean space Euclidean geometry, then we can describe force as a tangent vector. The Euclidean metric let's us associate a tangent vector to every 1-form. This will be shown when we discuss metric tensors. We all learn mechanics by first studying the mechanics of a particle moving in Euclidean space. We must realize that this is a special situation.

A further payoff for having a clear geometric picture of force comes in situations involving constraints. A slippery constraint is one having no frictional forces. One usually says that the constraint force is perpendicular to the constraint surface. Now if you are truly learning to think covariantly with respect to linear transformations, you will see that this is a nonsense statement. Perpendicularity is a meaningless concept in any configuration space that does not accidentally happen to have a metric. The correct geometric view of a constraint is sketched in Figure 18.4. As a 1-form, the constraint force is parallel to the constraint surface, and parallelism is a properly covariant notion. Again, the non-covariant language comes from excessive attention to the peculiar features of particle mechanics in Euclidean space, features which do not generalize.

[from p xv. "Covariance": The changes in the rules and mathematical structures as one goes from one equivalent representation to another. The idea is that the representation is changing, whereas the physical situation is not.]
 
  • #83
Thanks for the relevant quotes.

robphy said:
I think Burke is trying to find the correct geometrical model of a physical quantity.
To do so, he asks what is the minimum needed structure to perform a certain calculation of physical quantities.
In particular, he asks if a metric is needed.
If not, then he seeks the metric-free formulation and regards that as more fundamental,
which then suggests the appropriate geometrical representations.
I guess I fail to see how this procedure is more geometrical, I have always thought of geometry as something related to distances and angles, and for that you need a metric. Sure there are computations such as the one mentioned about volumes of parallelepipeds that seem to not need the metric, but I think this is a good example of the hidden metric case Burke precisely is trying to avoid.
robphy said:
Then, if there happens to be a metric is available, he certainly does not want to blur the distinctions because of that... that is to say, for forces, force is always a 1-form... and he'll never hide any use of the metric.
I'm all for not hiding the use of metrics, somthing that is sistematically done in physics textbooks. But as long as one uses a metric the assertion "force is always a 1-form" makes no sense. And in physics we need a metric, all measurements are done in the form of lengths or angles or can be reduced to them.



Burke said:
p.xiii
Here we will be able to turn most of the
infinitesimals commonly seen in physics into the appropriate geometric objects, usually into either rates (tangent vectors) or gradients (differential forms). The distinction between these is lost in the metric-blinded symbol pushing of tensor calculus.

p.20
A blindness caused by the unnecessary use of metrics afflicts many physicists; so they do not distinguish between vectors and covectors. It does take practice to develop an eye that sees relations in a metric-free fashion.
I think here Burke misses the target, I can't see how being aware of the metric blinds anyone, on the contrary, not being aware that the metric tensor is acting can lead to confusion as Burke himself admits.

Burke said:
Perpendicularity is a meaningless concept in any configuration space that does not accidentally happen to have a metric. The correct geometric view of a constraint is sketched in Figure 18.4. As a 1-form, the constraint force is parallel to the constraint surface, and parallelism is a properly covariant notion. Again, the non-covariant language comes from excessive attention to the peculiar features of particle mechanics in Euclidean space, features which do not generalize.
Hmm, maybe it's just me but if perpendicularity is meaningless without a metric(wich probably is), I don't know how parallelism is any more meaningful, I mean one seems to need something resembling Euclidean space locally (actually its affine generalization) to have the notion of parallelism between lines.
 
  • #84
TrickyDicky said:
Hmm, maybe it's just me but if perpendicularity is meaningless without a metric(wich probably is), I don't know how parallelism is any more meaningful, I mean one seems to need something resembling Euclidean space locally (actually its affine generalization) to have the notion of parallelism between lines.

To see the problem with perpendicularity, let's take a look at a manifold having nothing to do with spatial distances. Imagine that your manifold represents thermodynamic states of some system (say, a certain quantity of a gas). We can label the states by a pair of numbers (P,V) representing the pressure and the volume.

