Rade
"Time" is that which is intermediate between "moments"--each "momemt" is outside "time".Tosh said:Each moment is a temporary physical object...is that ok?
"Time" is that which is intermediate between "moments"--each "momemt" is outside "time".Tosh said:Each moment is a temporary physical object...is that ok?
Rade said:"Time" is that which is intermediate between "moments"--each "momemt" is outside "time".
Doctordick said:Hi Anssi, I am sorry I confused you. Sometimes I write a lot without realizing the various ways what I write can be taken; to paraphrase an old cliche, there are more ways to misinterpret what is being said than is dreamt of in your philosophy (which is really the essence of our conversation and I, of all people, should remember that). It is no fault of yours but you have missed intended central point of my ramblings.
The essence of magic is the misdirection of attention and physics has much to do with magic (it makes a lot of sense unless you happen to question something they can not answer). It is often very easy to miss a simple point simply because other issues catch your attention so I perhaps shouldn't have put so many varied issues in a single post; but it does tend to reveal those misunderstandings so I suppose I can be excused. I hadn't intended to send you off on a wild goose chase through google.
Could I ask what browser you are using? I am using “FireFox” in its default mode and the font in the LaTex expressions seems to be actually larger than the font in the main text. Maybe you have some preference set strangely. Sorry I can't help as I am quite ignorant of such things but quite surprised to hear of your difficulty. All the windows machines and “the Internet Explorer” seem to yield about the same result.
The only reason I even bring up quantum mechanics is that it is the most successful theory ever proposed and, by the time we finish, it will be quite obvious why it is so successful. What I am presenting to you is actually a logical deduction of quantum mechanics itself. Along with that, I will show you some subtle flaws in modern physics and their perspective on quantum mechanics.
By the way, the single most significant question asked by most scientists is, “where do we go from here?” That question makes the implicit assumption that “where we are” is significant. That is not the question I ask; I simply ask, where should we be going? What is important about the difference is that “where we are” can have no bearing on the answer; the answer must be universal.
Siah said:What is the difference between the 'moment' and the 'intermediate'?
If by, “how we have chosen to describe reality thus far”, you mean your world view, then you understand exactly what I meant.AnssiH said:You mean, we shouldn't burden ourselves unnecessarily by how we have chosen to describe reality thus far?
Are 'moments' composed of time? If not, what are they composed of?Rade said:As I see it, "time" is defined by "moments", time is not composed of moments, thus "moments" are outside of time but are the bounds of time,
NO, moments are not composed of time, moments are an "attribute" of time. An attribute is something that is not the entity itself, yet the entity and attribute are not two different things. A "moment" as an attribute of "time" is what can be separated only mentally from time--as opposed to a "part" which can be materially separated from the whole. It is not possible to have a concept of "moment" without a concept of "time", nor a concept of "time" without a concept of "moment". Moments are like electrons, they are "composed" of themselves. Moments, like all attributes of entities, are indivisible. Moments are the "now", the "present". Moments are the limit of the "past" and "future"--the "before" and "after". Moments are infinite in number.Siah said:Are 'moments' composed of time? If not, what are they composed of?
Rade said:NO, moments are not composed of time, moments are an "attribute" of time. An attribute is something that is not the entity itself, yet the entity and attribute are not two different things. A "moment" as an attribute of "time" is what can be separated only mentally from time--as opposed to a "part" which can be materially separated from the whole. It is not possible to have a concept of "moment" without a concept of "time", nor a concept of "time" without a concept of "moment". Moments are like electrons, they are "composed" of themselves. Moments, like all attributes of entities, are indivisible. Moments are the "now", the "present". Moments are the limit of the "past" and "future"--the "before" and "after". Moments are infinite in number.
Doctordick said:If by, “how we have chosen to describe reality thus far”, you mean your world view, then you understand exactly what I meant.
There are a few other minor details which will have to be cleared up sooner or later but for the moment, I would like to get over to that symmetry issue as I think you understand enough of my attack to understand it. At the moment, I have defined the knowledge on which any explanation must depend as equivalent to a set of points in an (x, tau, t) space: i.e., a collection of numbers associated with each t index which I have referred to as B(t). Any explanation can be seen as a function of those indices (the explanation yielding a specific expectation for that set of indices at time t. The output of that function is a probability and may be written
P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,x_3,\tau_3,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)
Now, the thoughts we need to go through here are subtle and easy to confuse but I think you have the comprehension to follow them. Suppose someone discovers a flaw free solution to the problem represented by some given collection of ontological elements. That means that their solution assigns meanings to those indices used in P. But, if we want to understand his solution, we need enough information to deduce the meanings he has attached to those indices. It is our problem to uncover his solution from what we come to know of the patterns in his assignment of indices. The point being that the solution (which has to contain the definitions of the underlying ontological elements) arises from patterns in the assigned indices. And the end result is to yield a function of those indices which is the exact probability assigned to that particular collection implied by that explanation.
But the indices are mere labels for those ontological elements. If we were to create a new problem by merely adding a number a to every index, the problem is not really changed in any way. Exactly the same explanation can be deduced from that second set of indices and it follows directly that
P(x_1+a,\tau_1+a,x_2+a,\tau_2+a,x_3+a,\tau_3+a,\cdots,x_n+a,\tau_n+a,t)
must yield exactly the same probability. That leads to a very interesting equation.
P(x_1+a,\tau_1+a,x_2+a,\tau_2+a,\cdots,x_n+a,\tau_n+a,t)-P(x_1+b,\tau_1+b,x_2+a,\tau_2+b,\cdots,x_n+b,\tau_n+b,t)=0
Simple division by (a-b) and taking the limit as that difference goes to zero makes that equation identical to the definition of a derivative. It follows that all flaw free explanations must obey the equation.
\frac{d}{da}P(x_1+a,\tau_1+a,x_2+a,\tau_2+a,x_3+a,\tau_3+a,\cdots,x_n+a,\tau_n+a,t)=0
Let me know if you have any problems with that.
Rade said:NO, moments are not composed of time, moments are an "attribute" of time. An attribute is something that is not the entity itself, yet the entity and attribute are not two different things. A "moment" as an attribute of "time" is what can be separated only mentally from time--as opposed to a "part" which can be materially separated from the whole. It is not possible to have a concept of "moment" without a concept of "time", nor a concept of "time" without a concept of "moment". Moments are like electrons, they are "composed" of themselves. Moments, like all attributes of entities, are indivisible. Moments are the "now", the "present". Moments are the limit of the "past" and "future"--the "before" and "after". Moments are infinite in number.
