Proving Rational Difference Exists in Finite Measure Subset [0,1]

AxiomOfChoice
Messages
531
Reaction score
1
This is a practice final exam problem that has been giving me fits: Let E be a Lebesgue measurable subset of the interval [0,1] that has finite measure. Show that there exist two points x,y \in E such that x-y is rational.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
AxiomOfChoice said:
This is a practice final exam problem that has been giving me fits: Let E be a Lebesgue measurable subset of the interval [0,1] that has finite measure. Show that there exist two points x,y \in E such that x-y is rational.

Moved to HH. Could you please post your work so far? Thanks.
 
Well, I haven't done much, as I'm rather stumped here. My professor gave me the following hint: "countable unions." He also mentioned that examining the non-measurable set constructed with the axiom of choice might help. But this sort of has me even more baffled.
 
Why don't you start by summarizing for us the construction of the non-measurable set you're referring to? If it's the usual construction in most textbooks, it should start by defining an equivalence relation on the unit interval, such that two points x and y are equivalent if and only if x - y is rational. That seems like a promising start.
 
jbunniii said:
Why don't you start by summarizing for us the construction of the non-measurable set you're referring to? If it's the usual construction in most textbooks, it should start by defining an equivalence relation on the unit interval, such that two points x and y are equivalent if and only if x - y is rational. That seems like a promising start.

That is exactly it. We consider an equivalence relation on [0,1] defined as follows: x\sim y if x - y \in \mathbb Q. We then employ the Axiom of Choice and choose one member x_\alpha from each equivalence class E_\alpha, and define the set N = \{x_\alpha \}. The uncountability of N follows from the fact that N must satisfy 1 \leq \sum_{k=1}^\infty m(N) \leq 3 (where m denotes Lebesgue measure).
 
Last edited:
OK, now let's consider your set E. Suppose the assertion were not true. Then there do not exist two distinct points x,y \in E such that x - y \in \mathbb{Q}.

Now consider the implication in terms of the equivalence classes E_\alpha. What is the maximum number of elements of E that can be contained in each class E_\alpha?
 
P.S. I am assuming that in the problem statement, "finite measure" should really be "finite NON-ZERO measure." Otherwise the statement is false, as the example E = \{0, 1/\sqrt{2}\} demonstrates.
 
jbunniii said:
P.S. I am assuming that in the problem statement, "finite measure" should really be "finite NON-ZERO measure." Otherwise the statement is false, as the example E = \{0, 1/\sqrt{2}\} demonstrates.

You're right. Actually, instead of finite, I should have said "positive" (which I'm assuming means 0 < mE < \infty).
 
jbunniii said:
OK, now let's consider your set E. Suppose the assertion were not true. Then there do not exist two distinct points x,y \in E such that x - y \in \mathbb{Q}.

Now consider the implication in terms of the equivalence classes E_\alpha. What is the maximum number of elements of E that can be contained in each class E_\alpha?

(1) You're very kind to help me out with this. Thanks. I'd buy you a beer if I could. (Or a glass of wine; whichever floats your boat.)

(2) Ah, I think I see...so each equivalence class consists of a single point: Given x,y\in E, x \sim y iff x = y. I guess this means there must be uncountably many equivalence classes, then, since mE > 0 implies it's necessarily uncountable. More importantly, don't we have N = \{ x_\alpha \} = E? I guess we can derive a contradiction from this?
 
Last edited:
  • #10
Yes, "positive" makes more sense than "finite." In fact, m(E) \leq m([0,1]) = 1 so finiteness is automatic.

OK, so far we have established that each equivalence class contains at most one point of E.

Now we can use the axiom of choice to construct a set S containing one point of E \cap E_\alpha for each equivalence class E_\alpha for which E \cap E_\alpha is non-empty. Since each E_\alpha contains at most one point of E, what can you say about S?
 
  • #12
jbunniii said:
Yes, "positive" makes more sense than "finite." In fact, m(E) \leq m([0,1]) = 1 so finiteness is automatic.

OK, so far we have established that each equivalence class contains at most one point of E.

Now we can use the axiom of choice to construct a set S containing one point of E \cap E_\alpha for each equivalence class E_\alpha for which E \cap E_\alpha is non-empty. Since each E_\alpha contains at most one point of E, what can you say about S?

Ok. I think my argument above has shown that each equivalence class consists of *exactly* one point, and that if we apply the Axiom of Choice (hehe) and pluck one point out of each equivalence class, at the end of the day we get N = E. So, if we define the translates N_k = N + r_k = E + r_k for an enumeration of the rationals in [-1,1], we find that

<br /> mE \leq \sum_{k = 1}^\infty mN_k \leq 3,<br />

since it can be shown that the sets N_k are disjoint, E \subset \bigcup_{k = 1}^\infty N_k (just take r_k = 0) and \bigcup_{k = 1}^\infty N_k \subset [-1,2]. But this implies, by translation invariance of m, that

<br /> \sum_{k=1}^\infty mE \leq 3.<br />

This is absurd, since we assumed mE &gt; 0 \Rightarrow \sum_1^\infty mE = \infty. Hence E is not measurable. Have I missed anything?
 
