Resolution to the Delayed choice quantum eraser?

In summary, the delayed choice experiment presents us with the paradox between our concept of time, and the photon's nature of living outside of time. The idler and the signal are measured at the same instant, but for us, time passed between the two measurements. Furthermore, the idler and the signal are entangled particles which means, that when the idler is measured of erased, then it immediately effects the signal - even though for us it is very far away. Could these assessments be true? There is no mystery, strange or paradoxical about delayed choice experiments, provided that you adopt any of the well developed interpretations of QM, such as Copenhagen, many world, Bohmian, or such. Delayed choice is confusing only
  • #1
Gothican
21
0
I've been thinking about this weird experiment for a while and came up with a couple of insights:

* This experiment presents before us the paradox between our concept of time, and the photon's nature of living outside of time. For the photon, the idler and the signal were measured at the same instant. But for us, time passed between the two measurements.

* Furthermore, the idler and the signal are entangled particles which means, that when the idler is measured of erased, then it immediately effects the signal - even though for us it is very far away.

Could these assessments be true?
I'd like to know what you think of them...
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
There is nothing mysterious, strange or paradoxical about delayed choice experiments, provided that you adopt any of the well developed interpretations of QM, such as Copenhagen, many world, Bohmian, or such. Delayed choice is confusing only to those who have still not chosen some coherent interpretation existing at the market, but try to think on QM in terms of concepts that represent a meaningless mixture of various mutually incompatible interpretations.

The fact that Wheeler (who first proposed a variant of the delayed choice experiment) was also confused with that only shows that he did not took his own interpretation of QM (many world) really seriously.
 
Last edited:
  • #3
I don't think you get it. You can use which ever interpretation that you want, but you still won't be able to explain the time paradox.
Let's say you use the Bohmian interpretation; he says that this is an nonlocal universe and therefore the measurement you made on the idler photon (which catches him at a certain position guided by the wavefunctions) immediately effects the signal one - understandable. But what about the fact that the idler photon was measured after the signal was already recorded?
As far as I know, no quantum interpretation explains this time problem. If one does please enlighten me.

The only explanation that I've heard so far was that the measurement of the idler photon gives us an explanation of the signal's past path. Which was kind of hard for me to accept - I mean, each signal photon when recorded, had to either interfere with itself, or not!
 
  • #4
Gothican said:
I don't think you get it. You can use which ever interpretation that you want, but you still won't be able to explain the time paradox.

There is no time paradox at all.

Gothican said:
The only explanation that I've heard so far was that the measurement of the idler photon gives us an explanation of the signal's past path. Which was kind of hard for me to accept - I mean, each signal photon when recorded, had to either interfere with itself, or not!

You do not have self interference here. Delayed choice experiments are all about two-photon interference. You will never see any interference without doing coincidence counting. In fact the signal you record is a superposition of two interference patterns, which are exactly shifted out of phase so that the sum of both shows no interference pattern at all. Detecting the idler too and doing coincidence counting now allows you to pick a subset of all detected photons depending on the position of the detector at the idler side. One of these subsets is one of the interference pattern. If you move the detector at the idler side a bit, you will see the other interference pattern in coincidence counting. This is more or less a question of filtering out the right information - and this filtering can be done any time. Therefore there is no time paradox present.
 
  • #5
Demystifier said:
There is nothing mysterious, strange or paradoxical about delayed choice experiments, provided that you adopt any of the well developed interpretations of QM, such as Copenhagen, many world, Bohmian, or such. Delayed choice is confusing only to those who have still not chosen some coherent interpretation existing at the market, but try to think on QM in terms of concepts that represent a meaningless mixture of various mutually incompatible interpretations.

The fact that Wheeler (who first proposed a variant of the delayed choice experiment) was also confused with that only shows that he did not took his own interpretation of QM (many world) really seriously.

Wheeler and many-worlds? I don't think so. His student Everett formulated many-worlds but I don't remember ever reading that Wheeler was an advocate.

Wheeler's Participatory Anthropic Principle is quite explicit in that he identified at face value the seemingly observer-centric nature of qm. And he cleverly used that interpretation of qm to explain why the universe appeared so fine tuned for life. Paul Davies recently expressed his preference for Wheeler's theory over many-worlds in his Goldilocks book.
 