No, this is not how I see it. Moments do not have a "time-span"--moments are not divisible, thus no span concept exists for moments. To be "between" logically requires a concept of three. Suppose two moments (A) and (D) at the present, the now. "Time" (B ---> C) is that which is intermediate between the moments, time is neither within A nor D as the present, A and D are limits of time (B----> C). So you see the concept of three--this is what I mean when I say "time is intermediate between moments": (A) | (B ---> C) | (D).Siah said:I am trying to clarify this earlier statement:
"Time is that which is intermediate between moments"
You say 'moments are an "attribute" of time. As I understand it you are saying that moments have a time-span. Is this correct?
The equation is a direct consequence of “symmetry”. The addition of a to every term in a collection of reference numbers is essentially what is normally referred to as a “shift symmetry”. With regard to symmetry, I think I already gave you a link to a post I made to “saviormachine” a couple of years ago (post number 696 in the “Can everything be reduced to physics” thread.”) That post, selfAdjoint’s response to it (immediately below that one) and my response to selfAdjoint’s (post number 703) should be read very carefully before googling around. I will paste one quote which I think is the central issue here.AnssiH said:Well, how would you put it, what does this say about "symmetry"?
What I feel everyone seems to miss is the fact that there exists no proof which yields any information which is not embedded in the axioms on which the proof is based.[/color] In fact, that comment expresses the fundamental nature of a proof! In my opinion, the fundamental underpinning of Noether’s proof is the simple fact that any symmetry can be seen as equivalent to the definition of a specific differential: i.e., in a very real sense, Noether’s theorem is true by definition as are all proofs.Doctordick said:My interest concerns an aspect of symmetry very seldom brought to light. For the benefit of others, I will comment that the consequences of symmetry are fundamental to any study of mathematical physics. The relationship between symmetries and conserved quantities was laid out in detail through a theorem proved by http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Noether_Emmy.html sometime around 1915. The essence of the proof can be found on [URL='https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/author/john-baez/']John Baez's web site[/URL]. This is fundamental physics accepted by everyone. The problem is that very few students think about the underpinnings of the circumstance but rather just learn to use it.![]()
Doctordick said:Our first grandchild (we thought we would never get one) will be one year old Sunday and she can sure wear out an old man. She’s not quite walking yet (not by herself anyway) and wants to walk everywhere holding on to your finger (which requires me to walk bent over).
Doctordick said:What I feel everyone seems to miss is the fact that there exists no proof which yields any information which is not embedded in the axioms on which the proof is based.[/color] In fact, that comment expresses the fundamental nature of a proof! In my opinion, the fundamental underpinning of Noether’s proof is the simple fact that any symmetry can be seen as equivalent to the definition of a specific differential
I was somewhat sloppy when I wrote my last post because the issue was to get you to think about the impact of shift symmetry in ontological labels. It is very interesting to note that x, tau and t are all totally independent collections of indices (the fact that we have laid them out as positions in a three dimensional Euclidean space says that shift symmetry is applicable to each dimension independently). In other words, that equation can actually be divided into three independent equations.
\frac{d}{da}P(x_1+a,\tau_1,x_2+a,\tau_2,x_3+a,\tau_3,\cdots,x_n+a,\tau_n,t)=0
\frac{d}{da}P(x_1,\tau_1+a,x_2,\tau_2+a,x_3,\tau_3+a,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n+a,t)=0
\frac{d}{da}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,x_3,\tau_3,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t+a)=0
I think you should find that quite satisfactory.
The next step involves what is called “partial” differentiation. A partial differential is defined on functions of more than one variable (note that above we are looking at the probability as a function of one variable: i.e., only a is being presumed to change; all other variable being seen as a simple set of constants). When one has multiple variables, one can define a thing called the “partial” derivative. A partial derivative is the derivative with respect to one of those variables under the constraint that none of the other variables change (all other variables are presumed to be unchanging). Essentially, the equations above can be seen as partials with respect to a except for one fact: the probability P is not being expressed as a function of “a”. That is to say, “a” is not technically an argument of P.
On the other hand, the equation does say something about how the other arguments must change with respect to one another. In order to deduce the correct implied relationship, one needs to understand one simple property of partial derivatives. The property that I am referring to is often called “the chain rule of partial differentiation’. I googled “the definition of the chain rule of partial differentiation” and got a bunch of hits on “by use of the definition of the chain rule of partial differentiation …” which seems pretty worthless with regard to exactly what it is. If you know what it is, thank the lord.
Doctordick said:Paul gives case 1 as the problem of computing dz/dt when z is given as a function of x = g(t) and y =h(t) or, to put it exactly as he states it, Case 1: z=f(x,y), x=g(t), y=h(t) and compute dz/dt).
What we want to do is compute is dP/da, which we know must vanish, but is expressed in terms of the reference labels of our valid ontological elements. We have established that the probability of a specific set of labels is given by an expression of the form,
Probability= P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,x_3,\tau_3,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)
or, just as reasonably
Probability= P(z_1,\tau_1,z_2,\tau_2,z_3,\tau_3,\cdots,z_n,\tau_n,t)
where our shift symmetry has resulted in the fact that those arguments, when expressed as functions of x and a are given by
z_1=x_1+a, z_2=x_2+a, z_3=x_3+a,\cdots, z_n=x_n+a.
With regard to our representation that dP/da vanishes, we can apply the example given by Paul,
\frac{dz}{dt}=\frac{\partial f}{\partial x}\frac{dx}{dt}+\frac{\partial f}{\partial y}\frac{dy}{dx}
as, in our case, equivalent to
\frac{dP}{da}=\sum_{i=1}^{i=n}\frac{\partial P}{\partial z_i}\frac{dz_i}{da};
however, in our case,
\frac{dz_1}{da}=\frac{dz_2}{da}=\frac{dz_3}{da}=\cdots=\frac{dz_n}{da}=1.
which yields the final result that
\frac{dP}{da}=\sum_{i=1}^{i=n}\frac{\partial}{\partial z_i}P = 0
when the x arguments of P are symbolized by z. But z is just a letter used to represent those arguments; one can not change the truth of the equation by changing the name of the variable. This same argument can be applied to the other independent arguments of P, yielding, in place of the differential expressions in post 462, the following three differential constraints.
\sum_{i=0}^{i=n}\frac{\partial}{\partial x_i}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
\sum_{i=0}^{i=n}\frac{\partial}{\partial \tau_i}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
and
\frac{\partial}{\partial t}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
which has utterly no mention of the shift parameter a.
Don’t worry about it.AnssiH said:Sorry for being so slow to reply again.
