Partitioning of transcendentals

  • Thread starter RobertCairone
  • Start date
In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of "width" as a way to partition real numbers into two groups - enfranchised and disenfranchised. Enfranchised numbers have a finite width and can be expressed using a finite number of mathematical symbols, while disenfranchised numbers have an infinite width and cannot be fully expressed using mathematical symbols. The significance of this concept is debated, with one person arguing that it is tied to our notational choices and another arguing that it may have connections to computability. However, it is noted that the number of enfranchised numbers is still finite, regardless of notation, and that this finite set includes all integers, rationals, algebraics, and some transcendentals.
  • #1
RobertCairone
Gold Member
7
0
Is this interesting?

I have a way to partition the transcendentals into two disjoint groups.

I begin by defining a property of the real numbers I call "width". Given a base b, say 10 for convenience, I write down all the numbers I can with a single digit. There are ten of them, ten integers of width 1. There are more numbers of width 2, the ninety from 10 to 99, plus the first nine negative integers, plus nine decimals, .1, .2, .3, etc. That's 118 of width 2. On width 3 we get a lot more. More integers, more decimals, and some numbers like 1/3 and 1/7. We have a finite number of understandable mathematical symbols, and we have a finite number of digits, so we have a finite number of elements of each width (we could allow for factorials and add five numbers to width 2, being 5!, 6!, etc. We wouldn't include 9[itex]^{5}[/itex] in width 2, as the exponent is a binary operator needing explicit specification. But it is width 3). The width of any number is defined as the minimum width that gives its value.

It's not always easy to know the minimum width. For example, [itex]\pi[/itex] = √6*Ʃi=1,∞1/i^2. For that typography, that's a width of 14. In other conventions or by using other expansions the width could be different. In any case, the value of [itex]\pi[/itex] is completely specified in a finite number of defined symbols.

There are two types of numbers - those with finite width and those without. I call the first set the "Enfranchised" numbers and the second set "Disenfranchised" since they have no clear representation. Note that the Enfranchised numbers contain all of the integers, all of the rationals, all of the algebraics, and many of the transcendentals.

The Disenfranchised therefore contain only transcendentals.

As there are no more than a countably infinite number of Enfranchised numbers, the Disenfranchised must be uncountable.

So if I were to ask you to pick a number at random, the probability that you would pick an Enfranchised number is exactly zero. And yet you have no way to pick anything but an Enfranchised number, so the probability is 1. That'd be my bet.
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I'm really not sure what you're trying to do here, or what the significance of "width" would possibly be. Why wouldn't the width of pi be equal to 1, since it's value is completely denoted by the symbol [itex]\pi[/itex]? Your definition is completely dependent on arbitrary notational choices.

You're almost touching on something vaguely related to computability, but you mess it up by introducing concepts that aren't really necessary.

So if I were to ask you to pick a number at random, the probability that you would pick an Enfranchised number is exactly zero.

The probability of picking one of any countable number of real numbers is zero, yes.

And yet you have no way to pick anything but an Enfranchised number, so the probability is 1. That'd be my bet.

You're negating your own premise here. Either we're picking a real number at random, or we're picking exclusively from the "enfranchised numbers". You can't have both.
 
  • #3
I might be very wrong here, but this just seems to be very superficial. Basing mathematical definitions on our way of expressing them seems kind of silly. You give a base 10 example, but if these definitions were going to make any sense, it should work for any base, right?

And what about this:
[itex]\lim_{n \to \infty}(1+1/n)^{1/n}[/itex]. What is the width of this? What if instead of that, I write [itex]\lim_{n}(1+1/n)^{1/n}[/itex]? The point is that you have tied something that is a very deep property about numbers and have made it about as superficial as possible, and so it doesn't seem like you could be able to do a lot with it.

Every real number is the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. Now, if you can write out the nth term, then you have a finite width number. If not, then I guess you have an infinite width number. But, again, we are trying to make a serious mathematical definition based on whether or not, in our notation, we can make a formula for something.

I *think* this is one of the biggest problems early mathematicians had. They wanted to define a continuous function to be something like "a function which has a one line formula" (ie no piecewise stuff.) (Note, I have not actually researched this myself, I have just read about it in some popular math books.) But this wasn't rigorous enough, and that lead to the epsilon-delta stuff we do now.
 
  • #4
Number Nine said:
I'm really not sure what you're trying to do here, or what the significance of "width" would possibly be. Why wouldn't the width of pi be equal to 1, since it's value is completely denoted by the symbol [itex]\pi[/itex]? Your definition is completely dependent on arbitrary notational choices.