  • #6
Wow. I finally got it. Thanks Cthugha.:blushing:

Just could you please explain to me the reason that the D0/D1 coincidence count is exactly mirrored by the D0/D2 coincidence (as seen http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Delayed_choice_quantum_eraser" .)

Why would the two detectors result in different patterns?

Thanks again.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #7
Demystifier said:
There is nothing mysterious, strange or paradoxical about delayed choice experiments, provided that you adopt any of the well developed interpretations of QM, such as Copenhagen, many world, Bohmian, or such. Delayed choice is confusing only to those who have still not chosen some coherent interpretation existing at the market, but try to think on QM in terms of concepts that represent a meaningless mixture of various mutually incompatible interpretations.

The fact that Wheeler (who first proposed a variant of the delayed choice experiment) was also confused with that only shows that he did not took his own interpretation of QM (many world) really seriously.

I've always been skeptical of QM interpretations although I know less about the Bohmian model. Both Copenhagen and Many Worlds are frankly metaphysical in that there's no known way to verify or falsify them. Perhaps I'm wrong about this. If so, please enlighten me.

I just posted a question here about the Ensemble model which bypasses the problems with the other interpretations although it may have been falsified in recent experiments using Bose-Einstein condensates.
 
  • #8
Here is a simplified explanation of these different patterns in the DCQE experiment as performed by Kim et al, which I posted earlier somewhere on this forum. It is a bit long, but maybe it helps you understand (and I am too lazy to write a completely new description ;) ).

You can treat this experiment as if every photon here originates from either point A or B (following the pictures in the DCQE paper by Kim). Now the setting is as following:

a) In entangled photon experiments each photon on its own behaves like incoherent light. This means, there is no or at least not much correlation between the phases ([tex]\phi_1[/tex] and [tex]\phi_2[/tex]) of the fields originating from points A and B at the same moment. For the sake of simplicity I will now treat the phase of these fields as completely random and the amplitude as constant and equal.

b) The two-photon state has a well defined phase. This means that the fields of both paths (signal and idler), which originate from the same point (A or B) have a fixed phase relationship. For the sake of simplicity I will now assume, that the initial phase is the same for signal and idler.

Let's first consider, what happens at the detector D0, which scans the x axis. Just like in an usual double slit experiment you will not detect any photons, if there is destructive interference and will detect a large number of photons, if there is constructive interference. Each point P on the x axis, which the detector scans, corresponds to a certain path difference between the paths from A to P and B to P, which can be expressed in terms of an additional phase difference [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex]. So you will have constructive interference at a point if [tex]\Delta \phi +(\phi_2 -\phi_1) = 2 \pi[/tex]. As [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex] is a constant for each point this means that a detection at a certain point P means, that the phase difference between fields at point A and B had a fixed value [tex]\phi_2 -\phi_1[/tex] at a certain time short before. So in fact, scanning the x-axis means scanning the phase difference of the fields. As the fields change completely random and independent of each other, each phase difference will be realized and there will be no interference pattern at D0 alone.

Now let's have a look at the other side. There are two detectors, which both fields can reach and two detectors, which can only be reached by one field. Let me explain D1 first. I will assume that the distances from A and B to each of the detectors are equal. Before the field originating from A reaches the detector, it crosses 2 beam splitters (no reflection) and a mirror. This influences the phase of the field. Assuming that the beam splitters are 50-50 each transmission changes the phase by [tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex] and each reflection changes the phase by [tex]\pi[/tex]. So summarizing the phase of the field originating from A will be [tex]\phi_1[/tex]+[tex]\pi[/tex](reflection at the mirror) + 2*[tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex] (transmission at the beamsplitters. The field reaching D1 from point B is reflected twice and transmitted once, so the phase will be [tex]\phi_2[/tex] + 2*[tex]\pi[/tex]+[tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex], so the phase difference at the detector will be [tex]\Delta \phi=\phi_2+2*\pi+\frac{\pi}{2}-(\phi_1+\pi+2*\frac{\pi}{2})=\phi_2-\phi_1+\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex]. Of course a detection implies again, that there is no destructive interference and most detections will occur, if [tex]\phi_2-\phi_1+\frac{\pi}{2}=2 \pi[/tex] (or a multiple).