In is interesting to note that this exchange concerns exactly what I am talking about: i.e., getting on the other side of that barrier. Tarika is using “%” for exactly the reason I am using numerical labels. The only reason I am using “numerical labels” is that there are a lot more of them then there are things like %, #, @, &, etc. Plus that, I have the advantage that there exists a world of internally self consistent defined operations on those numerical labels. That is, I don’t have to explain each and every manipulation I want to perform on the labels. (See Russell’s works on definition of mathematics.) You can google the phrase and get enough stuff to keep anyone busy for years. The only reason I bring it up is that he was very much interested in defining mathematics from “ground zero”. That is exactly the problem which constitutes the essential nature of the barrier being referred to above.Anssi said:Heh, isn't it interesting to try to force yourself through this barrier?
:) At least it gives us a better understanding about how there really is a barrier there, doesn't it?
Yeah, I knew that was going to be a problem; but I think we are beginning to clear up the true depth of the difficulty. I think we can handle it.AnssiH said:I am having a summer vacation and was away for couple of days, and on top of that it takes me a while to figure out all the math concepts since I need to study them before I understand what is being said :)
The capital sigma is used as a shorthand notation to represent a sum. The definitions of i given above and below the sigma tell you the starting value of i and the ending value of i. The term to be summed has an i reference in it which tells you how to construct the ith term in that sum. If you look at Paul’s example (for Case 1) you will see that the original function was a function of two variables and that his “total derivative”, dz/dt, is given by a sum of two terms: a partial with respect with each of those two variables times the “total derivative of each variable with respect to t. (“Total derivative” is the term used for what was originally defined to be “a derivative” so as to contrast it with the idea of a “partial derivative”). In our case, we have n arguments subject to our shift parameter "a" so our total derivative consists of a sum of n terms, one partial for each term in the function (times the respective total derivative).AnssiH said:Here I'm starting to have some troubles understanding what is being said. What is meant with \sum_{i=1}^{i=n} ? Something about this applying to every entry in the table?
Our shift symmetry can be seen as a simple change in variables where each x has been replaced by a related z where each z has been defined by adding a to the respective x.AnssiH said:I understood we are using z_i to express x_i+a, but I don't understand how \frac{dz_1}{da}=1
Exactly right except for one thing. We haven’t proven dP/da = zero here; what we have done is shown how that result (as you say “established earlier”) is totally equivalent to the assertion that the sum over all partials with respect to each argument must vanish.AnssiH said:Hmmm, that final result \frac{dP}{da}= 0
Isn't it the same as was established earlier already? I.e. changing "a" will not change the probability P?
This says that every ontological element (valid or invalid) associated with “that explanation” has associated with it, another thing (a consequence of symbolic shift symmetry). If we have the function for the probability relationships and the numerical labels, we can deduce a proper label (numerical label) to be assigned to that ontological element. What is interesting is the fact that the sum over all those “deduced proper labels” must be zero. We are talking about here is a conserved quantity; the sum over all of them is unchanging though the individual quantities associated with each ontological element might very well change.AnssiH said:Hmm, how should I read these expressions...? That the probability doesn't change when we change... what? I hope you (or anyone) can clear up the things I am not getting :)
Don’t worry, we’ve survived it. We will be heading home this weekend. That’s the great thing about being grandparents; you can always go home when the strain begins to show (and believe me, it's beginning to show; I am looking forward to our own schedule and our own home). You can’t do that with your own kids.AnssiH said:Heh, don't break your back :) I also became an uncle couple months back, plus my two other sisters are just about to multiply as well :)
Doctordick said:Regarding “they are % and % is not a thing.
In is interesting to note that this exchange concerns exactly what I am talking about: i.e., getting on the other side of that barrier. Tarika is using “%” for exactly the reason I am using numerical labels.
Doctordick said:Yeah, I knew that was going to be a problem; but I think we are beginning to clear up the true depth of the difficulty. I think we can handle it.
The capital sigma is used as a shorthand notation to represent a sum. The definitions of i given above and below the sigma tell you the starting value of i and the ending value of i. The term to be summed has an i reference in it which tells you how to construct the ith term in that sum. If you look at Paul’s example (for Case 1) you will see that the original function was a function of two variables and that his “total derivative”, dz/dt, is given by a sum of two terms: a partial with respect with each of those two variables times the “total derivative of each variable with respect to t. (“Total derivative” is the term used for what was originally defined to be “a derivative” so as to contrast it with the idea of a “partial derivative”). In our case, we have n arguments subject to our shift parameter "a" so our total derivative consists of a sum of n terms, one partial for each term in the function (times the respective total derivative).
This defined operation (the thing called the partial derivative with respect to the given argument multiplied by the common derivative of the same argument with respect to a) is to be performed for every numerical label in the collection of labels which constitute the arguments of that probability function (the mathematical function which is to yield the probability that the specific set of labels will be in the table). The n different results which are obtained by performing that specific mathematical operation which (if we happen to know what the function looks like, will yield a new function for each chosen i) are to be added together.
The requirement that the shift of "a" cannot yield any change in that resultant expression yields a rule which the probability function can not violate. Putting it simply, if we did indeed know exactly the correct function for n-1 of those arguments, we could use that differential relationship to tell us exactly the appropriate relationship for the missing argument. This is a simple consequence of “self consistency” of the explanation.
Our shift symmetry can be seen as a simple change in variables where each x has been replaced by a related z where each z has been defined by adding a to the respective x.
z_1=x_1+a, z_2=x_2+a, z_3=x_3+a,\cdots, z_n=x_n+a.
In order to evaluate the sum expressing the total derivative of P with respect to a (the derivative which we deduced earlier must vanish) we need the total derivative of each z with respect to a. But each z is obtained from a by adding a to the appropriate x. This constraint (as a function of a) presumes there is no change in the base x (as it is a shift on all x’s). From this perspective, each z can be see as a constant x plus a; it follows that dx/da vanishs (x is not a function of a) and da/da is identically one by definition.
Exactly right except for one thing. We haven’t proven dP/da = zero here; what we have done is shown how that result (as you say “established earlier”) is totally equivalent to the assertion that the sum over all partials with respect to each argument must vanish.
We first proved that we could see any specific explanation of our “what is”, is “what is”[/color] table as a mathematical function which would yield the probability of seeing a specific entry in that table. Then we argued that shift symmetry required that the total derivative with respect to that shift to vanish. Now I have shown that that requirement is totally equivalent to requiring a specifically defined sum of partial derivatives of that probability function, with respect to those numerical labels (numerical labels which are defined by that explanation), to vanish.