True to an extent, just as the designation of a particular base is arbitrary. Numbers in binary necessarily take more characters to write than numbers in decimal. But [itex]\pi[/itex] itself isn't a number, it is a symbol for a number. Unlike the digits 0 thru 9, the symbol [itex]\pi[/itex] tells nothing about it's value unless it is defined in terms of other numbers and/or operators. But given a clear definition for the value of this special number, I've no problem with creating a special symbol for it and assigning it to width 1. Just like we can define a one character symbol for the factorial operator. What doesn't make sense is to say "Here is a number I call '[itex]\vartheta[/itex]'" and not be able to describe what its value is. That [itex]\vartheta[/itex] is not a number of width 1.

The point is that there are still only finitely many numbers of width 1, Exactly how many numbers will fall into each width is dependent on notation and doesn't matter much. What matters is that it's a finite set.

Number Nine said:
You're almost touching on something vaguely related to computability, but you mess it up by introducing concepts that aren't really necessary. The probability of picking one of any countable number of real numbers is zero, yes.

Sorry, I was being a bit tongue in cheek. I didn't mean pick any particular number, I meant pick any number of that class. The Enfranchised numbers are all well defined and readily expressible, but there are only countably many of them. Even though they make up every number you know, and every number you can know, among the reals there are almost none of them. I find that ironic and amusing.

Number Nine said:
You're negating your own premise here. Either we're picking a real number at random, or we're picking exclusively from the "enfranchised numbers". You can't have both.

If you pick a disenfranchised number, as you probably would if you could, you cannot tell me what it is with any finite combination of numbers and operators. If I ask you what number you picked, you can't say and I can't know what it is. This is a curious property for what are almost all the numbers.
 
  • #5
But [itex]\pi[/itex] itself isn't a number, it is a symbol for a number.

So is 5 (and 3, and 100). So what?

The point is that there are still only finitely many numbers of width 1, Exactly how many numbers will fall into each width is dependent on notation and doesn't matter much. What matters is that it's a finite set.

It only a finite set because of our notational conventions.

If you pick a disenfranchised number, as you probably would if you could, you cannot tell me what it is with any finite combination of numbers and operators.

True, but that's not what you said, and it has nothing to do with the probability of drawing a "disenfranchised number".
 
  • #6
I think you've touched upon a deeper problem here than you may realize.
RobertCairone said:
If you pick a disenfranchised number, as you probably would if you could, you cannot tell me what it is with any finite combination of numbers and operators. If I ask you what number you picked, you can't say and I can't know what it is. This is a curious property for what are almost all the numbers.

How can I actually take up your offer to "pick" a number for myself? This whole offer seems like a conjuror offering me a pack of cards and saying, "Pick any card, don't show me what it is, and you mustn't look at it yourself." In what sense would I then have "picked" the card I hold in my hand, rather than any other one you still have in the pack? What difference is there between mine and all of yours?

If there's no way of detecting any difference between my number and all the (equally disenfrachised) numbers I didn't pick, we might as well consider them all to be equal -- just like the set of unicorns is equal to the set of mermaids: they are both the same empty set.

PS: What system of symbols we use to describe numbers isn't important, as long as we decide on one. Thereafter some numbers become "enfranchised" or "disenfranchised" within this system.
 
  • #7
Robert1986 said:
Every real number is the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. Now, if you can write out the nth term, then you have a finite width number. If not, then I guess you have an infinite width number. But, again, we are trying to make a serious mathematical definition based on whether or not, in our notation, we can make a formula for something.

I'm comfortable saying every Enfranchised number is the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. I'm not so sure about all the the Disenfranchised.

Robert1986 said:
I *think* this is one of the biggest problems early mathematicians had. They wanted to define a continuous function to be something like "a function which has a one line formula" (ie no piecewise stuff.) (Note, I have not actually researched this myself, I have just read about it in some popular math books.) But this wasn't rigorous enough, and that lead to the epsilon-delta stuff we do now.

Of course, the deltas and epsilons used must themselves be enfranchised, and I think they even have to be rational, since they are used in the very definition of irrational numbers.
 
  • #8
RobertCairone said:
Of course, the deltas and epsilons used must themselves be enfranchised, and I think they even have to be rational, since they are used in the very definition of irrational numbers.

You don't need the rational numbers to define the reals. Try this:

Let R be a field with a total order ≥ such that, for all real numbers x, y and z:
  • if x ≥ y then x + z ≥ y + z;
  • if x ≥ 0 and y ≥ 0 then xy ≥ 0;
and every non-empty subset S of R that has an upper bound in R also has a least upper bound in R.

Any such set R is isomorphis to the set of reals.
 
  • #9
Michael Redei said:
If there's no way of detecting any difference between my number and all the (equally disenfrachised) numbers I didn't pick, we might as well consider them all to be equal -- just like the set of unicorns is equal to the set of mermaids: they are both the same empty set.

But I don't think the disenfranchised is an empty set. Rather, compared to the disenfranchised, everything else is an empty set. Consider the function f(x) where f(x) = 0 if x is Enfranchised and f(x) = 1 if x is Disenfranchised. Then ∫[itex]^{0}_{1}[/itex]f(x) = 1, since you can remove up to a countably infinite number of points without affecting the integral.