Now let's check the other detector. Here the field originating from A is reflected twice and transmitted once and the field originating from B is transmitted twice and reflected once, which leads to a phase relationship of [tex]\Delta \phi = \phi_2 + \pi + 2* \frac{\pi}{2}-(\phi_1+ \frac{\pi}{2}+2*\pi)=\phi_2-\phi_1-\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex]. So the [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex] at the two detectors are exactly [tex]\pi[/tex] out of phase. This means that constructive interference on one detector at some certain phase difference automatically implies destructive interference at the other. So each detector selects a set of phase differences. Let me once again stress that the phases are completely random, so there will be no interference on these detectors either. The detectors D3 and D4 are simpler. As there is only one field present, there will be no interference and the phase does not matter. The detections will be independent of [tex]\phi_1[/tex] and [tex]\phi_2[/tex].

Now we're almost done. Now we have to consider the two-photon state, where the relative phases are not random anymore. As I stated before, a certain spot on the x-axis of D0 corresponds to a certain phase difference [tex]\phi_2 - \phi_1[/tex]. This very same phase difference will also correspond to a certain amount of constructive (or destructive) interference on D1 and consequently also (due to the different geometries concerning transmission and reflection mentioned above) to an equivalent amount of destructive (or constructive) interference on D2. So you will see this interference pattern in the coincidence counts of D0/D1 and D0/D2 due to the fixed phase difference of the two photon state. Now it is also clear, why there is no interference pattern if you have which-way information. If you have which-way information, there is just one field present, which has a random phase. There is no interference pattern present, which corresponds to the phase difference, which is present at D0 and therefore no interference pattern can show up in the coincidence counts.

I hope this simplified scheme shows, why the choice between the interference pattern and the which-way information can be done after the signal photon has already been detected, why it does not depend on whether we have a look at the data or not and that there are no problems with causality.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #9
See this article for a local deterministic explanation of the delayed choice experiment.

Computer simulation of Wheeler's delayed-choice experiment with photons
S. Zhao, S. Yuan, H. De Raedt and K. Michielsen 2008 EPL 82 40004
http://msc.phys.rug.nl/pdf/DelayedChoice-epl2.pdf
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #10
mn4j said:
Computer simulation of Wheeler's delayed-choice experiment with photons S. Zhao, S. Yuan, H. De Raedt and K. Michielsen 2008 EPL 82 40004
http://msc.phys.rug.nl/pdf/DelayedChoice-epl2.pdf

WARNING: This reference is not generally accepted science. De Raedt et al are part of a local realist group which is mostly ignored by mainstream scientists in the field. To the extent this group is not ignored, it has been critiqued. I do not recommend this. (Computer simulations are not theories or explanations anyway.)
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #11
Coldcall said:
Wheeler and many-worlds? I don't think so. His student Everett formulated many-worlds but I don't remember ever reading that Wheeler was an advocate.
You are wrong. It is true that Everett was first who proposed a variant of this interpretation, but he called it relative-state interpretation. Soon after the Everett work Wheeler has also written a paper where he further developed these ideas. It was Wheeler who called it many-world interpretation. The references are
H. Everett, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29 (1957) 454
J. A. Wheeler, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29 (1957) 463
so you can check it by yourself.
 
  • #12
Gothican said:
I don't think you get it. You can use which ever interpretation that you want, but you still won't be able to explain the time paradox.
Let's say you use the Bohmian interpretation; he says that this is an nonlocal universe and therefore the measurement you made on the idler photon (which catches him at a certain position guided by the wavefunctions) immediately effects the signal one - understandable. But what about the fact that the idler photon was measured after the signal was already recorded?
As far as I know, no quantum interpretation explains this time problem. If one does please enlighten me.
I think it is you who don't get it. In the Bohmian interpretation, the wave ALLWAYS goes through both slits, and the particle ALLWAYS goes through one slit only. An experiment made after these travels through the slits does not influence the past. So the Bohmian interpretation does solve the time problem. The Copenhagen and many-world interpretations also do so, but in a different way. In the Copenhagen interpretation the unmeasured past does not even exist, so it cannot be changed. In the many-world interpretation the wave goes through both slits, but after that the wave splits into two "worlds" so that a particular observer observes only one of them.
 
  • #13
SW VandeCarr said:
I've always been skeptical of QM interpretations although I know less about the Bohmian model. Both Copenhagen and Many Worlds are frankly metaphysical in that there's no known way to verify or falsify them. Perhaps I'm wrong about this. If so, please enlighten me.
Well, you must accept SOME interpretation, because otherwise the quantum theory is useless. Even the "shut-up-and-calculate" interpretation is an interpretation, and certainly a very useful one. Even with this interpretation there is no problem with delayed choice experiments, provided that you stick to this interpretation persistently.

