- #1
- 8,181
- 1,920
Morrobay suggested we split off this discussion from another thread.
I will post my summary of the EPR definition a bit later today.
I will post my summary of the EPR definition a bit later today.
nanosiborg said:DrChinese, I'm not sure what your point is.
mbd said:Antonio Di Lorenzo defines clearly the assumptions of Bell's Theorem.
http://arxiv.org/abs/1105.1286
DrChinese said:He is a local realist. As I have said many times, if you deviate from the Bell definition of realism, then you may get a different result. So what in this paper do you think is relevant to the discussion of Bell realism?
mbd said:Previously I posted a link to a paper of a team that you'd probably characterize as non-localists (although the science of their paper is untainted with bias), and it too had clear definitions and a uniquely clear exposition of the implications of the assumptions due to Bayes' Rule. Here is that link again:
http://dx.doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1002780107
mbd said:Antonio Di Lorenzo's paper (peer reviewed and recently published in Physical Review A) clearly defines the assumptions of Bell.
mbd said:Andrei Khrennikov defines realism, locality, and other relevant terms such as value definiteness, contextuality, etc.
http://arxiv.org/abs/1108.0001
lugita15 said:Let's suppose that QM is correct about all its experimental predictions. Then whenever you turn the polarizers to the same angle, you will get perfect correlation. From this you can reach three possible conclusions:
1. Even when you don't turn the polarizers to the same angle, it is still true that if you HAD turned the polarizers to the same angle, you WOULD have gotten perfect correlation.
2. When you don't turn the polarizes to the same angle, it makes no sense to ask what would have happened if you had turned them to the same angle.
3. When you don't turn the polarizers to the same angle, then it may be the case that you wouldn't have gotten perfect correlation if you had turned them to the same angle.
If we assume the principle of locality (i.e. excluding backward causation), then the only way option 3 would be possible is if the photons "knew" in advance what angle the polarizers would be turned to, or equivalently whatever is controlling the experiment decisions about the polarizer settings "knew" in advance whether the two photons would do the same thing or not. That would be superdeterminism, and we exclude it by the no-conspiracy condition.
So now we have two options left. Quantum mechanics takes option 2. But if you believe in counterfactual definiteness, you are forced into option 1. And then if you accept option 1 and the principle of locality (again, excluding backward causation), you are forced to conclude that the decision of each photon to go through or not go through must be determined by local hidden variables that are shared by the two photons.
mbd said:Here's a simple hypothetical counter-example to the conclusion that local realism is all but ruled out. I am not suggesting this to be physically plausible, nor am I proposing a theory. It is only an illuminating counter-example. It exploits two, if not more, known loopholes, that have not been closed experimentally. It has no backward-in-time effects, and no action at a distance, and results in CHSH correlations of 4.0.
Suppose that the measuring apparatuses are spewing, toward the emitter, a continuous, speed-of-light, stream of messenger particles that report the angle of the apparatus at the moment of messenger emission? Suppose that the emitter emits a pair of photon-precursor particles, one toward each measuring apparatus and that the photon pre-cursors remember the angle reported by the messenger particle arriving from their respective destinations at the moment of emission? Also, imbue the photon precursors with identical values if the measuring angles are pi/8 apart, and opposite values if the measuring angles are 3pi/8 apart. Now, also suppose that the photon pre-cursor observes the messenger particles it encounters along the way, and pauses whenever the messenger particle does not match the one seen on photon-precursor emission? Then, the pair of emitted photon pre-cursors can only arrive at the detectors coincidentally if both measuring apparatuses are at the same angles as they were when the photon pre-cursors were emitted. Upon arrival at the detector, the photon-precursors then produce a detection having the value imbued upon their emission.
The result in CHSH? 4.0
To make it do Malus' Law (to confirm measurements are consistent with classical photons), the particles need to, instead, slow or reverse course in proportion to how different the messenger is from the messenger seen at photon-precursor emission. It's less clear why this achieves a CHSH > 2 as well, thus it's left out in the simplified example above.