This says that every ontological element (valid or invalid) associated with “that explanation” has associated with it, another thing (a consequence of symbolic shift symmetry). If we have the function for the probability relationships and the numerical labels, we can deduce a proper label (numerical label) to be assigned to that ontological element. What is interesting is the fact that the sum over all those “deduced proper labels” must be zero. We are talking about here is a conserved quantity; the sum over all of them is unchanging though the individual quantities associated with each ontological element might very well change.
What is somewhat more important is the fact that I have proved that such a function exists and that one achieves that function through the addition of “invalid ontological elements”. What you need to remember is that these “invalid ontological elements” are invalid, not because the yield incorrect answers regarding the information to be explained but rather because they are not actually among the ontological elements which constitute the information our explanation is to explain. They are instead, total figments of our imagination. That is to say that they are inventions; inventions created to provide us with the ability to say what can and can not be under the presumed rule our explanation implements (i.e., the rule being that F=0): i.e., they are ontological elements our explanation presumes exist. If our explanation is indeed flaw free, it will be totally consistent with the existence of these invalid ontological elements.Doctordick said:This means that the missing index can be seen as is a function of the other indices. Again, we may not know what that function is but we do know that the function must agree with our table. What this says is that there exists a mathematical function which will yield
(x,\tau)_n(t) = f((x,\tau)_1, (x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x.\tau)_{n-1},t)
It follows that the function F defined by
F((x,\tau)_1,(x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x,\tau)_n) = (x(t),\tau(t))_n - f((x,\tau)_1, (x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x.\tau)_{n-1},t) = 0
is a statement of the general constraint which guarantees that the entries conform to the given table. That is to say, this procedure yields a result which guarantees that there exists a mathematical function, the roots of which are exactly the entries to our "what is", is "what is"[/color] table. Clearly, it would be nice to know the structure of that function.
Doctordick said:Thank you Anssi. This is the first time I have ever gotten anyone (other than Paul Martin, who is a personal friend) this far along in my arguments. Everyone else drops out long before we get to this point. We only have a small number of steps to complete my deduction. Remember post number 426 on this thread? It was there that I pointed out that there had to exist a set of invalid ontological elements which would guarantee that a function existed who's roots would yield that exactly that "what is", is "what is"[/color] table.
What is somewhat more important is the fact that I have proved that such a function exists and that one achieves that function through the addition of “invalid ontological elements”. What you need to remember is that these “invalid ontological elements” are invalid, not because the yield incorrect answers regarding the information to be explained but rather because they are not actually among the ontological elements which constitute the information our explanation is to explain. They are instead, total figments of our imagination. That is to say that they are inventions; inventions created to provide us with the ability to say what can and can not be under the presumed rule our explanation implements (i.e., the rule being that F=0): i.e., they are ontological elements our explanation presumes exist. If our explanation is indeed flaw free, it will be totally consistent with the existence of these invalid ontological elements.
What is really profound about this realization is the fact that it implies there exists a fundamental duality: the rule and what is presumed to exist are exchangeable concepts. That is to say, what the rule has to be is a function of what is presumed to exist: it is possible to exchange one for the other so long as one maintains some complex internal relationships. It turns out this is exactly the freedom which allows us construct a world view consistent with what we know; without this freedom the problem of “explaining the universe” could not be accomplished.
Another way to state the circumstance is to point out that the “explanation of reality” is actually a rather complex data compression mechanism. One's best bet for the future is very simply: one's best expectations are given by how much the surrounding circumstances resemble something already experienced.
But let's get back to this F=0 rule. There exists a rather simple function which can totally fulfill the need required here. That function is the Dirac delta function (google “Dirac delta function” for a good run down on its properties). The Dirac delta function is usually written as \delta(x) and is defined to be exactly zero so long as x is not equal to zero; however, it also satisfies the relationship:
\int_{-\infty}^{+\infty}\delta(x)dx= 1.
Clearly, since it is exactly zero everywhere except when x=0, it must be positive infinity at x=0. It is that property which makes it so valuable as a universal F=0 function. First, it is a very simple function and is quite well defined and well understood. Second, as it is only positive, the sum indicated below will be infinite if any two labels are identical (have exactly the same x, tau numerical label).
\sum_{i \neq j}\delta(x_i -x_j)\delta(\tau_i -\tau_j) = 0,
It is thus a fact that the equation will constrain all labels to be different and any specific collection of labels can be reproduced by the simple act of adding “invalid ontological elements” until all the wrong answers are eliminated. Now that sounds like an insane suggestion; however, it's really not as insane as it sounds and it ends up yielding an extremely valuable representation which I will show to you in my next post (after I have read your response to this post).
Sorry I was so slow to respond but I needed time to decide exactly how I was going to present this last step as it clearly seems like an rather extreme move to make even if it is true.
Well, since it is pretty well based on what I am showing you right now, I think it will have to be put off until you understand the essence of this presentation.AnssiH said:Yeah, we have to discuss your ideas about practical AI at some point.
As I said, it's really not as insane as it sounds. Stop and think about vacuum polarization: i.e., the problems with conceiving of the vacuum as “absolutely empty” thing, impossible to interact with. The existence of a “pure” vacuum in the sense originally put forth by scientists seems very much to be in conflict with modern physics; if there is no such thing as an “empty spot” doesn't that imply every location is full of something? I only make that comment to point out that one cannot count the idea as insane if one has any faith in modern science. However, note that I use it as a collection of “invalid ontological elements” because of its ability to yield all possible observed results, not because modern science has come to the conclusion that it is correct (I like deduction, not induction). (By the way, that “observed result” would be any possible collection of ontological elements we need to explain: i.e., it's a very powerful tool.)AnssiH said:That sounds insane alright!
I further showed how viewing that probability as a square of some function (the vector dot product) provided a valuable consequence: i.e., I introduced a mechanism for guaranteeing that the constraints embodied in the concept of probability need no longer be extraneous[/color] constraints. Under my representation, they are instead embodied in the representation without constraining the remaining possibilities in any way! This is the central issue behind the representationDoctordick said:This same argument can be applied to the other independent arguments of P, yielding, in place of the differential expressions in post 462, the following three differential constraints.
\sum_{i=0}^{i=n}\frac{\partial}{\partial x_i}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
\sum_{i=0}^{i=n}\frac{\partial}{\partial \tau_i}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
and
\frac{\partial}{\partial t}P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=0
which has utterly no mention of the shift parameter a.
Everybody is slow when they are not sure what should be done.AnssiH said:Good thing I'm not the only slow one here :)
Again you make it quite clear that you did not follow my presentation. My equation says absolutely nothing about reality. It speaks entirely to the problem of interpreting reality. My source data is taken to be explicitly uncorrelated in any manner (the ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] information table). What I show is that absolutely any flaw-free explanation of anything can, through the presumption of implied ontological elements (and there are presumptions made unconsciously in any attempt to understand anything), can always be interpreted in a manner such as it will obey my fundamental equation.Rade said:...represents the "implicate order" of Bohm, (e.g., the veiled underlying order that governs the universe) ?
