The notion of locality in (Quantum) Physics should be clearly defined

In summary, the thread about entanglement and Bell tests has been closed prematurely. It has not been clarified what "locality" means. Locality is the property of a relativistic theory that obeys the causality principle of relativistic spacetime. Locality is implemented by construction through the demand that local observables must commute at space-like separated arguments. This means that there cannot be any nonlocal (inter)actions between distant parts of a quantum system. However, in the mostly discussed case of entangled photon pairs you can of course have entangled photon states with the corresponding Bell-inequality violating correlations between the outcomes of measurements on the single photons in the pair at far distant places.
  • #141
vanhees71 said:
We experience these correlations in our experiential reality (what other reality should be?), because obviously QT is a correct description of Nature and not something invented by EPR what they think should be the right description. That's, how the natural sciences work under the best of all circumstances: You have two well-defined models about how Nature is described (this was of course not given by EPR but by Bell about 30 years later for the model "local, realistic HV theory", while it was established for modern QT already in 1926 ;-)), and you can thus objectively decide which of the models describe the observations better, and that's clearly QT. It's even better: There's not the slightest hint that QT delivers any wrong predictions for the outcome of experiments yet!
I completely agree. The heart of the problem in all these disputes is quantum probability and randomness. Andrei Khrennikov and Karl Svozil/1/ put it – to my mind – in a nutshell:

It might not be totally unreasonable to claim that, already starting from some of the earliest (in hindsight) indications of quanta in the 1902 Rutherford–Soddy exponential decay law and the small aberrations predicted by Schweidler [6], the tide of indeterminism [7,8] was rolling against chartered territories of fin de siécle mechanistic determinism. Riding the waves were researchers like Exner, who already in his 1908 inaugural lecture as rector magnificus [9] postulated that irreducible randomness is, and probability theory therefore needs to be, at the heart of all sciences; natural as well as social. Exner [10] was forgotten but cited in Schrödinger’s alike “Zürcher Antrittsvorlesung” of 1922 [11]. Not much later Born expressed his inclinations to give up determinism in the world of the atoms [12], thereby denying the existence of some inner properties of the quanta which condition a definite outcome for, say, the scattering after collisions.

Von Neumann [13] was among the first who emphasized this new feature which was very different from the “in principle knowable unknowns” grounded in epistemology alone. Quantum randomness was treated as individual randomness; that is, as if single electrons or photons are sometimes capable of behaving acausally and irreducibly randomly. Such randomness cannot be reduced to a variability of properties of systems in some ensemble. Therefore, quantum randomness is often considered as irreducible randomness.

Von Neumann understood well that it is difficult, if not outright impossible in general, to check empirically the randomness for individual systems, say for electrons or photons. In particular, he proceeded with the statistical interpretation of probability based on the mathematical model of von Mises [14,15] based upon relative frequencies after admissible place selections.
” [Bold by LJ]

/1/ Khrennikov, A., Svozil, K.: Quantum probability and randomness. Entropy 21(1), 35 (2019)
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, DrChinese and vanhees71
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #142
AndreasC said:
So what is your objection to observationally equivalent theories/interpretations?
I have no objection against equivalent theories. If they make the same predictions they are the same theory. I only have strong objections against interpretations that contradict the very foundation of the theory they pretend to interpret.
 
  • #143
vanhees71 said:
If they make the same predictions they are the same theory.
I don't think it's quite so simple...

vanhees71 said:
I only have strong objections against interpretations that contradict the very foundation of the theory they pretend to interpret.
What do you mean exactly? The point is that you can have theories with different foundational postulates that deliver the same observational predictions. That's what, say, Bohmian mechanics does. It's not really the same theory, but you can't rule it out observationally.

Suitable Lorentz ether theories are also observationally equivalent to special relativity, but the shift in perspective was important!
 
  • Like
Likes kered rettop and Demystifier
  • #144
vanhees71 said:
I only have strong objections against interpretations that contradict the very foundation of the theory they pretend to interpret.
That a theory is corroborated theory doesn't mean its foundations or constraints are impeccable.

Some object to precisely to the QM foundations(but for different reasons), but doesn't dispute predictions as an effective theory.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier and AndreasC
  • #145
vanhees71 said:
I have no objection against equivalent theories. If they make the same predictions they are the same theory. I only have strong objections against interpretations that contradict the very foundation of the theory they pretend to interpret.
What if two theories have different foundations (so they contradict the foundations of each other), but make the same measurable predictions?

