JeffJo said:
The reader is, presumably, asked to assess the correctness of the statistician's solution in the OP, in the same way prisoner C does in Wikipedias's rendition of the same problem.
Prisoner C doesn't present all that analysis. He presumably could, but he doesn't have to. He knows that he could have been pointed out, but wasn't.
The Wikipedia version ... inserts that role into the story.
and the version as stated in the thread does not, wherefore the problems are different.
And regardless, it only affects the superficial point you brought up: that nobody in the OP, except the statistician, cares if the statistician was right. Yet you said the reader is supposed to care. See "personification."
That's not what I said.
You said the reader is supposed to make the determination of whether the statistician is correct.
That's close enough to something I said.
You even claimed it was a different problem if the the question was "is he right?" or "is he wrong?"
No, I didn't.
So such a person does exist, just not as a character in the story.
No such person exists as a subject in the problem as stated in this thread, whereas in the problem as stated in Wikipedia, there is such a subject: Prisoner C.
In the problem as stated in this thread, the only legitimate candidate for a subject that corresponds to prisoner C in the Wikipedia version, is the non-inquiring not pointed out prisoner, and he does not, in terms of his knowledge, correspond to prisoner C, because unlike prisoner C, he has not been told by the inquirer of the pointing out.
You can't legitimately drag in the reader, who is not a subject in the problems, to take the place of a subject in the problem. Our knowing that a fact is known to two subjects in the second problem doesn't make the second problem equivalent to the first problem, in which we know there to be only one subject who knows that fact.
But this is becoming ridiculous.
It's ridiculous to take someone to task merely for pointing out a difference as a difference after you incorrectly pronounced two different problems to be the same.
Even after repeated precise identification of the difference and of its consequences, you persist in saying that two problems that are different are the same. You misstate and mischaracterize what your opposition says. You present as equivalent a problem that in most aspects, but not all, is equivalent, and then dismiss the inequivalency as superficial, as if it were at the level of superficiality of mere names, e.g. calling the inquirer in the first version the statistician, and calling the inquirer in the second version prisoner A.
You drag in a viewpoint (ours) that's not part of the problem, and pretend that the existence of that external viewpoint is a valid counterpart for a point of view that is internal to the problem. You try to excuse that by pointing out that in the second problem, prisoner C is in the same knowledge position, and that in the first problem, the statistician is in the same knowledge position. That's obviously not parallel.
I have defined the conditions that make the problems equivalent,
You are attempting to do that by decree. The problems already have their own pre-stated conditions. You can't legitimately arrogate to yourself the fiat to rule out a stated condition as unimportant in order to make yourself right and someone else wrong. The problems as originally stated are not the same.
and you continue to ignore that definition in order to emphasize the window dressing devised to make the problem into a story problem.
What I originally said was that the problem as stated in this thread was not equivalent to the Monty Hall problem, because the statistician doesn't have an option to swap verdicts, as the contestant has an option to switch doors.
You said that the 2/3 chance of the other non-inquiring not pointed out prisoner corresponded to the 2/3 chance of the not-opened door. I agreed, but only because in the second version of the 3 prisoners problem, the non-inquiring not pointed out prisoner -- prisoner C -- is told by the inquirer about the pointing out of the other non-inquiring prisoner. I said that the first version of the 3 prisoners problem was not the same as the Monty Hall problem, because unlike in the second problem, in which prisoner C being told mapped to the contestant being given an option to switch doors, there.was not only no such option; there was also no such informing to take its place.
You couldn't resort to the knowledge of prisoner A's first version counterpart, the statistician, because in that problem, the inquirer didn't tell the other non-inquiring not-pointed out prisoner the news. You then wound up resorting to the reader as the counterpart to prisoner C, because he too has the knowledge that prisoner A has. The problem with that, is that just like the statistician, we didn't tell the other non-inquiring not pointed out prisoner either.
The problems represent the different real-world manifestations of the same underlying probability space. The minute differences in the presentation affects only how we might phrase an answer to address the explicit question (when there is one), or the question we infer (as is the case in the OP). The consequences of the outcomes in the real-world manifestations are irrelevant to how we address the problem.
What this means is that the same problem is described by a different story in each version.
It doesn't mean that, and even if it did, that wouldn't change the fact that that the two problems are different. Even if it be granted that from an external objective point of view, the probability spaces are the same, the problem in each case is to evaluate the statements of the subjects, and the result for the one subject in the first version does not match up with the results for the two subjects in the second version, there being a second subject in the second version, only because there is an added condition in the second version, that along with the requirement to evaluate the second subject's appraisal of the post-pointing out chances of the two subjects, makes the two problems different.
+++++
My point at the beginning, before sysprog's absurd digression,
No other person has ownership of your digression from your point. Putting that label on my disagreement with your assessment, doesn't make me wrong, any more than any of your other failed attempts does.
was that what I think you call a "more general, logical argument" is an incorrect, non-mathematical approach that just happens to get the right answer.
I think PeroK did as I did. He looked around for a prima facie reason to suppose that the statistician was right to think his chances had improved, and correctly seeing none, correctly concluded that the statistician still had the same chances as before.