Doctordick said:My equation says absolutely nothing about reality. It speaks entirely to the problem of interpreting reality
I am sorry I have upset you; that was not my intention. You simply have no idea of the difference between an explanation and the constraints on such; they are actually rather different concepts.Rade said:Good gravy--do you not see the contradiction of your words. You cannot on the one hand say that your equation "says nothing about reality" (absolutely even you say), and then on the other hand claim "it speaks to interpreting reality". Well good Dr. when you say you "interprete reality" you most clearly do say "some"thing" about reality.
I am very sorry I tried a civil attempt at communication with you, it is clear you have absolutely no idea what I was asking in my question about Bohm.
Doctordick said:At this point, there are three paths open to us. One, we could spend some time discussing anything underlying my deduction which seems shaky to you; two, I could show the details of those solutions I spoke of; or three, we could talk about the philosophical implications of my discovery.
Doctordick said:This means that the missing index can be seen as is a function of the other indices. Again, we may not know what that function is but we do know that the function must agree with our table. What this says is that there exists a mathematical function which will yield
(x,\tau)_n(t) = f((x,\tau)_1, (x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x.\tau)_{n-1},t)
It follows that the function F defined by
F((x,\tau)_1,(x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x,\tau)_n) = (x(t),\tau(t))_n - f((x,\tau)_1, (x,\tau)_2, \cdots, (x.\tau)_{n-1},t) = 0
is a statement of the general constraint which guarantees that the entries conform to the given table. That is to say, this procedure yields a result which guarantees that there exists a mathematical function, the roots of which are exactly the entries to our "what is", is "what is" table. Clearly, it would be nice to know the structure of that function.
Clearly, since it is exactly zero everywhere except when x=0, it must be positive infinity at x=0. It is that property which makes it so valuable as a universal F=0 function. First, it is a very simple function and is quite well defined and well understood. Second, as it is only positive, the sum indicated below will be infinite if any two labels are identical (have exactly the same x, tau numerical label).
\sum_{i \neq j}\delta(x_i -x_j)\delta(\tau_i -\tau_j) = 0,
It is thus a fact that the equation will constrain all labels to be different and any specific collection of labels can be reproduced by the simple act of adding “invalid ontological elements” until all the wrong answers are eliminated.
As I said, it's really not as insane as it sounds. Stop and think about vacuum polarization: i.e., the problems with conceiving of the vacuum as “absolutely empty” thing, impossible to interact with. The existence of a “pure” vacuum in the sense originally put forth by scientists seems very much to be in conflict with modern physics; if there is no such thing as an “empty spot” doesn't that imply every location is full of something?
I further showed how viewing that probability as a square of some function (the vector dot product) provided a valuable consequence: i.e., I introduced a mechanism for guaranteeing that the constraints embodied in the concept of probability need no longer be extraneous[/color] constraints. Under my representation, they are instead embodied in the representation without constraining the remaining possibilities in any way! This is the central issue behind the representation
P(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)=\vec{\Psi}^{\dagger}(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)\cdot\vec{\Psi}(x_1,\tau_1,x_2,\tau_2,\cdots,x_n,\tau_n,t)dV
Note that the "\dagger” is there solely to bring the representation closer to the common Schrödinger representation of quantum mechanics: i.e., allowing the components of that indicated vector to be “complex” is essentially adding nothing which could not just as easily be represented by twice as many “real” components in the vector nature of \vec{\Psi}. The fact that the number of components must be even is of no account at all when seen from the perspective of the availability of invalid ontological elements (if that really needs clarification, I will clarify it).
I think we need to go back to that post where I first began adding “invalid ontological elements”. The fact that we can add these invalid ontological elements gives us the power to organize or represent that ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] table in a form which allows for easy deduction. In that post, I said I wanted to add three different kinds of “invalid ontological elements”, each to serve a particular purpose. You need to understand exactly why those elements are being added and how the addition achieves the result desired.AnssiH said:Actually, let me get back to that older quote about recovering missing indices. I don't know if the answers are supposed to be obvious to me but they are not :) Hopefully you can pick up what am I missing.
One could continue the process of adding “invalid ontological elements” in order to define a function which would yield two missing indices but I see no purpose to such an extension. My purpose was to prove that one could always achieve a circumstance (by adding invalid ontological elements) such that the rule which determined what reference numbers existed in the ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] table consisted of “those entries are the roots of the function F”: i.e., the rule can be written asAnssiH said:Is this valid only when there is only 1 missing index, or is it valid for larger number of missing indices?
It says that the only acceptable reference numbers for the ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] table are roots of some function “F”. Or rather, that there always exists a collection of “invalid ontological elements” such that the rule as to what reference numbers can be seen in that table are given by the solutions to some equation expressed in the form F=0.AnssiH said:I took it on faith that the above expression "guarantees that there exists a mathematical function, the roots of which are exactly the entires...", but I don't fully grasp what that expression says.
In a sense you are right; but the issue is not really to test the function F as we do not have it. Before you can actually have that function, you have to have the solution to the problem. That is F can not be defined until the epistemological construct which explains that ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] table is known (it is that explanation which specifies those numerical references). What is important here is that, if I am given a set of “valid ontological elements” there always exists a set of “invalid ontological elements” which together with a rule F=0 will yield exactly those “valid ontological elements” (along with those presumed “invalid ontological elements”). That is, it is always possible to construct a flaw-free epistemological construct where the only rule is “F=0” and the entire problem is reduced to “what exists”. This is a much simpler problem than being confronted with two apparently different issues to solve: “What exists?” and “What are the rules?”.AnssiH said:The part that I thought I understood is that it would be possible to recover one missing index from a specific B, if we had a function that gave "0" with the input of the correct (full) set of indices of that B. So we could just test which index gave a 0. That was the idea with this?
You appear to understand what I am saying; however, it is possible that you are stepping off trying to construct a epistemological solution which conforms to the circumstance I have laid out. That, you shouldn't be trying to do. Remember, what I have laid out must be capable of representing all possible epistemological constructs. That is a pretty extensive field and it would be a mistake to presume that simple answers exist. I have proved that the procedure I described could be accomplished in principal since the number of elements being referred is finite; however, their number could easily exceed any mechanical equipment we might envisage to carry out such a procedure. I certainly have not proved any such thing could actually be done in one's life time; even with the simplest problem. All I have shown is that the process can be done “in principal”.AnssiH said:I suppose the expression essentially means we take a specific B, and its every X is compared with every other X and every tau is compared with every other tau. So that we'll see if any of them are the same. Or in other words, we are simply labeling every entry as unique?