Michael Redei said:
PS: What system of symbols we use to describe numbers isn't important, as long as we decide on one. Thereafter some numbers become "enfranchised" or "disenfranchised" within this system.

I agree the systems of symbols isn't important. But I rather suspect that enfranchised will map to enfranchised and the disenfranchised will remain disenfranchised. Simply changing the base of the number system won't do it, so it would have to be some fundamental changes to the arithmetic operators. I don't know what that might be.

I've been struggling with the idea that the indistinguishability of the disenfranchised means they could all be treated as equals. I don't buy that. Rather, I think they allow us to consider them as continuous.
 
  • #10
Michael Redei said:
" In what sense would I then have "picked" the card I hold in my hand, rather than any other one you still have in the pack? What difference is there between mine and all of yours?
If nothing else, when the conjurer draws another card from the deck and asks "Is this your card?", you can confidently answer "no".

An interesting point to note is that if you define the complex numbers as the algebraic closure of the real numbers, the two square roots of -1 are indistinguishable in the same sense you describe.
 
  • #11
I didn't say the set of disenfranchised numbers was empty. What I did say was that each disenfranchised number resembles the empty set in having no property that distinguishes it from other disnfranchised numbers.

Let's just assume we decide on some system for describing real numbers, and some real numbers now are disenfranchised. Can one say anything worthwhile about these numbers, as a whole, even if not about anyone specifically? The set of all disnfranchised numbers is uncountable, sure, but that's nothing new -- there are other uncountable subsets of the reals. What makes the disenfranchised numbers interesting after we've defined them? What use are they, what insights do they offer?
 
  • #12
Hi Robert,

Your notion of "width" is of course not well defined.

Your idea of distinguishing between numbers with finite and infinite "width" is not a new one. For example, the notion of a definable real number, does perhaps capture your idea, and more.
RobertCairone said:
I'm comfortable saying every Enfranchised number is the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. I'm not so sure about all the the Disenfranchised.
It is an elementary fact that every real number is a limit of a sequence of rationals.
 
  • #13
Hurkyl said:
If nothing else, when the conjurer draws another card from the deck and asks "Is this your card?", you can confidently answer "no".

If I can pick a card, it automatically becomes "enfranchised" since it now has gained a defining property: it's the one in my hand. And if I can't pick even a first card, the conjurer can't pick a second one.
 
  • #14
RobertCairone said:
I'm comfortable saying every Enfranchised number is the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. I'm not so sure about all the the Disenfranchised.

It is absolutely true. Every irrational number can be approximated by a rational number to any degree of accuracy. Surely you can see how this means every irrational number is a limit of a sequence of rationals. For example, if r is a number, for each N pick some rational number that is in the interval (r-(1/N),(r+(1/N)) but is not in (r-(1/(N-1),r-1/N) or (r+1/N,r+1/(N-1))


Of course, the deltas and epsilons used must themselves be enfranchised, and I think they even have to be rational, since they are used in the very definition of irrational numbers.
You completely missed my point. My example was to show you that non-rigorous definitions don't work in math.
 

1. What is partitioning of transcendentals?

Partitioning of transcendentals is a mathematical technique used to divide a transcendental function into simpler functions, making it easier to solve or analyze. This process involves breaking down the function into smaller parts, often by considering specific values or limits of the function.

2. Why is partitioning of transcendentals useful?

Partitioning of transcendentals is useful because it allows us to solve complex equations involving transcendental functions that may not have an exact solution. By breaking down the function into simpler parts, we can use various mathematical techniques to approximate the solution or analyze the behavior of the function.

3. Can any transcendental function be partitioned?

Yes, any transcendental function can be partitioned. However, the complexity and effectiveness of the partitioning may vary depending on the specific function. Some functions may be easier to partition than others, and the resulting simpler functions may not always accurately represent the original function.

4. How is partitioning of transcendentals different from other mathematical techniques?

Partitioning of transcendentals is different from other mathematical techniques, such as differentiation or integration, because it specifically focuses on breaking down transcendental functions. While other techniques may also be used to solve or analyze these functions, partitioning offers a unique approach that can be particularly helpful for complex equations.

5. Are there any limitations to partitioning of transcendentals?

Yes, there are some limitations to partitioning of transcendentals. In some cases, the resulting simpler functions may not accurately represent the original function, leading to potential errors in the solution or analysis. Additionally, partitioning may not always be possible for highly complex functions or for certain types of transcendental functions.

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
4
Views
229
Replies
8
Views
1K
Replies
7
Views
583
Replies
3
Views
278
  • General Math
Replies
11
Views
1K
Replies
9
Views
1K
  • General Math
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
4
Views
429
Replies
2
Views
853
Back
Top