I've asked you this question so many times, in different forms, but never got a self-consistent answer.

One example is quantum theory with and without the collapse. They contradict the foundations of each other, but make the same measurable predictions. How do you decide which of the two is right? (And please, don't repeat your mantra that collapse only describes the special case of projective experiments, because all POVM measurements can be described by a generalized collapse rule, see the book by Nielsen and Chuang, which is a book about practical applications of QM, not about interpretations.)

Another example is Bohmian and standard quantum theory. What if the Bohmian version was developed first, but then later someone developed what we call "standard" version, would you be against the standard version because it contradicts foundations of the Bohmian theory?

@PeterDonis, don't delete it because collapse and Bohmian mechanics have a lot to do with quantum nonlocality.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes DrChinese, Fra and AndreasC
  • #146
AndreasC said:
Suitable Lorentz ether theories are also observationally equivalent to special relativity, but the shift in perspective was important!
Excellent point! The Einstein special theory of relativity was formulated as an interpretation of Maxwell equations and Lorentz theory of ether, but it contradicted the very foundations of the ether theory. Einstein didn't base his interpretation on the Michelson-Morley experiment. @vanhees71 , according to his own principles, should be the first to oppose the Einstein no-ether interpretation.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC
  • #147
What an utter nonsense. Why should I oppose Einstein's no-ether interpretation? To the contrary: Something that's no observable nor necessary to formulate the theory isn't needed and complicates the issues. It's as with Bohmian trajectories, which are just superfluous complications of math and neither needed to formulate QT nor does it provide anything observable.
 
  • #148
vanhees71 said:
I have no objection against equivalent theories. If they make the same predictions they are the same theory. I only have strong objections against interpretations that contradict the very foundation of the theory they pretend to interpret.
This is not what you meant. You really meant this:

"I have no objection against equivalent theories. If they make the same predictions and accept the same foundations, they are the same theory. I only have strong objections against interpretations based on other foundations, different from foundations of my favored interpretation. My favored interpretation is the best because it is the minimal interpretation, which means that it makes the smallest number of assumptions, where, of course, the foundations of the theory are not counted as assumptions, because they are the right foundations that every theory compatible with present experiments should be based on."
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question and DrChinese
  • #149
vanhees71 said:
Why should I oppose Einstein's no-ether interpretation?
Because it contradicts the very foundation of the Lorentz ether theory it pretends to interpret.
 
  • #150
Einstein didn't intepret Lorentz ether theory but introduced an entirely new concept, i.e., introducing a new description of space and time and a new realization of inertial frames.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #151
vanhees71 said:
Einstein didn't intepret Lorentz ether theory but introduced an entirely new concept, i.e., introducing a new description of space and time and a new realization of inertial frames.
So did Bohm, he didn't interpret QM but introduced an entirely new concept, i.e., introducing a new description of microscopic phenomena and a new realization of uncertainty relations.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC
  • #152
Yes, but it doesn't lead to any other prediction of observable facts than standard QM. I've nothing against Bohmian mechanics within non-relativistic 1st quantized QM. I've not seen a convincing realization for relativistic QFT. I know that you disagree with the latter.
 
  • #153
vanhees71 said:
Something that's no observable nor necessary to formulate the theory isn't needed and complicates the issues.
You mean, something like Feynman path integrals in non-relativistic QM?
 
  • #154
Path integrals are just another mathematical tool to formulate QM, and it's applicable in relativsitic QFT too.
 
  • #155
vanhees71 said:
I've nothing against Bohmian mechanics within non-relativistic 1st quantized QM.
Really? Isn't it an unnecessary complication?

vanhees71 said:
I've not seen a convincing realization for relativistic QFT. I know that you disagree with the latter.
We already discussed it. You didn't claim that it doesn't make the same predictions. You objected that it is not based on the same foundations. In particular, you couldn't accept that gauge potentials can be "real", even though there is no experiment that can't be interpreted by a "real" gauge potential. Is an interpretation with a "real" gauge potential more complicated? Probably is, but Bohmian interpretation of 1st quantized QM is also more complicated, and yet you have nothing against it.
 
