Fredrik said:
It's central to their interpretation of the result (the absurdities they put in the title and the abstract), but it's not used in the proof, and it's not needed to understand the statement of the theorem.
Ok, I think I see, and might help explain some of your objections. So when you said the "definition" isn't used in the proof it wasn't a claim that the authors didn't use the "definition". This has a number of consequences in trying to make sense of your interpretation. One, that you are at odds with PBR's interpretation of their theorem. This you verify farther down this post. So now a quick outline of some implications of your interpretation.
1) That you are at odds with the "interpreted statistically" used in the title.
Note: This is not the only interpretation of statistics, merely one interpretation of statistical that is ostensibly common among certain types of realist. Hence taking issue with it has another implication about your interpretation.
2) That "interpreted statistically" has a singular interpretation.
This is wrong. Nor did the PBR paper imply that "interpreted statistically" as used in the title was the only way to interpret "statistically". This implies:
3) That your rejection of "interpreted statistically", as used in the title, is consonant with the articles rejection of "interpreted statistically" on the basis of the theorem.
Why then are you taking issue with "interpreted statistically" as used in the title? This implies:
4) You must hold a differing interpretation as to what "interpreted statistically" entails.
Fine, so do I in the QM context. But to reject the incongruent take on "interpreted statistically" as used in the title implies it is not valid a priori. Leaving no point in defining a theorem to rule it out. This implies we are back to:
2) That "interpreted statistically" has a singular interpretation.
And around in circles we go.
Yet the fact remains that not only that interpretation, ostensibly common among certain types of realist, requires that it get a fair shake at falsification, but it says nothing a priori about your alternative characterization of "interpreted statistically". In effect your interpretation is ostensibly consonant with the results of the theorem, yet are are taking issue with the authors rejection of an interpretation of "interpreted statistically" that you yourself do not ascribe to.
This seems to be a symmetrical characterization of why/how you could assign ontological/epistemic labels in a manner that is exactly opposite of how someone else could apply those same labels in a potentially valid way, using the same definitions of ontological/epistemic. That's why I tried to get you to look at ontological/epistemic characterization outside of the QM proper to begin with. To illustrate how the labeling can legitimately be reversed without affecting the legitimacy of the labels under the same definitions.
Fredrik said:
Not only is it demonstrably true, I have demonstrated it. See post #155, where I typed up the argument for a qubit without using any assumptions about "properties".
If you are not making any assumptions about "properties", how do you go about specifying the argument in terms of a qubit? In order for a qubit to be a qubit it must in some sense contain the "properties" of a qubit. Furthermore, to be a qubit with qubit properties entails that the "outcomes" of experiments on a qubit have certain characteristics. I recognize, as you reiterate below, that you did not deem the definition as I restated it as unreasonable, but it appears to me that you are hinging your absolute characterizations on descriptive elements of the model that fall bellow the level of empirically accessible "outcomes". Not a problem in general except for the absolute character of those characterizations. The same absolutes I am taking issue with when you specify X with either an ontological or epistemic characterization. It's not the characterization it that is at issue, it is the unique law of the excluded middle characterization that is at issue.
Fredrik said:
It's the HS definition of ontological model. Yes, the person who thought of this definition probably had the concept of "complete list of properties" in mind when he wrote it down, but that idea just inspired the definition, it's not actually a part of it. It can't be, because you can't make something undefined a part of a definition. (Not if you're working within the framework of mathematics. If you're trying to define what you mean by "mathematics", that's another story).
Ontological specifications have a character very similar coordinate choices in math. A coordinate choice is not a physical choice. Yet how a system is ontological characterized is often contingent upon that coordinate choice. Several (non)paradoxes hinge on this, like whose clock is
really the slow clock of the two? What is the
true momentum of that mass? Is that variable really an ontic or an epistemic variable? Given the HS definitions, a system described from one perspective can specify a variable as ontic, whereas the same variable described from another equally perspective will specify it as epistemic, using the exact same HS definition. Neither one is any more right or wrong than whose clock is really going slower in SR. See my problem when you designate an ontological characterization and presume that that ontological characterization is in itself sufficient to invalidate the legitimacy of a characterization?
Fredrik said:
I didn't object to the fact that you related λ to outcomes. I objected to the fact that you defined "ontic" as λ determines outcomes, and claimed that this is what HS did, when in fact they defined "ψ-ontic" as λ determines probabilities of outcomes.
So apparently you restricted the meaning of "determines outcomes" to entail a narrower meaning than what was provided. In fact, if λ determines "
probabilities of outcomes" that is in part the outcome which λ determines. To say that A determine B does not entail that B ≠
probabilities of outcomes.