Suppose I have four states: S_1 = (P_1,V_1), S_2 = (P_2,V_2), S_3 = (P_3,V_3) and S_4 = (P_4,V_4)

Define:

\delta(P)_{12} = P_2 - P_1
\delta(V)_{12} = V_2 - V_1
\delta(P)_{34} = P_4 - P_3
\delta(V)_{34} = V_4 - V_3

To say that the line from S_1 to S_2 is parallel to the line from S_3 to S_4 is to say that there is some nonzero real number \lambda such that:

\delta(P)_{34} = \lambda \delta(P)_{12}
\delta(V)_{34} = \lambda \delta(V)_{12}

So parallel displacement vectors are defined for this space. On the other hand, how would you define perpendicularity for displacement vectors? What does it mean to say that the line from S_1 to S_2 is perpendicular to the line from S_3 to S_4?

If the points were points in Euclidean space, and the coordinates were Cartesian, then we could say that the displacements are perpendicular if

\delta(P)_{12} \delta(P)_{34} + \delta(V)_{12}\delta(V)_{34} = 0

But that equation doesn't even make any sense for pressures and volumes. You can't add a square pressure to a square volume. In order to make sense of adding squared pressures and squared volumes, you need a conversion factor that relates pressure to volume.

So for a general abstract manifold, you can always make sense of parallel lines, but you can't always make sense of perpendicular lines.
 
  • #85
stevendaryl said:
So for a general abstract manifold, you can always make sense of parallel lines, but you can't always make sense of perpendicular lines.
Again this requires some additional structure; your example is not a archetype of the norm. For an arbitrary smooth manifold M and p,q\in M you can't just subtract p from q to get some vector in T_{p}(M) like you could geometrically in euclidean space. Neither can you just simply subtract some v\in T_{p}(M) from some u\in T_{q}(M). If you want to compare vectors that exist in different tangent spaces to the smooth manifold then you have to first define a connection \triangledown to go with M (you also need this connection to even talk about "lines" i.e. geodesics). The sense of parallelism that makes sense without that extra structure, and is the kind I'm sure the author is talking about, is just plain old linear dependence / independence of some u,v\in T_{p}(M) which we can make sense of simply by use of the vector space structure of the tangent space. If in addition we had a metric tensor defined on M, which is another additional structure that the author says need not be there a priori, then this metric tensor at each point is just an inner product on the tangent space at that point and of course we can then talk about orthogonality.
 
  • #86
WannabeNewton said:
Again this requires some additional structure; your example is not a archetype of the norm. For an arbitrary smooth manifold M and p,q\in M you can't just subtract p from q to get some vector in T_{p}(M) like you could geometrically in euclidean space.

The point of my example was to illustrate how it is possible to have a space with parallel lines, but no perpendicular lines.
 
  • #87
stevendaryl said:
The point of my example was to illustrate how it is possible to have a space with parallel lines, but no perpendicular lines.

Yes, but your final claim was:

stevendaryl said:
So for a general abstract manifold, you can always make sense of parallel lines

This is false. You need a connection in order to make sense of this, as wbn mentioned.
 
  • #88
micromass said:
Yes, but your final claim was:
This is false.

Fine. I feel that in a discussion, it is important to have the level of the discussion to be appropriate to the topic at hand, rather than in complete generality. The point of using displacements is that displacements give an intuitive idea of the tangent space, where a notion of "parallel" is always defined (in terms of one vector being a linear multiple of another).

The mathematical definition of the tangent space is a little involved. It's not something that people are familiar with just from learning vectors in the Euclidean cartesian context.

So your clarifications are completely correct, but they are a little unfocused. The people who can appreciate what you're saying are the people who don't need to hear it.
 
  • #89
stevendaryl said:
Fine. I feel that in a discussion, it is important to have the level of the discussion to be appropriate to the topic at hand, rather than in complete generality. The point of using displacements is that displacements give an intuitive idea of the tangent space, where a notion of "parallel" is always defined (in terms of one vector being a linear multiple of another).

