HallsofIvy said:
Deacon John, with that definition of "infinity" you get complex numbers with an "infinite number of infinities"- a different infinity of each end of each straight line through the origin. Topologically, that is the "Stone-Chech compactification" of the complex numbers and it is topologically equivalent to a circle and its interior.
You can also do the "one point compactification" of the complex numbers by defining a topology so that all "large" complex numbers (large in the sense that the absolute value is large) so that there is only one "infinity". Then you get a set topologically equivalent to the surface of a sphere.
However, those are purely topological constructions- you haven't said anything about how to do arithmetic with these new "infinities" much less take the logarithm.
HallsOfIvy,
You're basically right. I'm doing more like "applied mathematics" than pure mathmatics, here. But then, the answer that I gave seemed to me to be in the spirit of the question that was asked.
Two minor points,
1) I did say that something like Robinson's non-standard analysis might be required to make the above arguments rigorous, although it seems to me that the intuitive content is clear. Robinson's N-S-A allows one to do normal arithmetic with infinities and infintesimals.
Actually, another way to do it is just using limits and elementary calculus and throwing in just those infinities that one needs. As you noticed, if one works out the complete solution that I started, one probably needs an infinity at each end of each line through the origin in the plane. Or, maybe each line in the plane. One would have to work out the details to be sure. Of course, that is just exactly what Robinson did. So, if one did that, he would be taking a first step in the direction of what Robinson did.
The elementary concept of limits can be linked to the topological concept using, for example, the techniques developed for the study of metric spaces in Kelly's General Topology.
2) a circle at infinity attached to each end of each line in the plane is only a small part of the Stone Check compactification.
In fact the S.C. c. plane is so big that I've never been able to get an intuitive handle on it.
The most my intuition has been able to stretch around in the S-C compactification of N. There, for example, you can associate a point in the S-C compactification of N that is in the closure of the even numbers but not the odd numbers. (just take a bounded multiplicative linear functional on l_infinity that is zero on the odd njumber but is non-zero on the even numbers and is not of the form x->f(x) for some x in N (f is in l_infinity) and use the Hahn Banach theorem to extend it to all of N. - Wow -it's been over 30 years since I've actually looked at the definition of the S.C. c. of anything. I hope I got that right.)
There are similar examples (I'm sure) in the S.C.c. of the plane, showing that there are more points than just the "infinities" attached to the end of each line.
Neverthe less, the subset of the S-C-c of the plane that you called out is probably the natural topological setting for my arguments.
And a question - I have the impression that the Stone Chech compactification (of a measure space) is the maximal ideal space of the set of bounded measurable functions when that set (L_infinity or l_infinity) is viewed as a commutative W* algebra acting on the Hilbert space of all square integrable functions of that set. Please let me know if I've got that wrong.
DJ
P.S. One of the many things that's so great about this forum. It's helping me get back in shape. In the last couple of days since I've been on your forum, I've looked up all kinds of things (especially in number theory) that I'd sluffed over as I tried to learn the subject on my own. I've been trying to learn modern number theory off and on - basically on my own - for over ten years now. I still don't have Wiles proof "under my belt," but I get closer all the time.
I think in the future I'll concentrate on the number theory board.