Last edited:
  • #13
jbunniii said:
P.S. I love Belgian ales.:smile:

La Chouffe, maybe? Chimay?
 
  • #14
Replying to your updated message:

AxiomOfChoice said:
(2) Ah, I think I see...so each equivalence class consists of a single point: Given x,y\in E, x \sim y iff x = y. I guess this means there must be uncountably many equivalence classes, then, since mE &gt; 0 implies it's necessarily uncountable. More importantly, don't we have N = \{ x_\alpha \} = E? I guess we can derive a contradiction from this?

Let's be sure we agree about everything so far. Using your notation:

The equivalence classes are called E_\alpha.

Now each E_\alpha \cap E contains either zero or one element. For convenience, define

A = \{\alpha : E_\alpha \cap E \neq \emptyset\}

Using the axiom of choice, for each \alpha \in A we choose x_\alpha \in E_\alpha \cap E. We thereby construct this set:

N = \bigcup_{\alpha \in A} \{x_\alpha\}.

As you pointed out, we actually have N = E.

Now let

\{r_i\}_{i=1}^{\infty}

be an enumeration of the rationals in [0,1]

And define the following sets:

N_i = N + r_i

where the addition is performed modulo 1.

Then, exactly as in the construction of the standard non-measurable set, we have

N_i \cap N_j = \emptyset

whenever i \neq j, i.e., the sets are disjoint.

Then consider

\bigcup_{i=1}^{\infty} N_i

What can you say about the measure of this set, and why is that a contradiction?

P.S. For some reason the preview function is behaving strangely - it puts the wrong stuff in each TeX section. So I will have to fix any typos after I post the message.
 
  • #15
AxiomOfChoice said:
Ok. I think my argument above has shown that each equivalence class consists of *exactly* one point, and that if we apply the Axiom of Choice (hehe) and pluck one point out of each equivalence class, at the end of the day we get N = E. So, if we define the translates N_k = N + r_k = E + r_k for an enumeration of the rationals in [-1,1], we find that

<br /> mE \leq \bigcup_{k = 1}^\infty mN_k \leq 3,<br />

I assume you mean

\sum_{k=1}^\infty

not

\bigcup_{k = 1}^\infty

Yes, now you use the fact (just as in the standard construction of the nonmeasurable set) that the N_k are pairwise disjoint, and also the translation invariance of Lebesgue measure, to obtain

\bigcup_{k=1}^\infty N_k \subset [-1,2]

and thus

\sum_{k=1}^\infty m(E) \leq 3

That can't be true if m(E) &gt; 0. (Note that it COULD be true if m(E) = 0, which is why the positive hypothesis is important.)

Thus we have a contradiction. Therefore our assumption was wrong, and E must indeed contain distinct x,y such that x - y \in \mathbb{Q}.
 
Last edited:
  • #16
jbunniii said:
I assume you mean

\sum_{k=1}^\infty

not

\bigcup_{k = 1}^\infty

Yes, now you use the fact (just as in the standard construction of the nonmeasurable set) that the N_k are pairwise disjoint, and also the translation invariance of Lebesgue measure, to obtain

\bigcup_{k=1}^\infty N_k \subset [-1,2]

and thus

\sum_{k=1}^\infty m(E) \leq 3

That can't be true if 0 &lt; m(E) &lt; \infty. (Note that it COULD be true if m(E) = 0, which is why the positive hypothesis is important.)

Thus we have a contradiction. Therefore our assumption was wrong, and E must indeed contain distinct x,y such that x - y \in \mathbb{Q}.

jbunniii,

Yes, I meant \sum instead of \bigcup. You've also pointed out to me that there is actually no contradiction present in

<br /> mE \leq \sum_{k=1}^\infty mE.<br />

The contradiction comes from the *other* inequality, which would force mE = 0, which is impossible. I have made the appropriate corrections to my posts above.

Thanks again!
 
  • #17
Looks good! By the way, notice that we didn't actually need the axiom of choice in this case to construct the set N. We could have simply said "let N = E" and shown directly that the N_k's are pairwise disjoint.
 
  • #18
AxiomOfChoice said:
La Chouffe, maybe? Chimay?

I'm considering attending this event this afternoon:

http://www.artisanwinedepot.com/ProductDetails.asp?ProductCode=EVENT-CRAFTBEERBATTLE

Needless to say, I think the Belgians will thrash the Germans. :cool:
 
Back
Top