The mathematical definition of the tangent space is a little involved. It's not something that people are familiar with just from learning vectors in the Euclidean cartesian context.

So your clarifications are completely correct, but they are a little unfocused. The people who can appreciate what you're saying are the people who don't need to hear it.

It is very dangerous to pretend that a topic is much easier than it actually is. I'm not saying that we should treat each topic in its full generality, but at least we should try not to make statements which are factually incorrect. If you want to talk about "parallellism" and tangent spaces in the easier context of \mathbb{R}^n, then this is perfectly fine. But you shouldn't say that it is the same in arbitrary manifolds since it is simply not true. I'm not saying we should actually define general tangent space, connections, etc. But at least, let's try to be precise and correct.
 
  • #90
TrickyDicky said:
Thanks for the relevant quotes.
I guess I fail to see how this procedure is more geometrical, I have always thought of geometry as something related to distances and angles, and for that you need a metric. Sure there are computations such as the one mentioned about volumes of parallelepipeds that seem to not need the metric, but I think this is a good example of the hidden metric case Burke precisely is trying to avoid.

Projective geometry (that of perspective and vanishing points, etc...) has no metric (akin to the Euclidean metric).
"Geometry" (in Felix Klein's view http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Erlangen_program and http://arxiv.org/abs/0807.3161 ) is (paraphrasing) a space and group of transformations of the space, seeking invariants under the group of transformations.

Klein said:
p2
But metrical properties are then to be regarded no longer as characteristics of the geometrical figures per se, but as their relations to a fundamental configuration, the imaginary circle at infinity common to all spheres.

p4
As a generalization of geometry arises then the following comprehensive problem:
Given a manifoldness and a group of transformations of the same; to investigate the configurations belonging to the manifoldness with regard to such properties as are not altered by the transformations of the group.
...
Given a manifoldness and a group of transformations of the same; to develop the theory of invariants
relating to that group.
which predates Special Relativity. I'm certain that Klein's view influenced Minkowski.
Hmm, maybe it's just me but if perpendicularity is meaningless without a metric(wich probably is), I don't know how parallelism is any more meaningful, I mean one seems to need something resembling Euclidean space locally (actually its affine generalization) to have the notion of parallelism between lines.

As you mention, parallelism is an affine concept.
The notion of two lines being parallel makes sense (in the same way) in Euclidean, Minkowskian, or Galilean [sorry to bring it up again] space[time]s. It is more primitive.
Next, add additional structure [e.g. a more restrictive group--say, a choice of defining what "rotations" are] to get perpendicularilty, in addition to the already existing notation of parallelism. As you know, "perpendicularity" in Euclidean space is generally different from the other space[time]s.

If you take away the parallelism structure (relaxing the group of transformations), then you allow a more general "geometry", like elliptic/spherical geometry. However, you still have even more primitive structures like "incidence" (whether a point is on a line).

With regard to the volume of parallelepipeds, I think the correct statement is that whether you choose the Euclidean, Minkowski, or Galilean metric, you get the same value for the volume [possibly, up to signs]. So, it really doesn't depend on the metric... but instead on something common to those metrics (something describing the affine structure). Does the "determinant" rely on the choice of metric among these three space[time]s... or just the parallelepiped's vectors themselves?
 
  • #91
micromass said:
You need a connection in order to make sense of this, as wbn mentioned.

Exactly, and I like to think of this affine connection that is needed in order to differentiate vector fields in differentiable manifolds as a structure that takes advantage of the common property of all manifolds, being locally like an affine Euclidean space.
So it is clear that some extra structure is needed, it just seems natural to me that this connection needed to parallel transport is the canonical Riemannian connection in the vast majority of classical physical problems, be it in configuration space (configuration manifold), Euclidean space, Lorentzian manifolds, etc.
My point was that I don't understand Burke's prejudice against metric tensors and what is it "not geometric" about them that might bother anyone. I agree with him that it should be more enphasized when the Euclidean metric is being implicitly used and when it is not.
 