First of all, the Dirac delta function does not make every single entry unique, all it does is yield an infinite result when any two are the same. It should be clear that, if there exists a finite set of “invalid ontological elements” which will make the rule “F=0” yield both the “valid ontological elements and those we added (providing us with that flaw-free epistemological solution), we can certainly add a bunch more without bothering that solution. All we need do is recognize them as “presumed” and not necessarily part of that valid ”what is”, is “what is”[/color] table.AnssiH said:I am missing, why do we need a dirac delta function to make every single entry unique?
That seems to me to be a pretty straight forward issue. The only real problem is that the number of references has now gone to infinity and we can no longer argue things from a “finite” perspective. That introduces some subtle problems which require additional mathematics to handle. Other than that, I think my statement is rather incontrovertible.Doctordick said:It is thus a fact that the equation will constrain all labels to be different and any specific collection of labels can be reproduced by the simple act of adding “invalid ontological elements” until all the wrong answers are eliminated.
Let me start with the relationship between Psi and our probability. The issue is the fact that probability is defined to be bounded by zero and one. As a function, that makes P a rather special function. Note that, in my presentation, I don't want to make any limitations on the possibilities at all.[/color] It follows that I need to work with a totally unconstrained function: i.e., the solution to our problem must be left to be ANYTHING[/color]. Now, “any[/color] mathematical function” is a pretty obvious entity: it's arguments are a collection of numbers and it's output is a collection of numbers. A “mathematical function” is a method from getting from the first to the second, “PERIOD”[/color], no other constraints! If we are to include all possibilities, that is about all we can say about the solution to our problem, the possible epistemological construct.AnssiH said:Yeah I think some things need clarification at least. I don't know what the \dagger means. I am not familiar with Schrödinger representation (as I am not familiar with mathematical representation of much of anything :)
If we go to representing the components of the vector function Psi as complex numbers, it is completely equivalent to using two components for each normally real component so, in a sense we are limiting our consideration to functions with a even number of components. This isn't really troublesome as, if the correct answer turns out to be a function with an odd number of components, it can just as well be seen as a function of an even number where one of the components is always zero. All this move really does is make the notation appear to be similar to Schrödinger's.AnssiH said:I may have forgotten something but, why does the number of components have to be even?
I have read the thread and their comments are pretty typical of physicists I have run across in the past. As far as interacting with professional physicists is concerned, I have done plenty of that in my life time. I have earned a Ph.D. in theoretical physics from a reputable university and had plenty of interactions with the academy during that period. At that time (the early sixties) the position of theoretical physicists was that the big problem was not understanding the universe (they already understood it all) the big problem was how to calculate solutions to their equations. As I have said somewhere else, Richard Feynman got a Nobel Prize for developing a notation for keeping track of terms in an expansion of an infinite series (which everyone believed to be correct ). To quote Caltech themselves, http://pr.caltech.edu/events/caltech_nobel/ And I do not intend any insult to Richard in any way. In fact, I talked to him in 86 and he said he would like to follow my thoughts as soon as he finished with that NASA accident (he was the chairman of the investigating committee). Next thing I heard, he had died of cancer (I finally get an intelligent educated person to talk to me and he ups an dies; just my luck).Rade said:In response to a comment you made in post # 478 above, I started a thread in quantum theory section of forum, and I see that you will have to provide clarification of your thoughts. I think this a good opportunity for you to interact with professional physicists about your philosophy here presented--see here if you have an interest:
At least he finds my rebellion “understandable” though he clearly does not think my thoughts are worth thinking about.jostpuur said:I'll put it this way: "Physicists are usually not interested in philosophy, they are interested in calculating." That is something that many will probably agree with, and if Doctordick is criticizing it, it is understandable, although I'm not convinced that he himself would be improving anything.
Yeah, sure they are interested; as long as it comes from a recognized authority and not a rebellious skeptic of their great accomplishments.country boy said:But every physicist I know is interested in the possibility that QM and other aspects of modern physics might be derivable from more fundamental, as yet unrecognized, principles.
Yeah, there is a lot of truth to that all right. When it comes to serious thought, most people have an intention span of about two minutes. They want “simple minded” answers to their questions, not simple answers. One should recognize that Newton's theories are quite simple but they are not at all “simple minded”. There is a great difference between “simple " and "simpleminded”.Hurkyl said:... you run the risk of losing some of your audience if they have to do a lot of theoretical work before they can actually compute anything.
That is a succinct statement of the academies position on the issue. As I have said many times, physicists say what I am doing is philosophy and they have no interest in it; philosophers say what I am doing is mathematics and they have no interest in it and mathematicians say what I am doing is physics and they have no interest in it. All I am looking for is people who are interested in thinking; a very rare breed indeed.Llewlyn said:Please note that all physics is put in axiomatic form.
Doctordick said:Tell your friends to start with post #211 on this thread
What I am saying is that understanding implies it is possible to predict expectations for information not known; the explanation constitutes a method which provides one with those rational expectations for unknown information consistent with what is known
The procedure we follow differs in one remarkable way from the manner that has in the past been followed in setting up physical theories. Normally one starts by establishing a mathematical formalism, setting up a set of equations, and then one tries to append an interpretation to it. This is a very difficult problem; historically it has affected not only statistics and statistical physics – what is the meaning of probabilities and of entropy – but also quantum theory – what is the meaning of wave functions and amplitudes. The issue of whether the proposed interpretation is unique, or even whether it is allowed, always remains a legitimate objection and a point of controversy.
Here we proceed in the opposite order, we first decide what we are talking about and what we want to accomplish, and only afterwards we design the ap- apropriate mathematical formalism. The advantage is that the issue of meaning never arises.
The Foundations of Physical Reality said:The issue of truth by definition rests on two very straight forward points:
(1.) we either agree on our definitions or communication is impossible and
(2.) no acceptable definition can contain internal contradictions.
The Foundations of Physical Reality said:Thus, the problem becomes one of constructing a rational model of a totally unknown universe given nothing but a totally undefined stream of data which has been transcribed by a totally undefined process.
The Foundations of Physical Reality said:As it is my intention to make no assumptions whatsoever, even the smallest assumption becomes a hole which could possibly sink the whole structure. As I do not claim perfection, errors certainly exist within this treatise. None the less, I claim the attack will be shown to be extremely powerful.
The Foundations of Physical Reality said:Thus, the problem becomes one of constructing a rational model of a totally unknown universe given nothing but a totally undefined stream of data which has been transcribed by a totally undefined process.
