Proving the Inequality 1 > 0 in Real Numbers

  • Thread starter Thread starter issacnewton
  • Start date Start date
issacnewton
Messages
1,035
Reaction score
37
Hi

I am trying to prove that 1 > 0. I am going to assume a contradiction .

Assume 1 \leqslant 0

First consider 1=0, Let a \in \mathbb{R} be arbitrary. So

a=1.a = 0.a = 0 using field axioms. Actually 0.a=0 is not field axiom , but I have
proved it separately .

that means \forall \;\; a\in \mathbb{R} \Rightarrow a=0

since all numbers are equal to 0 , no inverse exists in the set R. So R is not a field. Hence
the contradiction. So

1 \neq 0

that means we have to consider the second option

1 < 0

Consider a > 0 \backepsilon a \in R

Now I have already proved another theorem.

If q,b,c are in R and q < b , c < 0 then qc > bc

letting c =1 and q = 0 , b= a we can say that

(0)(1) > (a)(1) which means 0 > a or a < 0 but this is contradiction since
we assumed that a> 0 . So our assumption that 1 < 0 , is wrong.

Hence 1 > 0

is my proof right ?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Hi IssacNewton! :smile:

It might help if you list the axioms you use. Some of the comments I make will be about how I've seen the field axioms, but you might have different axioms.

IssacNewton said:
Hi

I am trying to prove that 1 > 0. I am going to assume a contradiction .

Assume 1 \leqslant 0

First consider 1=0, Let a \in \mathbb{R} be arbitrary. So

a=1.a = 0.a = 0 using field axioms. Actually 0.a=0 is not field axiom , but I have
proved it separately .

that means \forall \;\; a\in \mathbb{R} \Rightarrow a=0

since all numbers are equal to 0 , no inverse exists in the set R. So R is not a field. Hence
the contradiction.

This is not a contradiction. The field axioms say that every nonzero element in R must have an inverse. But taking R={0} satisfies this: every nonzero element has an inverse, because there are no nonzero elements!

In fact, most field axioms take 1\neq 0 as an axiom. So there's nothing to prove here. However, your axioms might do things differently...

that means we have to consider the second option

1 &lt; 0

Consider a &gt; 0 \backepsilon a \in R

Who says such an a exists?

Now I have already proved another theorem.

If q,b,c are in R and q < b , c < 0 then qc > bc

letting c =1 and q = 0 , b= a we can say that

(0)(1) > (a)(1) which means 0 > a or a < 0 but this is contradiction since
we assumed that a> 0 . So our assumption that 1 < 0 , is wrong.

Hence 1 > 0

is my proof right ?

The rest of the proof looks right.
 
Hi Micro

Your comments about the first part are right. Only non zero elements of R have inverse.
I will try to modify that part. The axioms I am using doesn't say that 1 \neq 0
as part of the any axiom. So I will need to come up with some contradiction.

For the second part, I am using some a \in \mathbb{R} which is greater than 0. Is that wrong ?
 
IssacNewton said:
Hi Micro

Your comments about the first part are right. Only non zero elements of R have inverse.
I will try to modify that part. The axioms I am using doesn't say that 1 \neq 0
as part of the any axiom. So I will need to come up with some contradiction.

Your axioms somehow need to rule out the possibility that R={0}. So try to see why this can't be possible.

For the second part, I am using some a \in \mathbb{R} which is greater than 0. Is that wrong ?

That isn't wrong, and I'm being extremely pedantic here. But who says that there exists an a which is greater than 0? That is, can't it happen that all elements in \mathbb{R} are <0?? (it can't, but why not?)
 
Here's another attempt for the first part

Let a,b \in \mathbb{R} and a &lt; b

then 1.a &lt; 1.b since 1 is multiplicative identity

0.a &lt; 0.b since 1=0

0 &lt; 0 a.0 = 0 (I proved this elsewhere)

this is a contradiction. Hence

1 \neq 0

does it look right now ?
 
IssacNewton said:
Here's another attempt for the first part

Let a,b \in \mathbb{R} and a &lt; b

Hmm, you're going to find me annoying. But how do you know there exists numbers in \mathbb{R} such that a<b?