Last edited:
  • #92
TrickyDicky said:
Exactly, and I like to think of this affine connection that is needed in order to differentiate vector fields in differentiable manifolds as a structure that takes advantage of the common property of all manifolds, being locally like an affine Euclidean space.
So it is clear that some extra structure is needed, it just seems natural to me that this connection needed to parallel transport is the canonical Riemannian connection in the vast majority of classical physical problems, be it in configuration space (configuration manifold), Euclidean space, Lorentzian manifolds, etc.
My point was that I don't understand Burke's prejudice against metric tensors and what is it "not geometric" about them that might bother anyone. I agree with him that it should be more enphasized when the Euclidean metric is being implicitly used and when it is not.
How is it goin Tricky Dicky. Just to clarify, a connection is not the ONLY way to differentiate vector fields on a smooth manifold. Take, for example, the lie derivative. Both offer different geometric notions of "parallelism". I think his issue is just that in coordinate - based computations, there is so much blurring of what quantities should naturally be taken as one - forms and what as vectors because people tend to use the metric tensor to go from one to the other readily.
 
  • #93
robphy said:
Projective geometry (that of perspective and vanishing points, etc...) has no metric (akin to the Euclidean metric).
Yes, that is a good example of not needing the concepts of angle and distance in geometry generalizations. A geometry only based in those concepts would be very poor. But my point was rather that there wasn't anything wrong with metrics if one wants to stress the geometrical side of something.

robphy said:
With regard to the volume of parallelepipeds, I think the correct statement is that whether you choose the Euclidean, Minkowski, or Galilean metric, you get the same value for the volume [possibly, up to signs]. So, it really doesn't depend on the metric... but instead on something common to those metrics (something describing the affine structure). Does the "determinant" rely on the choice of metric among these three space[time]s... or just the parallelepiped's vectors themselves?
Of course it doesn't. But I always think of the cross product when talking about the determinant, is there anything more Euclidean than that? :wink:
 
  • #94
micromass said:
It is very dangerous to pretend that a topic is much easier than it actually is.

I'm not sure that I agree. Progress in physics really was only possible because physicists oversimplified in a way that was good enough for the problems that they were interested in. I think it's important to have a feel for what the limitations are of a particular approach, and sometimes going forward means going backwards and redoing what you've already done, but in a more careful way.

Anyway, I was aiming my comments at the level of someone who is familiar with vectors in the context of Euclidean space, but doesn't realize the full implications of lacking a metric. I think going into the full complexities of differential geometry is the wrong level for the discussion.
 
  • #95
WannabeNewton said:
How is it goin Tricky Dicky. Just to clarify, a connection is not the ONLY way to differentiate vector fields on a smooth manifold. Take, for example, the lie derivative. Both offer different geometric notions of "parallelism".
Yes, the only difference is that the Lie derivative admits torsion. I was jst thinking that most classical physics situations don't need to include torsion. An exception is the non-mainstream Einstein-Cartan theory that relates torsion with QM spin, but QM spin is not a classical concept.
WannabeNewton said:
I think his issue is just that in coordinate - based computations, there is so much blurring of what quantities should naturally be taken as one - forms and what as vectors because people tend to use the metric tensor to go from one to the other readily.
Yeah, agreed. But again, sure, you don't need metrics to talk about differential forms and vectors, but I still don't know if I buy the notion that classical physics quantities must be taken naturally as one or the other independently of the geometry of the physical problem at hand.
 
  • #96
stevendaryl said:
I think going into the full complexities of differential geometry is the wrong level for the discussion.

This looks a bit condescending with the people in this forum. (Not with poor ignorant me but with many others very capable of handling that level).
 
  • #97
TrickyDicky said:
This looks a bit condescending with the people in this forum. (Not with poor ignorant me but with many others very capable of handling that level).