In any case, it passes the realism test, it violates Bell's Inequality, but it is not counterfactual definite.
Malus' Law only requires "randomness" if you assume the completeness, or correctness, of quantum mechanics. In the absolute mechanism I described, of course Malus' Law is not honored. In order for Malus' Law to be honored, the rate of emission and/or the velocity of the hypothetical "photon precursor" needs to be modulated according to the most recently received messenger particle. This would be consistent with classical conservation of angular momentum. But, if you insist on randomness, then it is in fact easier to simply put local randomness in each "photon precursor" and have it create a photon event upon impact with the polarizer conditioned by a probability distribution that will result in compliance with Malus' Law. (so, now we're using the detection loophole too!)DrChinese said:Second: Does it reproduce Malus? Sadly, no. That is because being deterministic, there is no way to get the random element going we need.
There is no communication between Alice and Bob. No need to explain something that doesn't happen. All interactions depend only on locally available information.DrChinese said:Lastly: There is NO explanation of how Alice and Bob’s communication occurs.
mbd said:1. Malus' Law only requires "randomness" if you assume the completeness, or correctness, of quantum mechanics. In the absolute mechanism I described, of course Malus' Law is not honored. In order for Malus' Law to be honored, the rate of emission and/or the velocity of the hypothetical "photon precursor" needs to be modulated according to the most recently received messenger particle. This would be consistent with classical conservation of angular momentum. But, if you insist on randomness, then it is in fact easier to simply put local randomness in each "photon precursor" and have it create a photon event upon impact with the polarizer conditioned by a probability distribution that will result in compliance with Malus' Law. (so, now we're using the detection loophole too!)
2. There is no communication between Alice and Bob. No need to explain something that doesn't happen. All interactions depend only on locally available information.
mbd said:DrChinese, I am very sorry for having gone out of my way to create an extremely simple, no math necessary, self-evident, example of a system that can violate Bell's Inequality.
jk22 said:In QM treatment of EPRB it is seen from the onset that the measurement disturbs the system since suppose we measure 1st particle with + then
psi_before equals ((+-)-(-+))/sqrt2 and
psi_after equals* (+-)
since both differ we conclude there was a disturbance.
Hence we cannot use the EPR criterion of existence of elem. of phys. reality.
DrChinese said:You have made a good point, and I am sure Bohr would agree with you! In QM the system is disturbed.
However, if you ASSUME that there was no such disturbance (as EPR does), then the criterion applies. (Of course there was something of a circular nature to the EPR argument.) They say:
"On the other hand, since at the time of measurement the two systems no longer interact, no real change can take place in the second system in consequence of anything that may be done to the first system."
mbd said:There is nothing circular about the EPR argument. It is a standard proof by contradiction.
The assumption is that special relativity applies to all physical phenomena. With this assumption, measuring the first cannot change the second. QM, though, predicts a change to the second. So, either special relativity does not exclude "spooky action" or QM is an incomplete theory.
The EPR paradox, named after its creators Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, is a thought experiment that challenges the principles of quantum mechanics. It suggests that two entangled particles can have their properties correlated in a way that is impossible to explain using classical physics.
Bell's inequality is a mathematical inequality that can be used to test the predictions of quantum mechanics against those of classical mechanics. It was developed as a way to test the predictions of the EPR paradox and determine whether quantum mechanics was a complete theory.
Bell's theorem proved that quantum mechanics cannot be explained by any local hidden variables theory. This means that there is no way to explain the correlations between entangled particles using classical physics, and that there must be some form of non-locality or action at a distance.
Realism, in the context of EPR and Bell experiments, refers to the idea that physical objects have properties that exist independent of observation or measurement. The EPR and Bell experiments suggest that this idea may not hold true in the quantum world, as the properties of entangled particles seem to be dependent on the act of measurement.
The EPR and Bell experiments have significant implications for our understanding of the nature of reality. They challenge traditional notions of causality and locality, and suggest that the act of measurement can have a direct influence on the properties of particles. These experiments continue to spark debates and further research in the field of quantum mechanics.