  • #156
vanhees71 said:
Path integrals are just another mathematical tool to formulate QM
Do you know any problem in non-relativistic QM that is easier to solve with path integrals, then with other methods? (I know that path integrals simplify a lot calculations in gauge field theories, but that's not what I'm asking about.)
 
  • #157
No, path integrals are usually pretty nasty. The solution of the most simple non-relativistic model for the energy eigenstates of the hydrogen atom took a long time to achieve at all, and that's why Feynman abandoned the path-integral for use in introductory QM lectures. Even in the cases, where you can calculate the propagator exactly using the path-integral description the operator approach (using the Heisenberg picture) or wave-mechanics is simpler. That's for cases, where you have to evaluate a Gaussian path integral (free particle, harmonic oscillator, particle in a homogeneous force field). In the path-integral approach you need some regulator scheme. I think the most convenient one is the heat-kernel approach, although for free particles and the harmonic oscillator you can do it by brute-force evaluation as the continuum limit of the time-lattice calculation.

Indeed it's full advantage the path integral shows for many-body calculations and QFT. Indeed the quantization of non-Abelian gauge theories is much simpler than the equivalent operator formalism, which has been developed after the path-integral approach (Faddeev-Popov quantization) had been developed and BRST symmetry discovered. The latter plays the key role in the operator quantization (Kugo et al).
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and Demystifier
  • #158
vanhees71 said:
Yes, but it doesn't lead to any other prediction of observable facts than standard QM.
Generally, for me at least: the merit of a competing theory, that may be built on different foundations, and have the same predictions in the current domain of corroboration, may offer a different paths forward when we try to generalize the theory to new predictive domains. It's like SR vs GR vs classical mechanics; for everyday physics or standard engineering on earth, classical mechanics is the BETTER effective theory in the sense that it is more efficient to use, to make computations with etc; even though it's "foundations" are questionable. But try to convince a construction engineer that he should use general relativity instead of newtons mechanics to check his construtions. Why would he?

So for me, the main discriminator I use to choose between competing paradigms is; which of them you belive makes extending the theory unification of all forces easier to solve? And here we may have different ideas and noone can tell in advance what is the best one.

I don't know if anyone in the Bohmian program today has any such ambitions though. But not that I am aware of.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese, AndreasC and Demystifier
  • #159
Fra said:
So for me, the main discriminator I use to choose between competing paradigms is; which of them you belive makes extending the theory unification of all forces easier to solve? And here we may have different ideas and noone can tell in advance what is the best one.

I don't know if anyone in the Bohmian program today has any such ambitions though. But not that I am aware of.
In my case, Bohmian way of thinking taught me that symmetries, especially space-time symmetries, may be emergent than fundamental. Then thinking of symmetries as emergent lead me to new ideas that do not depend on the Bohmian interpretation as such, see e.g. https://arxiv.org/abs/2301.04448
 
  • Like
Likes Fra
  • #160
vanhees71 said:
Einstein didn't intepret Lorentz ether theory but introduced an entirely new concept, i.e., introducing a new description of space and time and a new realization of inertial frames.
But earlier you said that if two theories are observationally equivalent, they are the same theory!
 
  • #161
True, but then usually one chooses the simpler one, i.e., one favors SRT against LET, because the latter makes unobservable additional assumptions (some "ether frame"), which doesn't add anything new, i.e., concerning observable facts about Nature they are otherwise equivalent. From a purely scientific point of view they are the same theory.
 
  • #162
Demystifier said:
In my case, Bohmian way of thinking taught me that symmetries, especially space-time symmetries, may be emergent than fundamental. Then thinking of symmetries as emergent lead me to new ideas that do not depend on the Bohmian interpretation as such, see e.g. https://arxiv.org/abs/2301.04448
This is a "insight" I share with you, even if I am not into Bohmian mechanics.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #163
vanhees71 said:
True, but then usually one chooses the simpler one
But simplicity is subjective. Personally I find the Bohmian QM simpler than the standard one, for many reasons. One of the reasons is that Bohmian QM does not need the measurement postulate, which standard QM does ("When an observable is measured, then the probability is such and such ...").
 
  • #164
But Bohmian QM doesn't predict anything from that. All there is, also within BM, are the said probabilities.
 