I don't mean to be condescending, it's just that in an informal setting, as opposed to writing a textbook, it seems to me that pitching at the right level is more important than being perfectly general. Yes, there's the danger that someone will take something more literally than it was intended, and could be led astray, but I think that people generally can recognize the difference between a textbook style formal definition and an intuitive argument, and should know that the latter is only meant to steer someone in the right direction, rather than to be the definitive last word on the subject.
 
  • #98
robphy said:
Here are some quotes from Burke's Applied Differential Geometry that support my statement above

The quotes are great, robphy -- thanks for going to the trouble of posting them. I found the one about forces of constraint to be particularly helpful.
 
  • #99
stevendaryl said:
I don't mean to be condescending, it's just that in an informal setting, as opposed to writing a textbook, it seems to me that pitching at the right level is more important than being perfectly general. Yes, there's the danger that someone will take something more literally than it was intended, and could be led astray, but I think that people generally can recognize the difference between a textbook style formal definition and an intuitive argument, and should know that the latter is only meant to steer someone in the right direction, rather than to be the definitive last word on the subject.

If you don't want to be completely literal and precise, then that's perfectly ok. But you should say that you're being imprecise. Nobody benefits from people getting misconceptions.
 
  • #100
William Burke said:
A further payoff for having a clear geometric picture of force comes in situations involving constraints. A slippery constraint is one having no frictional forces. One usually says that the constraint force is perpendicular to the constraint surface. Now if you are truly learning to think covariantly with respect to linear transformations, you will see that this is a nonsense statement. Perpendicularity is a meaningless concept in any configuration space that does not accidentally happen to have a metric. The correct geometric view of a constraint is sketched in Figure 18.4. As a 1-form, the constraint force is parallel to the constraint surface, and parallelism is a properly covariant notion. Again, the non-covariant language comes from excessive attention to the peculiar features of particle mechanics in Euclidean space, features which do not generalize.

I wanted to see if I could work out an example of this that was as simple as possible. I think my example makes sense, but maybe others here could tell me if this makes sense and help me smooth out the stuff I'm unsure of.

I actually made two examples. Example #1 is a billiard ball of unit mass in two dimensions, constrained by a diagonal wall to have y<x. The Lagrangian formalism just leads to the expected Newtonian expressions, p_x=\dot{x}, p_y=\dot{y}. The force of constraint is F_a=dp_a/dt. Let w^a be a vector parallel to the wall. Since we do happen to have a metric in this example,we can say that F_aw^a=0; most people would say that the force was perpendicular to the wall.

Example #2 is a human arm with a heavy mass gripped in the hand. The upper arm is raised at an angle \theta and the lower arm raised at an angle \phi (both measured relative to the vertical). The arm's weight is negligible compared to the unit mass of the gripped weight, and both the upper and lower arm have unit length. Because of the construction of the elbow joint, we have a constraint \theta \le \phi. The conjugate momenta (which are actually angular momenta) turn out to be p_\theta=\dot{\theta}+\cos(\phi-\theta)\dot{\phi} and a similar expression for p_\phi. The force of constraint is F_a=dp_a/dt. The surface of constraint can be represented by a vector w^a, which is on a diagonal line in the (\phi,\theta) plane. Since there is no metric, it doesn't make sense to say that F_a is perpendicular to w^a.

Geometrically, Burke has a nice representation of a 1-form as a pair of parallel lines, with one of the two lines marked with an arrowhead (see http://www.scribd.com/doc/37538938/Burke-DivGradCurl ). In this representation, the parallel lines representing the force of constraint are clearly parallel to the surface of constraint.

But I'm not clear on how to notate this idea that in both examples, the force 1-form is parallel to the surface. Do you represent the surface as, say, a 1-form created by taking the (infinite) gradient of a step function across the wall?

Apart from my notational confusion, does the rest of this seem right?
 
Last edited by a moderator:
Back
Top