In the following, I'm ignoring sysprog's kind of reasoning
You can ignore it, but you haven't refuted it.
(where "two have guilty verdicts and one (at random) has a not-guilty verdict" and "three are convicted but on (at random) has a pardon", and asking an additional question, make it a different problem).
That's yet another misstatement of what I said. You deliberately left out the distinction that in this thread's version of the 3 prisoners problem, the non-inquiring not pointed out prisoner is not told of the news about the pointing out of the other non-inquiring prisoner as guilty, while in the other version, prisoner A tells prisoner C the news. You say that's irrelevant, and I say it's pivotal. Pretending I said that something else was alone enough to make the two problems different, is not even a good faith effort at honest exposition.
Since the Wikipedia version is also the same problem,
It isn't the same problem, and saying "also" should means with something else. Presumably that should mean that you have just shown the 3 prisoners problem as stated in this thread to be equivalent to the Monty Hall problem, but you haven't, so I'll disregarding the bolded "also", and take this re-invocation of the Wikipedia version to mean that's the problem you'd like to discuss.
I'll use it to compare these solutions:
- Prisoner A now knows that there are only two prisoners who could receive the pardon. Since each was equally likely to receive it in the first place, each now has a 1/2 probability.
- Prisoner A didn't receive any information that could make a change, so his initial probability of 1/3 is unaffected.
- 1. is incorrect, and 2. is correct.
Both of these make the same mistake, of not recognizing that "new information" affects not just one probability but the set as a whole.
1. "makes a mistake": the second sentence of 1. is a non sequitur. 2. does not evince any mistake.
In the first it is one mistake - using an insufficient, but otherwise correct event partition {A pardon, B pardon, C pardon} with probabilities {1/3,1/3,1/3}. It then correctly set the probability of "B pardon" to zero and correctly normalizes what remains, {1/3,1/3,0} to {1/2,1/2,0}.
If you "correctly normalize" from an "insufficient but otherwise correct" partition, because if it is insufficient, it is ipso facto incorrectly defined, wherefore a normalization predicated thereupon is of no value. There was no need in 2. to do a partitioning and normalization, because there was no prima facie indication that any of the new information could affect the chances for A.
The sufficient partition is {A pardon point to B, A pardon point to C, B pardon point to C, C pardon point to B} with probabilities {1/6,1/6,1/3,1/3}. The same, correct procedure now removes the two events with "point to C", leaving {1/6,0,1/3,0} which normalizes to {1/3,0,2/3,0}.
That is a not-incorrect showing of what is wrong with 1. It has no necessary bearing on 2.
The second not only makes the incorrect claim of no new information,
2. does not make the claim of no new information. In your statement of 2. you refer to "information that could make a change"; not to "new information"
per se.
it also claims that it cannot affect his probability.
It correctly states that A does not receive "any new information that could make a change" (for A).
According to your statement of it, 2. says:
2. Prisoner A didn't receive any information that could make a change, so his initial probability of 1/3 is unaffected.
The new information would make a difference for A if and only if A could swap positions with C. Response 2. correctly observes that the new information cannot change anything for A, and correctly infers that his initial probability of 1/3 is unaffected.
The reason many people don't understand problems like this ... is because the information does affect prisoner A's chances. But in a way that returns it to the value it had before.
A single informational event is not a process that can change something and then change it back. Your subsequent analysis is a process, only inside of which A's chance changes and changes back. The process from input to output produces no external change for A's chance. The condition of A's chance before, during, and after the informational event remain exactly the same. The analysis you present is sufficient for recognizing that, but not necessary for recognizing it. It can be recognized without any such analysis.
If you add the condition that A tells C what the guard did, and ask also about C's updated chances and his new estimation thereof, as the Wikipedia version of the problem, which version you are at this juncture purporting to be referencing does, then and only then is some further analysis necessary, because the added condition that C is told the news, has changed the impact of the event, not on the chances themselves, but on C's ability to recognize them. He doesn't need to do an exhaustive anylysis, but he does need to recognize that he could have been pointed out but wasn't. Whether his estimation of his new chance as having improved to 2/3 while the chance of A remains the same 1/3 it was to begin with is correct, is part of what the Wikipedia version asks, that the problem as stated in this thread does not ask. Along with C being told the news, that part makes the two problems different.
(as opposed to confusing the problem with the story, as sysprog does)
I didn't confuse anything.
+++++
But I usually take your generalization one step further. All of these problems, and one more where many "experts" accept the statistician's logic, are variations of what I call the Generalized Bertrand's Box Problem. I'll point out that an odd transformation,
that is perfectly valid but I'm fairly certain sysprog won't accept because it essentially uses different names for the cases,
is necessary to apply it to Monty Hall and Three Prisoners.[/quote]You have no good reason to toss in this misleading jibe. I already expressly acknowledged the Wikipedia version of the 3 prisoners problem to be equivalent to the Monty Hall problem, given that after A has told C the news, C's new information, and the contestant's option to switch doors, make C mappable to the other unopened door.