  • #165
vanhees71 said:
True, but then usually one chooses the simpler one, i.e., one favors SRT against LET, because the latter makes unobservable additional assumptions (some "ether frame"), which doesn't add anything new, i.e., concerning observable facts about Nature they are otherwise equivalent. From a purely scientific point of view they are the same theory.
Right, so I think then we can agree that it is a case of two theories, or interpretations of theories, with different foundations, where one eventually came to dominate, despite being observationally equivalent. That is, however, different from the description of shifts only happening because one theory matches the results better. Simplicity is kind of subjective (indeed many physicists at the time probably did not find the counterintuitive aspects of relativity to be "simpler"), what I think is much more indicative that this was the correct idea (which of course may be reappraised in the future) is that this shift in the metaphysics of the theory, despite being observationally equivalent, provided a new way of thought that allowed new breakthroughs, for instance general relativity. So I see this as an example where a change of interpretation led to radical increase in content and understanding, and discovering new properties of nature.

Bottom line is, I definitely agree with what @Fra said. As such, I don't think interpretational (or, to use a "bad" word, "philosophical") investigations are pointless, and honestly I think this is the main problem in this thread.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt
  • #166
vanhees71 said:
But Bohmian QM doesn't predict anything from that. All there is, also within BM, are the said probabilities.
So?
 
  • #167
So, there's no need to consider these fictitious trajectories.
 
  • Skeptical
  • Like
Likes GarberMoisha and weirdoguy
  • #168
vanhees71 said:
So, there's no need to consider these fictitious trajectories.
There is no need to make the discussion of this whole thread, and yet we do. Why? Because we want to understand something conceptually. The same is with considering the fictitious trajectories.
 
  • #169
What is fictious seems to depend on your primary notions. From the perspective of QFT i would say internal observers is fiction because they are ambigous. But OTOH from an agent centered starting point the "observer" that corresponds to QFT is what is fictious because it ia also ambigous in another way.

But seeing both views I think helps see the power of using symmtries as constraints, and the explanatory value of symmetries beeing emergent. I think both mechanisms are at play at once at different levels in the theory.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC
  • #170
What are "internal observers"?
 
  • #171
Lets see if Peter Donis will slap my fingers for using the term:

its just a normal observer, but one with finite information capacity, to supposedly be more realistic. Otherwise its a normal observer.

But this limit meas thay cant entertain infinite repeats of experimenta to make perfect ensembles and timeless inferences.

In QFT or qm. Ensembles or arbitrarily large quantum systesm otherwise need to collect, process and represent so much data that its "fictious"

Also an internal observer does not need to be a classical or macro device. Its just tjat its inferencea would be extremely volatile.

Of course QM isnt desgine for internal observers.which is exactly MY problem with it. It is desigen for an ideal "fictive" asymptotic observer. But this fiction is reasonable for small systems.

/Fredrik
 
  • Sad
Likes weirdoguy
  • #172
Fra said:
Lets see if Peter Donis will slap my fingers for using the term
Not for using the term but for making a statement like this. It's off topic and adds nothing to the thread. If you have something to say, just say it. Don't speculate about what, if any, moderator response you will get.
 
  • #173
Fra said:
its just a normal observer, but one with finite information capacity, to supposedly be more realistic. Otherwise its a normal observer.

But this limit meas thay cant entertain infinite repeats of experimenta to make perfect ensembles and timeless inferences.

In QFT or qm. Ensembles or arbitrarily large quantum systesm otherwise need to collect, process and represent so much data that its "fictious"

Also an internal observer does not need to be a classical or macro device. Its just tjat its inferencea would be extremely volatile.

Of course QM isnt desgine for internal observers.which is exactly MY problem with it. It is desigen for an ideal "fictive" asymptotic observer. But this fiction is reasonable for small systems.
What does any of this (even assuming it's all valid) have to do with the topic of this thread?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #174
PeterDonis said:
What does any of this (even assuming it's all valid) have to do with the topic of this thread?
It was an example of that different perspectives/interpretation yields different elements that are fictious. An example that i consider interesting especially for the view of spacetime and its symmetries.

/Fredrik
 
  • #175
Fra said:
It was an example of that different perspectives/interpretation yields different elements that are fictious.
Is it an example you just made up, or is it taken from something in the literature. Remember that personal speculation is off limits here.

Also, I'm still not clear how this relates to the topic of this thread. This thread is about the specific notion of locality. It is not about general properties of different interpretations.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
44
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
830
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
54
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
6
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
79
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
4
Replies
138
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
0
Views
351
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
4
Replies
109
Views
7K
Back
Top