JDoolin said:
This is a major part of what I can't understand. The Effect of the Lorentz Transformations are essentially directly proportianal to distance in space and time. i.e. If you Lorentz Transform an event that is 2 light years away, the effect will be roughly twice as much as if you Lorentz Transform an event that is 1 light-year away.
...Maybe I'm misinterpreting what you're saying when you say "the laws of SR hold locally." The way I'm taking your meaning is that you can Lorentz Transform events within a certain radius in spacetime, but events beyond that radius are not Lorentz Transformed.
That's not what I mean; see below.
JDoolin said:
A "limited domain" of applicability for SR seems to me, the same as "throwing it away." If I told you that "rotation" had a limited domain of applicability, it would mean that if you turn to the left or right, only nearby objects respond. Things in your room might change positions relative to your facing, but distant stars would not cooperate; they would remain in the same place; stubbornly remaining in front of you as you spin around, because rotation is "only valid locally".
If you say "SR is valid only locally" you're saying that only nearby objects are affected by the Lorentz Transformations. It is absurd. Either SR is valid or it's not.
There are several issues conflated here, which I'll try to disentangle; hopefully this will also clarify some of the terms (e.g., "domain of applicability") I'm using.
First, the general issue of the "validity" of theories: If you absolutely must have a "go/no go" decision on SR, so to speak, then SR is *not* valid, just as Newtonian mechanics is not valid. Both are approximate theories that have known limitations. Newtonian mechanics can't handle objects moving at speeds large enough relative to the speed of light. SR can't handle situations where gravity must be taken into account.
GR is also an approximate theory with known limitations, but its domain of applicability is wider than both Newtonian mechanics and SR, since it includes both as special cases. If we specialize to weak gravity and slow speeds, we get Newtonian mechanics; if we specialize to negligible gravity (but allow relativistic speeds) we get SR.
GR's known limitations are: (1) It predicts spacetime singularities in certain situations, which basically amounts to saying that it admits it can't cover those particular situations and new physics is needed; (2) It isn't a quantum theory, and the general belief is that a quantum theory of gravity is needed (for example, to cover those situations where GR predicts singularities).
Second, there's the issue of what, given the above, it means to say that SR holds "locally". In the standard interpretation of GR (where gravity = spacetime curvature), SR holds "locally" in a curved spacetime in the same sense that Euclidean geometry holds "locally" on a curved surface, such as the surface of the Earth. The Earth's surface is not Euclidean, but I don't have to worry about its curvature when I'm measuring the square footage of my house; the curvature is too small to matter. But if I try to measure the area of the state of Alaska, for example, I'd better take the Earth's curvature into account or I'll get the wrong answer; in other words, Euclidean geometry does *not* hold on the Earth's surface when you get to that large a scale.
Does that mean that, for example, if my house is in the middle of the state of Alaska, and I stand in the middle of my house and spin around, my house spins but the state of Alaska as a whole doesn't? Of course not. But it does mean, for example, that my spinning around doesn't change the area of the state of Alaska; it's still different than it would be if the Earth's surface was flat. So whatever coordinate transformation is being induced on the entire surface of the Earth by my rotation, it must preserve the non-Euclidean geometry of that surface. If that means that such a transformation is different in some way than a "standard" rotational transformation in flat Euclidean space, then okay, it's different. But locally (within my house), I can still treat the transformation as a standard rotation in flat Euclidean space, as long as I remember that I can only make that approximation over a small enough distance.
Similarly, if I'm in a curved spacetime and I change my velocity, locally (i.e., over a small enough patch of spacetime that the effects of curvature are negligible--same basic criterion as I used above for my house vs. Alaska) I can model this by a standard Lorentz transformation, provided I set up local Minkowski coordinates around the event of the velocity change (just as I can set up local Euclidean coordinates inside my house, even though they don't do a good job of representing the entire state of Alaska). It may well be that the transformation induced on distant parts of spacetime will *not* be a standard Lorentz transformation, because it will have to preserve the global curvature (i.e., non-Minkowskian geometry) of the spacetime. But certainly *some* transformation will be induced; the entire universe will look different after the velocity change, not just a local patch, just as it's not only my house that spins around me when I spin.
Third, there's the issue of "interpretations" of GR. I said above that gravity = spacetime curvature is the standard interpretation. However, it is true that it is not the *only* interpretation. (One good discussion of this is Kip Thorne's, in his book
Black Holes and Time Warps: Einstein's Outrageous Legacy, which I highly recommend, and not just for this specific issue but as a generally very good presentation of relativity for the lay reader.) Another way to interpret GR is by treating the metric as a field on a background spacetime that is flat--i.e., Minkowski. Basically, you start by writing the metric as
g_{\mu \nu} = \eta_{\mu \nu} + h_{\mu \nu}
where \eta_{\mu \nu} is the standard Minkowski metric and h_{\mu \nu} is the extra field that accounts for the effects of gravity. Then you try to figure out what h_{\mu \nu} is by doing an expansion in powers of some parameter; when this method was first investigated in the 1950's and 1960's, by Feynman among many others, the motivation was to look for a quantum theory of gravity, so h_{\mu \nu} was taken to be (sorry for the bit of jargon here) a massless spin-two quantum field, the "graviton", on the background spacetime, and the expansion was just a standard perturbation expansion in powers of the graviton's quantum coupling constant (which is related to, but not necessarily the same as, Newton's gravitational constant), adding more and more different Feynman diagrams for different possible virtual graviton exchanges, similar to the methods that had worked so well for quantum electrodynamics. The end result of this process would be an expression for the action of spacetime, to some level of approximation anyway, which could be used, in the classical limit (i.e., letting Planck's constant go to zero), to derive a field equation by the same route that Hilbert had used in 1915 (which I referred to in an earlier post).