(Excuse me for correcting your spelling; it's sort of a compulsion ingrained by my father years ago.) You are clearly misinterpreting what I am doing. I made no claim to understanding how human beings unconsciously solve the problem; all I said is that they obviously solve it on a regular basis which implies it is a solvable problem. Thus the fact that I have solved the problem bears little impact on how the average person does so. In fact, there are a lot of points to persuade one to accept the fact that they certainly do not use my method. In particular, we have the fact that no one (to my knowledge) uses that equation I derived and, secondly, their solutions are often ripe with errors. But they certainly are “solutions”, and dammed good ones at that (almost everyone agrees with “what is real”).Fra said:How do you picture an observer being exposed to this data stream? What happens when the observers memory is full, and runs out of memory for your constructions?
Thank you for your kindness to my compulsions.Fra said:( I don't mind if you want to spellcheck - go ahead )
I had no intention for you to take my comment as a rebuke; I was merely pointing out the source of your difficulty.Fra said:I am well aware that I may misinterpret your intentions, but that's what the questions are for.
The basic reference can be found http://home.jam.rr.com/dicksfiles/Explain/Explain.htmFra said:You somewhere (I forgot where) defined an "explanation" as a method for obtaining a expectation? This sounds interesting, but I am still not sure if you mean what I think you mean.
Essentially yes.Fra said:Question on definition of expectation: Do you with expectation mean like some probability in [frequentness?] interpretation, define on the current known fact? ie history or past, or whatever is part of your known facts?
What I am saying is that your explanation of something (no matter what that explanation is about) is the source of your expectations. If I understand your explanation, I will be able to estimate your expectations as a probability attached to the various possibilities. In particular, you need to recognize that the correctness of your expectations is not the issue here. The issue is defining exactly what “an explanation” is and, in my opinion, it is a mechanism for generating expectations. I am defining "an explanation", not "a good explanation". A good explanation would be one with few flaws. An explanation which yields expectations perfectly consistent with the known facts would be a "flaw-free" explanation (what we would all like to find).I will suggest that what an explanation does for information is that it provides expectations of subsets of that information. That is, it seems to me that if all the information is known, then any questions about the information can be answered (in fact, that could be regarded as the definition of "knowing"). On the other hand, if the information is understood (explainable), then questions about the information can be answered given only limited or incomplete knowledge of the underlying information: i.e., limited subsets of the information. What I am saying is that understanding implies it is possible to predict expectations for information not known; the explanation constitutes a method which provides one with those rational expectations for unknown information consistent with what is known.
Your expectations are whatever you expect. The easiest way to express your expectations in a precise mathematical way is to give the probabilities of various possibilities. Have you ever heard of the game “20 questions”? Think of your expectations as your answers to a game of “an infinite number of questions with yes/no answers”. A complete description of your expectations could consist of a probability distribution for your answers: i.e., a number bounded by zero and one for each and every question. If I understood your personal explanation of the pertinent information, I could use that explanation to create an estimate of those probabilities: i.e., I would know what to expect from you with regard to that subject (the pertinent information).Fra said:Or does expectation refer to the unknown? ie. that what you know, induce an expectation on the unknown? ie. future?
I would say that the idea includes both; the exact expectations are defined by probabilities zero and one, the educated guesses are represented by numbers elsewhere in the range.Fra said:If you _define_ a probability pretty much like some relative frequency on a given, fixed set of facts, then the "expectation" applied to that set is of course exact by definition? Is this what you mean?
Or do you suggest, that the expectation provides us with educated guesses in cases where we lack information?
Once again, you are clearly misinterpreting what I am doing. I am making no predictions of any kind; I am analyzing the problem of making predictions (estimating the probabilities your explanation should yield). Take a quick look at this response to Anssi.Fra said:You said somewhere I think that you make no predictions? But isn't an expectation a kind of prediction? I mean the expectation is not exact, it doesn't tell us what will happen, but it gives us a basis for bet placing - thus there are good and bad expectations. Do you somehow claim that your expectation is the optimum one?
We are talking about explanations here (epistemological constructs designed to explain reality). I am looking for logical constraints on those constructs. I take your use of the term “standard model” to imply you are misunderstanding what I am doing. When it comes to setting constraints on explanations, the “standard model” is, “it has to make sense”, a very vague and imprecise statement. Every professor I have ever heard define “an explanation” seldom does more than give a few example explanations and then comment something like “I'm not going to waste my time explaining things to you if you can't understand what an explanation is”. It appears to be an unexamined concept: i.e., what I am talking about is something no one looks at carefully.Fra said:Let me ask this: What is the benefit, someone would have, adapting your models, over someone that uses the standard model? Would they somehow be more "fit" (thinking of the analogy of natural selection here).
Doctordick said:To put it another way, knowing is having facts available to you (the facts come from the past, not the future) and understanding allows discrimination between good and bad answers (facts you might expect to become available to you in the future). Now the human race has become quite good at this discrimination since all we living things first crawled out of the sea. We are the undoubted leaders in the realm of "understanding" the world around us. And yet no one has come up with a good argument to dismiss the Solipsist position. The fact that we have come so far without being able to prove what is and what is not real should make it clear to you that understanding reality can not possibly require knowing what is real.This is why every serious scientist (I except myself of course[/color]) has vociferously argued against any rational consideration of the question. Their position is: if we don't know what's real, how can we possibly dream of understanding reality. They hold that we must assume we know what's real. You can see that position promulgated all over this forum! Why do you think they label me a crackpot?
![]()
Well, I was interested in answering the question “What can[/color] we know?” If you cannot answer that question, how can you have any direction to your attempts to understand reality. Again, in my opinion, the “standard approach” to understanding reality is a “guess and by golly” approach with little or no thought given to logical direction. I had proved the validity of my equation over ten years prior to unraveling the first solution to that equation. Prior to discovering a method of finding solutions, it just seemed reasonable to me that, if I could find a solution, that solution should have practical application. When I finally figured out how to solve it, I discovered practical realistic applications up the wazzo (so to speak). For the moment, why don't we not worry about that; we should first comprehend the defense of the definition and the deduction of the equation itself.Fra said:I am just trying to find a practical realistic application of your thinking. I don't care if we call it physics or mathematics or biology, but for me I am interested in understanding reality.
Doctordick said:For the moment, why don't we not worry about that; we should first comprehend the defense of the definition and the deduction of the equation itself.
will define the expectations to be the probability that a particular B(tk) will become a member of C: written as P(B(tk)).
Perhaps I do and, if so, I would like to be corrected as communications with common language is difficult at best; I much prefer mathematics as meanings are usually quite universal and generally precise.Fra said:Perhaps you also misinterpret some of my questions too ;) some were provocative in order to probe your responses on key points.