But if you have some your own interpretation that boroughs elements from many different "official" interpretations, you must be very careful because it is very likely that such a mixture is not consistent and that delayed choice will look paradoxical. If you want to be consistent, it is much safer to choose one particular "official" interpretation that you like and to stick to it very strictly and persistently.
 
Last edited:
  • #14
Wow Cthugha, You really managed to clarify this for me. Thanks for the great post.

Oh, and just to be sure - each time a idler photon goes through one of those mirrors and gets 'phased out', it immediately changes the signal's phase too (in the same order). Right?

Greetings from Israel.:smile:
 
  • #15
Gothican said:
Wow Cthugha, You really managed to clarify this for me.
Since now you understand what is really going on in the experiment, perhaps you might like this metaphoric explanation as well:
https://www.physicsforums.com/blog.php?b=7
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #16
Cthugha said:
So the [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex] at the two detectors are exactly [tex]\pi[/tex] out of phase. This means that constructive interference on one detector at some certain phase difference automatically implies destructive interference at the other.

But if we wanted to, we could just add a mirror in front of one of them, so that one of their phases would bump back [tex]\pi[/tex]. Then the phase of both of the detectors would match - & we would be able to define whether a signal interfered with itself or not, before we would measure the idler!
 
  • #17
Gothican said:
But if we wanted to, we could just add a mirror in front of one of them, so that one of their phases would bump back [tex]\pi[/tex]. Then the phase of both of the detectors would match - & we would be able to define whether a signal interfered with itself or not, before we would measure the idler!

No, that would not help. Putting a mirror somewhere will always alter two of the probability amplitudes so that the final situation is the same. If you put the mirror directly in front of a detector, this is trivial. You just have a phase shift of pi for both fields so that he phase difference between them remains the same. If you put a mirror directly in front of BS A or B, you will alter the phase difference at both detectors by pi, which in turn will finally also lead to the same total difference of phase differences.
 
  • #18
Ahhhhh, right.
Satisfying answer.
Once again, Thanks a lot.
 
  • #19
Demystifier said:
I think it is you who don't get it. In the Bohmian interpretation, the wave ALLWAYS goes through both slits, and the particle ALLWAYS goes through one slit only. An experiment made after these travels through the slits does not influence the past. So the Bohmian interpretation does solve the time problem. The Copenhagen and many-world interpretations also do so, but in a different way. In the Copenhagen interpretation the unmeasured past does not even exist, so it cannot be changed. In the many-world interpretation the wave goes through both slits, but after that the wave splits into two "worlds" so that a particular observer observes only one of them.

Demystifier said:
But if you have some your own interpretation that boroughs elements from many different "official" interpretations, you must be very careful because it is very likely that such a mixture is not consistent and that delayed choice will look paradoxical. If you want to be consistent, it is much safer to choose one particular "official" interpretation that you like and to stick to it very strictly and persistently.

Demystifier, you are right and I LOVE your precision in quoting that is so much absent in present physics (other disciplines would have collapsed with the level of rigor in quoting and citing that one sees in the physics literature since the sixties or a bit before). BUT, isn't it worthwhile and perhaps NECESSARY to try to have an interpretation that would let one expect to go beyond the Copenhagen Interpretation -or CopInt- (and would meanwhile replace the most dogmatic aspects of the Copenhagen quasi religion -even if it is the best complete system so far -I personally prefer the CopInt to Consistent Quantum Theory=CQT )? A theory that would (for instance) use yet unknown coordinates-assuming coordinates are used, as expected by Schrodinger and Einstein, but not naive and worthless as the HV of de Broglie, Bohm, Bell and others. I barely see where this theory would lie between actual Nature laws, QM and the macroscopic physics used to give meaning to QM according to Copenhagen, so do not ask me any detail.
For sure the past is not changed after elapsed in the CopInt, and precisely for the reason that you give, yet the past is defined after elapsed in the CopInt and that is not very nice. I believe that taking non-realism more seriously let's one avoid all the problems of Copenhagen, still respecting what is most respectable in he CopInt. I'll elaborate elsewhere but let me point out that Wheeler's discussion does not take into account that once one gets into the Interference Zone (or IZ, the overlap of the volumes reaches by the rays on both paths, (notice then that MZI's are not good machines for Wheeler's experiment without a slight modification that creates an IZ, but Wheeler missed that point)), the question of where a particle comes from does not make sense any more (I assume here that Welcher Weg (WW) is unknown for all photons or else). IZ is a macroscopically defined object whose structure can be computed in simple cases or observed rather simply using separate observations. Once one understand that WW Determination (WWD an objective state of affairs) is impossible as soon as IZ is reached, it becomes obvious why Afshar's experiment does not allow WWD, and even less WW Knowledge (or WWK, a weaker, subjective status). Back to Wheeler, in all cases, if the observation is made in IZ or beyond IZ, the quantum went both ways. One can now make the observation just before the IZ, but then it is easy to see that the delay is meaningless (except if you believe that small green men transport the info faster than light to the beam splitting apparatus).
So the ONLY real problem remains the one pointed out by Feynman, i.e., the interference.
This is another story that I will not undertake here (but I'd love to discuss that somewhere soon enough).
 