Of course there are an infinite number of terms in the perturbation expansion, but remarkably, in the case of gravity, it turned out that there was a way to calculate the sum of all of them, which converged to a finite answer, which, remarkably, turned out to be the *same* action that Hilbert had calculated in 1915! So basically, the theory of a massless spin-two field on flat Minkowski spacetime turns out to be GR, at least in the classical limit. But there are two key points about this:
(1) The flat "background" spacetime is unobservable: the actual, physical spacetime (meaning, the actual physical metric that determines proper times and proper distances) is curved, just as in the standard interpretation of GR. This is why this "field on flat spacetime" model is called an "interpretation" of GR instead of a different theory: it makes exactly the same predictions for all experiments as the "curved spacetime" model.
(2) The assumption of a flat background spacetime restricts the possible solutions in a way that the standard curved spacetime model of GR does not. For example, asymptotically flat solutions, such as the Schwarzschild spacetime, are allowed. But it does not, as I understand it, allow solutions such as the FRW spacetime, at least in the k = 1 and k = -1 cases (I'm not sure whether the k = 0 case would be allowed--it does have flat spatial slices, but conformally it doesn't look the same as Minkowski spacetime). So even though the field equation is the same, the underlying assumptions of the flat spacetime model are more restrictive and exclude solutions which are certainly relevant in physics, and to our discussion here.
In this thread I've been talking entirely within the curved spacetime model, since that's the standard interpretation, and since the flat spacetime interpretation ends up making the same predictions anyway for experiments. But see below for some further comments specifically about Minkowski spacetime as a solution of the EFE.
JDoolin said:
But you reject the possibility that maybe space ISN'T stretching, and you reject the possibility that perhaps there was an era of non-uniform acceleration, and you reject the possibility that the galaxies might actually be moving apart. And you reject the possibility that Lorentz Transformations might actually work on the long range.
The comoving observers (not galaxies, necessarily--see next comment) *are* moving apart, in the sense that the proper distance between them is increasing with time. I'm not sure what you mean by "an era of non-uniform acceleration"; if you mean that the rate of expansion of the universe (the rate of change of the scale factor a(t) with t) may have changed in the past, it has--we know that by the curvature in the Hubble diagram that you mentioned in an earlier post. If you mean that various individual pieces of matter may have accelerated non-uniformly, against the background of FRW spacetime overall, I agree that certainly may have happened, but as I said before, these details are averaged out in the overall FRW models we've been discussing (though they are treated numerically in more detailed models). I talked about how transformations would work long range above.
JDoolin said:
So it is an available option to just set a(t)=1 and k=0, right? So Minkowski spacetime actually is a possible solution to the Einstein Field Equations? And then we don't have to throw away Special Relativity.
Minkowski spacetime *is* a solution to the EFE, but only if there is no matter-energy present--i.e., the stress-energy tensor is zero identically. That isn't true of the universe, and the FRW solutions to the EFE are valid in the presence of matter-energy (non-zero stress-energy tensor). In the presence of matter, we can't set a(t) = 1 and k = 0 by fiat; we have to work out the dynamics and see. When we do that, we find that a(t) must change with time, and that there are three possible values for k, and which one actually holds for our universe is something we have to determine by measuring the overall density of matter-energy in the universe, the curvature of the Hubble diagram, etc.
JDoolin said:
Ah, I see. Yes, of course, if we have comoving observers, then of course, they would all share the same proper time. But it is one thing to define a family of observers moving along those parallel worldlines. It is quite another to claim that the galaxies in the real universe are a family of observers moving along those worldlines.
I agree, and I don't think I've claimed the latter, only the former. Individual galaxies, galaxy clusters, etc. may be moving with respect to the cosmological coordinates. The assumption of a perfect fluid on a cosmological scale allows that, as long as the motions average out to zero, just as with the molecules in an ordinary fluid.
JDoolin said:
I'm sorry. Unintentionally, I've been switching back and forth between two ideas, and now there are three. The third idea is what you are explaining, that a set of comoving observers share a proper time, and that proper time is the same as their coordinate time. That's valid. The first idea is that those comoving observers are the galaxies in the real universe, who only appear to be moving apart because of the stretching of space. (That's wierd, but not where my argument was coming from.) What I was thinking about were galaxies moving apart from each other, with real recessional velocities, whose proper times were all different. In this environment, it would be ridiculous to simply set proper time equal to coordinate time, because the galaxies wouldn't be comoving.
If individual galaxies are not "comoving" (if they are changing their spatial "location" in cosmological coordinates with time), then their proper times will *not* be directly related to coordinate time. That's quite true. The "comoving" observers are abstractions, and there may not be any actual observers in the actual universe who are exactly "comoving" in this sense. However, the condition for determining whether an observer is "comoving" (do they see the universe, for example the CMBR, as isotropic) is quite clear and physically realizable.
JDoolin said:
One thing that I think we have established is that the large scale curvature, if it occurs at all, occurs at a level that is almost imperceptible up to a scale of at least a billion light years, and a billion years. Yet no one will entertain the idea that the large scale curvature actually is null; that a(t)=1 and k=0; that is, that the universe actually is, on the large scale, Minkowski.
It seems to me like this should be a starting point. That we should be willing to explore this simplest of possible options, and see what the actual expectations would be.
As I noted above, Minkowski spacetime is only a solution of the EFE if there is no matter-energy present--if the stress-energy tensor is zero. So the actual universe *cannot* be a Minkowski spacetime. That's why we are forced to consider models that are more complicated than Minkowski spacetime. As Einstein said, "Make everything as simple as possible--but not simpler."