One problem we are apparently having here is that you are thinking in terms of epistemological constructs themselves whereas I am concerned with “representation” of epistemological constructs. I have found that the difference between these two issues is very difficult to communicate. That is one of the reasons I keep bringing up my conversation with Anssi; I am pretty well convinced that he has managed to get his mind past that barrier.Fra said:For obvious reasons I can never be sure I hold the same information as you, but I can say as much that at least some of the things you say makes perfect sense to me and seems closely related to my thinking - this is the part of your explanation or current facts as you put it, implies expectations on the unknown - this bears striking resemblance to optimal inference methods, where one might try to device a relative probability, which I personally call an expectation of the probability because you know what you know, but you can only guess what you don't know, thus sometimes the definition of the proper probability space itself gets unclear.
You were concerned with my definition of probabilities. As you said, one can only guess what they don't know; however, that is of no concern to my analysis in any way. All I am saying is that expectations can be seen in terms of the mathematical concept of probability. It makes utterly no difference how those expectations were arrived at; probability gives us a symbolic way of expressing them; it is a well understood method of communicating expectations.Doctordick said:I will make much use of Mathematics without defense or argument. In essence, it is quite clear that mathematicians are very concerned with the exactness of their definitions and the self consistency of their mental structures. I suspect mathematics could probably be defined to be the study of self consistent systems. At any rate, their concerns are exactly those which drive my work; I am merely attacking a slightly different problem.
I do not understand your question. First of all “how” I introduce tau is a pretty insignificant issue, I just throw it in as an index referring to “invalid ontological element” (a convenient figment of my imagination). Why I introduce it is a much more pertinent question. You need to look at another communication I had with Anssi which I think would clear the issue up a bit. Consider the following excerpt:Fra said:I'm not sure I understand how you introduce tau. My associations is an absolute frequency of x, or something else?
I hope you know that the little blue carrot to the right of the person being quoted is a link to the quote? I say that because it would be worthwhile for you to read that whole post.Doctordick said:Another good example would be that family tree of the primates I brought up. How would you show multiple entries for the same species? You already use horizontal displacement to indicate different species and vertical displacement to indicate time and you would have to include another axis if you wanted to show the time change in populations.
That strikes me as highly probable; I suspected getting you over the hump of seeing my perspective was the real issue. Actually, once you understand where I am coming from, what I am saying is quite simple. Perhaps you could help me communicate with Fredrick? I can certainly use the help.AnssiH said:I have been able to answer some of my questions all by myself.
Doctordick said:The concept “optimal inference method” is itself the result of an epistemological construct (it is a concept defined within your world view). In order for you to communicate to me what you mean by that phrase, you would have to do your best to define what you mean by the expression.
Doctordick said:Certainly, the issue of “epistemological constructs” has already reared it's ugly head but I will suggest that that is
only because you want those terms in my definitions defined.
Again, you have totally missed the point of my response. When I said, “one problem we are apparently having here is that you are thinking in terms of epistemological constructs themselves whereas I am concerned with “representation” of epistemological constructs”, I was referring to the fact that you are not even considering the fundamental problem under discussion. The fundamental problem is, how does one construct “a rational model of a totally unknown universe given nothing but a totally undefined stream of data which has been transcribed by a totally undefined process”. The issue is that you are beginning with the assumption that you have already solved that problem (which is totally equivalent to ignoring it). You start by assuming your world view is valid.Fra said:Of course, you are absolutely right. This is something I'm working on... but I think it would get messy for my to describe my theories here.
Again I seem to have great difficulty communicating the fact that what I am presenting is not a theory (theories are[/color] epistemological constructs). I tried to make that clear in that private note I sent you but apparently you misunderstood what I was saying.Fra said:At least in this thread I suggest we stick to your theory.
The fact is that I have discovered an analytical solution to “the problem of constructing a rational model of a totally unknown universe given nothing but a totally undefined stream of data which has been transcribed by a totally undefined process”. I am trying to communicate that solution to you so that you can evaluate the logic of the solution for yourself.The first comment I would like to make is that what I present is not a theory[/color] (a fact which seems to be impossible to communicate). It is no more or less than a way of organizing what we know without knowing what it is that we know. Somewhat analogous to the Dewy decimal system of organizing a library; the point being that the Dewy decimal system does not depend on knowing what will come to be in that library: it is no more than a procedure for handling the information when it gets there.
The problem in “choosing definitions” is communicating what is meant: i.e., that process itself means we are immediately dealing with epistemological constructs (see my above post to Anssi); ergo,Fra said:There is clearly a universal problem of choosing definitions. You may choose yours differently than mine, and there is no problem.
Doctordick said:My intention was to “make no assumptions” and, under that constraint, all I have to work with is my definition of “reality” (which I define[/color] to be the set of “valid ontological elements” on which my world view is built) and my definition of “an explanation” ( which I define[/color] to be “a method of obtaining expectations from given known information”).
Certainly, the issue of “epistemological constructs” has already reared it's ugly head but I will suggest that that is only because you want those terms in my definitions defined. Ontology is commonly defined to be the study of “being” (which is most often taken to be “what exists”: i.e. reality). What I am saying is that I am going to use those symbols, “reality” and “valid ontology”, to reference what it is that I want to understand (as my meanings seem to be at least quite similar to the common intention of those words). This evades being an epistemological construct by the very fact that I have specified it to be undefined[/color] (it only becomes defined with regard to a specific epistemological construct).
With regard to your ideas, I would agree with you. With regard to my presentation, I would not. I am presenting a logical deduction, not a theory. Either that deduction is a logically valid deduction or it is not. If we disagree on the validity of a logical step, one of us is wrong! There is no room for opinion there. I would love to discuss any error in my deductions which you might find. To date, every case I am aware of has been simple misinterpretation of what I am saying (the “theory” thing being a case in point).Fra said:I guess still, the ultimate proof of success is in the survival and fitness of any ideas. This goes for mine as well as yours. There is IMO no need for us to agree on this.
Doctordick said:I have now read the link you offered and actually find little in his thoughts which impact on my analysis. The first comment I would like to make is that what I present is not a theory (a fact which seems to be impossible to communicate). It is no more or less than a way of organizing what we know without knowing what it is that we know. Somewhat analogous to the Dewy decimal system of organizing a library; the point being that the Dewy decimal system does not depend on knowing what will come to be in that library: it is no more than a procedure for handling the information when it gets there.
Doctordick said:The fundamental problem is, how does one construct “a rational model of a totally unknown universe given nothing but a totally undefined stream of data which has been transcribed by a totally undefined process”.