Last edited:
  • #20
You must remember that from the photons point of view (both the signal and idler photons), time does not exists and distances shrink to zero at the speed of light. So as far as the photons are concerned, each arrives at their respective detector simultaneously.
 
  • #21
Cthugha said:
Here is a simplified explanation of these different patterns in the DCQE experiment as performed by Kim et al, which I posted earlier somewhere on this forum. It is a bit long, but maybe it helps you understand (and I am too lazy to write a completely new description ;) ).

You can treat this experiment as if every photon here originates from either point A or B (following the pictures in the DCQE paper by Kim). Now the setting is as following:

a) In entangled photon experiments each photon on its own behaves like incoherent light. This means, there is no or at least not much correlation between the phases ([tex]\phi_1[/tex] and [tex]\phi_2[/tex]) of the fields originating from points A and B at the same moment. For the sake of simplicity I will now treat the phase of these fields as completely random and the amplitude as constant and equal.

b) The two-photon state has a well defined phase. This means that the fields of both paths (signal and idler), which originate from the same point (A or B) have a fixed phase relationship. For the sake of simplicity I will now assume, that the initial phase is the same for signal and idler.

Let's first consider, what happens at the detector D0, which scans the x axis. Just like in an usual double slit experiment you will not detect any photons, if there is destructive interference and will detect a large number of photons, if there is constructive interference. Each point P on the x axis, which the detector scans, corresponds to a certain path difference between the paths from A to P and B to P, which can be expressed in terms of an additional phase difference [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex]. So you will have constructive interference at a point if [tex]\Delta \phi +(\phi_2 -\phi_1) = 2 \pi[/tex]. As [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex] is a constant for each point this means that a detection at a certain point P means, that the phase difference between fields at point A and B had a fixed value [tex]\phi_2 -\phi_1[/tex] at a certain time short before. So in fact, scanning the x-axis means scanning the phase difference of the fields. As the fields change completely random and independent of each other, each phase difference will be realized and there will be no interference pattern at D0 alone.

Now let's have a look at the other side. There are two detectors, which both fields can reach and two detectors, which can only be reached by one field. Let me explain D1 first. I will assume that the distances from A and B to each of the detectors are equal. Before the field originating from A reaches the detector, it crosses 2 beam splitters (no reflection) and a mirror. This influences the phase of the field. Assuming that the beam splitters are 50-50 each transmission changes the phase by [tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex] and each reflection changes the phase by [tex]\pi[/tex]. So summarizing the phase of the field originating from A will be [tex]\phi_1[/tex]+[tex]\pi[/tex](reflection at the mirror) + 2*[tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex] (transmission at the beamsplitters. The field reaching D1 from point B is reflected twice and transmitted once, so the phase will be [tex]\phi_2[/tex] + 2*[tex]\pi[/tex]+[tex]\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex], so the phase difference at the detector will be [tex]\Delta \phi=\phi_2+2*\pi+\frac{\pi}{2}-(\phi_1+\pi+2*\frac{\pi}{2})=\phi_2-\phi_1+\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex]. Of course a detection implies again, that there is no destructive interference and most detections will occur, if [tex]\phi_2-\phi_1+\frac{\pi}{2}=2 \pi[/tex] (or a multiple).