Fredrik said:
I'm not particularly interested in whether there are other definitions that would also make sense, and perhaps be more useful in a different context, because PBR indicated that they are using the HS definitions. They did this by referencing the HS article immediately after declaring that they are going to explain what they mean by the two views, and then proceeding to state criteria that perfectly match the HS definitions of ψ-ontic, ψ-complete, ψ-supplemented, and ψ-epistemic.
But it is not strictly "other definitions" than those provided by HS, rather other equally valid context in which the same variables are defined, that those same HS definitions entail assigning the same variables different ontological characterizations. That is why I previously pointed out that if you partition a set of epistemic variables you can then create a new set of derivative variables in which the partition epistemic variables are, by HS definition, ontic relative to the derivative variables.
Fredrik said:
I'm sorry about that, but I have spent most of this week on stuff related to this article, and I'd rather not expand the list of topics further by getting into a discussion about ways to avoid talking about the stuff the article is talking about.
Fine. Then address these issues I have pointed out wrt ontological specifications of variables. Simply assigning epistemic/ontic characterizations and presuming legitimacy from that alone will get you nowhere until these issues are addressed.
Fredrik said:
The question only makes sense if you believe that "λ uniquely determines an outcome" means the same thing as "λ uniquely determines the probability of every outcome". An outcome is a measurement result. A specification of the probabilities of all the outcomes is a state, not an outcome.
As a matter of fact that is exactly the way I intended it, but I have to admit that by qualifying "determines" with "uniquely" I left it poorly defined.
Here's the difficulty. In classical probability a probabilistic
state does not correspond to any actual state. It's merely a model state due to limited knowledge. In QM, in some sense, this probabilistic
state is apparently in fact the actual state of the system itself, not just the model, at least to some extent. The PBR article constructed a pair of states to demonstrate this. Empirically predicated on non-probabilistic outcomes, i.e., a zero probability of differing outcomes. Hence, unlike classical probabilities, the resulting state is apparently an actual outcome, rather than state of the model alone.
So classically saying that "λ uniquely determines an outcome" means the same thing as "λ uniquely determines the probability of every outcome" makes no sense, in QM probabilities it apparently does mean the same thing in some sense. So if I characterized "outcomes" in a manner that did not allow for the possible inclusion of "probability of outcome" it would be tantamount to rejecting the results of the PBR theorem a priori.
Fredrik said:
P(k|\lambda,\lambda,X)=0 is the result that contradicts the assumption that we started with a ψ-epistemic ontological model for QM. It certainly doesn't mean that they assume that the ontological model only assigns probabilities 0 or 1 to measurement results. They do not make any such assumption. However, as I said in #141, I think the interesting part of the result is that it rules out ontological models that do satisfy that requirement. (It does so as a side effect of ruling out all ψ-epistemic ontological models for QM).
Of course not. The pair pure quantum state was explicit chosen to avoid mixed states, not deny their existence. Though I am still lost as to how your labeling of epistemic verses ontological are relevant in the domain of all possible models, nor can get you to even attempt to clarify, I do agree that interesting part of PBR succeeded ruling out models that attempt to separate the probabilistic state from the ontic state, or treat the probabilistic state as purely a modeling artifact like it is in classical physics.
So we are not so far apart wrt our interpretations when limited to the context of QM as it presently formulated, but in the space of all possible models, exactly equivalent or not, I see the narrow epistemic/ontological labels breaking down as any sort of meaningful label.
Fredrik said:
This is what I said in #141, in slightly different words:
Is it possible that quantum probabilities are classical probabilities in disguise? If the answer is yes, then there's a ψ-epistemic ontological model for QM that assigns probabilities 0 or 1 to each possible measurement result. We can prove that the answer is "no" by proving that no such model exists, but we have found a way to prove a stronger result: There is no ψ-epistemic ontological model for QM.
Yes, and I agree to a large extent. But here is the problem, is it possible to formulate a theory in which a pool ball either has a non-zero kinetic energy or not? No. Its kinetic energy, and whether it's zero or not, depends solely on the non-physical choice of what coordinate system it is considered under. Hence the fact that QM does not provide for assigning 0 or 1 to each possible measurement result is not at all strange, nor fall outside the possibility of characterizing with a purely ontic substructure. It only requires properties to be derivative, rather than innate, like the "magic" Ken G spoke of, to whatever ontic constructs are posited.
Fredrik said:
Assuming that we're no longer talking about ψ-epistemic and ψ-ontic, and instead about whether a variable should be described as representing knowledge or reality, I would say that it depends on the context. The epistemic states of one theory might correspond to the ontic states of another, less accurate theory.
There it is in the last sentence. The core of the issues I have been attempting to articulate and get clarification from you on. Yet the last sentence of that paragraph appears to directly contradict the first. If the epistemic states of one theory correspond to the ontic states of another then we are still talking about ψ-epistemic and ψ-ontic. Hence it still depends on the context in which you define ψ, as your first sentence notes. So how does this not justify everything I have been trying to get you to articulate?