May I know what field axioms you're starting from?
 
micromass said:
That isn't wrong, and I'm being extremely pedantic here. But who says that there exists an a which is greater than 0? That is, can't it happen that all elements in \mathbb{R} are <0?? (it can't, but why not?)

All elements of \mathbb{R} can't be < 0 since we need an identity element for the operation of addition. One of the axioms says that there exists a zero element(
identity element) for the operation of addition.
 
IssacNewton said:
All elements of \mathbb{R} can't be < 0 since we need an identity element for the operation of addition. One of the axioms says that there exists a zero element(
identity element) for the operation of addition.

OK, but a=0 won't be good in your proof. You'll need to find an element >0...
 
here are the axioms I am using
1) for all a,b \in \mathbb{R} we have a+b , a.b \in \mathbb{R}

2)\forall a,b \in \mathbb{R} , a+b=b+a \;\; a.b=b.a

3)\forall a,b,c \in \mathbb{R} ,\; (a+b)+c=a+(b+c) \;\; (a.b).c=a.(b.c)

4)there exists a zero element in \mathbb{R} , denoted by 0, such that
a+0=a \;\; \forall a \in \mathbb{R}

5)\forall a \in \mathbb{R} there exists an element -a in
\mathbb{R} , such that a+(-a)=0

6) there exists an element in \mathbb{R} , which we denote by 1, such that
a.1=a \;\; \forall a\in \mathbb{R}

7)\forall a \in \mathbb{R} with a\neq 0 there exists an element
in \mathbb{R} denoted by \frac{1}{a} or a^{-1}
such that

a.a^{-1}=1

8)\forall a,b,c \in \mathbb{R} we have

a.(b+c)=(a.b)+(a.c)
 
  • #10
IssacNewton said:
here are the axioms I am using
Okay. Then your first challenge is to prove the following statement is not true:
\forall a,b \in \mathbb{R}: a = b​
(hint: this challenge is actually impossible to complete)

(also, those axioms don't say anything about > anyways, so you couldn't possibly use them to prove anything about orderings)
 
  • #11
I'm afraid that this list of axioms is incomplete then, since R={0} satisfies all these axioms. There should at least by a remark that says that 1 is distinct from 0, or even something that says that R has more than one element.

If you check wiki's entry for a field you'll see one of the following axioms:

Additive and multiplicative identity
There exists an element of F, called the additive identity element and denoted by 0, such that for all a in F, a + 0 = a. Likewise, there is an element, called the multiplicative identity element and denoted by 1, such that for all a in F, a · 1 = a. To exclude the trivial ring, the additive identity and the multiplicative identity are required to be distinct.

This last sentence is essential.
 
  • #12
Sorry to interrupt, but strictly speaking you also need the order axioms:

1) Trichotomy property: for all a, b in R, only one of the following holds: a < b, b < a, or a = b.

2) Transitive property: for all a, b, c in R, if a < b and b < c, then a < c.

3) Additive property: for all a, b, c in R, if a < b, then a + c < b + c.

4) Multiplicative property: for all a, b, c in R, if a < b and 0 < c then ac < bc; if a < b and c < 0 then bc < ac.

EDIT: As Hurkyl and micromass have pointed out, the additive and multiplicative identities must be distinct in any field; 0 ≠ 1.
 
  • #13
Hi Hurkyl

I think you are also saying that \mathbb{R}\neq \{0\} . My starting point that 1=0 lead me to conclude that \mathbb{R}= \{0\} . Now you guys are saying that this can't be true. I don't see which of the axioms are violated. Or do I have
to think about the completeness axiom ?

Also some comments about the latex thing. The latex output here doesn't look so nice. Is
there some maintenance going on ?
 
  • #14
Unit, oh yeah,

I forgot about the order axioms. They are there.
 
  • #15
I think the axiom no 7 listed by implicitly says that 1\neq 0

Since we have 1.1^{-1}=1 that means , inverse of 1 exists and so
it must be true that 1\neq 0 . am I right ?
 
  • #16
How do you know 1.1 is in R?

The only numbers you know are in R are 1, 0, and the additive inverse of 1. Try cases, noting that 1 times 1 is 1.
 
  • #17
IssacNewton said:
Hi Hurkyl

I think you are also saying that \mathbb{R}\neq \{0\} . My starting point that 1=0 lead me to conclude that \mathbb{R}= \{0\} . Now you guys are saying that this can't be true. I don't see which of the axioms are violated.

None of the axioms are violated, that's the point. There's an axiom missing that says that 1\neq 0.
 
  • #18
Unit said:
How do you know 1.1 is in R?

The only numbers you know are in R are 1, 0, and the additive inverse of 1. Try cases, noting that 1 times 1 is 1.

closure property. Since 1 \in \mathbb{R}

1.1 \in \mathbb{R}
 
  • #19
IssacNewton said:
I think the axiom no 7 listed by implicitly says that 1\neq 0
It doesn't. However, you proved in post #1 that if 1=0, the field is the trivial field {0}.

Most authors include the axiom 1≠0. Some don't. I would choose not to include it, and instead do what you did: Prove that the only field that doesn't satisfy this condition is trivial.
 
  • #20
micromass said:
None of the axioms are violated, that's the point. There's an axiom missing that says that 1\neq 0.

Micromass, as I pointed out , doesn't that follow implicitly from axiom 7. go 2-3 posts back.

thanks
 
  • #21
IssacNewton said:
closure property. Since 1 \in \mathbb{R}

1.1 \in \mathbb{R}

My mistake. You should use 1\cdot 1 (that is, \cdot) to indicate multiplication. I mistook it 1.1 for 11/10.
 
  • #22
IssacNewton said:
Micromass, as I pointed out , doesn't that follow implicitly from axiom 7. go 2-3 posts back.

thanks

No, it doesn't follow from any of your axioms. Setting R={0} will satisfy all your axioms, so you explicitly need to eliminate the possibility that R is the trivial ring.
 
  • #23
Micromass, so if I include 1\neq 0 as one of the axioms, that takes care
of the first part of my proof. Which means that the statement 1=0
must be wrong.

I remember reading axioms from other books and people do say explicitly that 1 is not 0.
So the book I am using has problems. Maybe I should write the author, Witold Kosmala
 
  • #24
IssacNewton said:
Micromass, so if I include 1\neq 0 as one of the axioms, that takes care
of the first part of my proof. Which means that the statement 1=0
must be wrong.

I remember reading axioms from other books and people do say explicitly that 1 is not 0.
So the book I am using has problems. Maybe I should write the author, Witold Kosmala

Hmm, I don't seem to find the book, but I guess it's a mistake. Writing him sounds like a nice thing to do!
 
  • #26
IssacNewton said:
I think the axiom no 7 listed by implicitly says that 1\neq 0
First off, axiom 7 says every non-zero element has an inverse. If every element is zero, the axiom tells us nothing.

Secondly, in the zero ring, 0 does have an inverse: 0^{-1} = 0.

(edit: didn't notice the second page)
 
  • #27
Ok sorry for the late reply. I was traveling. We have already established that 1\neq 0
Now assume the second option that 1 &lt; 0

\Rightarrow -1 &gt; 0

Now I have proved the following theorem

Theorem: If a \in \mathbb{R} such that a \neq 0 then
a^2 &gt; 0.

I am going to use this theorem here. Since -1 &gt; 0 it follows that
(-1)^2 &gt; 0 hence 1 &gt; 0 which is a contradiction. Hence
we reject 1 &lt; 0 hence 1&gt; 0

is it right ?
 
  • #28
IssacNewton said:
Ok sorry for the late reply. I was traveling. We have already established that 1\neq 0
Now assume the second option that 1 &lt; 0

\Rightarrow -1 &gt; 0

Now I have proved the following theorem

Theorem: If a \in \mathbb{R} such that a \neq 0 then
a^2 &gt; 0.

I am going to use this theorem here. Since -1 &gt; 0 it follows that
(-1)^2 &gt; 0 hence 1 &gt; 0 which is a contradiction. Hence
we reject 1 &lt; 0 hence 1&gt; 0

is it right ?

Sounds good! Maybe you should show that (-1)^2=1...
 
  • #29
micromass said:
Maybe you should show that (-1)^2=1...

My mistake; I misread your post.

OP: Well done. :smile:
 
Back
Top