Now let's check the other detector. Here the field originating from A is reflected twice and transmitted once and the field originating from B is transmitted twice and reflected once, which leads to a phase relationship of [tex]\Delta \phi = \phi_2 + \pi + 2* \frac{\pi}{2}-(\phi_1+ \frac{\pi}{2}+2*\pi)=\phi_2-\phi_1-\frac{\pi}{2}[/tex]. So the [tex]\Delta \phi[/tex] at the two detectors are exactly [tex]\pi[/tex] out of phase. This means that constructive interference on one detector at some certain phase difference automatically implies destructive interference at the other. So each detector selects a set of phase differences. Let me once again stress that the phases are completely random, so there will be no interference on these detectors either. The detectors D3 and D4 are simpler. As there is only one field present, there will be no interference and the phase does not matter. The detections will be independent of [tex]\phi_1[/tex] and [tex]\phi_2[/tex].

Now we're almost done. Now we have to consider the two-photon state, where the relative phases are not random anymore. As I stated before, a certain spot on the x-axis of D0 corresponds to a certain phase difference [tex]\phi_2 - \phi_1[/tex]. This very same phase difference will also correspond to a certain amount of constructive (or destructive) interference on D1 and consequently also (due to the different geometries concerning transmission and reflection mentioned above) to an equivalent amount of destructive (or constructive) interference on D2. So you will see this interference pattern in the coincidence counts of D0/D1 and D0/D2 due to the fixed phase difference of the two photon state. Now it is also clear, why there is no interference pattern if you have which-way information. If you have which-way information, there is just one field present, which has a random phase. There is no interference pattern present, which corresponds to the phase difference, which is present at D0 and therefore no interference pattern can show up in the coincidence counts.

I hope this simplified scheme shows, why the choice between the interference pattern and the which-way information can be done after the signal photon has already been detected, why it does not depend on whether we have a look at the data or not and that there are no problems with causality.

Is the understanding and explanation of DCQE below correct? else please modify:

http://grad.physics.sunysb.edu/~amarch/


Case 1: which-way for s and no-which-way for i (after s has been detected)

if we look at Ds, we will see no interference pattern (prior to coincidence matching)

however after co-incidence count we will see interference pattern (on both Ds and Di)

This is because only those photons will get selected/paired (via co-incidence counting) that lie on the interference pattern.

Case 2: no-which-way for s and which-way for i (after s has been detected):


if we look at Ds, we will see no interference pattern (prior to coincidence matching)

After co-incidence count we will NOT see interference pattern either (on both Ds and Di)

This is because only those photons will get selected/paired (via co-incidence counting) that lie all over the sheet.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #22
Cthugha said:
There is no time paradox at all.
You do not have self interference here. Delayed choice experiments are all about two-photon interference. You will never see any interference without doing coincidence counting. In fact the signal you record is a superposition of two interference patterns, which are exactly shifted out of phase so that the sum of both shows no interference pattern at all. Detecting the idler too and doing coincidence counting now allows you to pick a subset of all detected photons depending on the position of the detector at the idler side. One of these subsets is one of the interference pattern. If you move the detector at the idler side a bit, you will see the other interference pattern in coincidence counting. This is more or less a question of filtering out the right information - and this filtering can be done any time. Therefore there is no time paradox present.
Case 1: if we detected s with no-which-way and later manipulate idler to which-way:

i am not able to see how the subset would explain the above because:

in this case all the s photons are on the interference pattern thus there is only one subset (after co-incidence matching)...that of interference pattern...because we sent all s-photons via no-which-way...however we actually get no interference pattern which matches with the idler

what am i missing?

because when we remove the noise, we should get only no-which-way photon marks...i.e. an interference pattern...because we sent only no-which-way photons
 
Last edited:
  • #23
charlylebeaugosse said:
Demystifier, you are right and I LOVE your precision in quoting that is so much absent in present physics (other disciplines would have collapsed with the level of rigor in quoting and citing that one sees in the physics literature since the sixties or a bit before).
Thanks! :blushing:

You might also like my similar arguments here:
https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=402497
especially in the first post.
 
  • #24
San K said:
in this case all the s photons are on the interference pattern thus there is only one subset (after co-incidence matching)...that of interference pattern...because we sent all s-photons via no-which-way...

There is no "the" interference pattern. There are many of them depending on the actual wavevector involved. You can also try that out on a simple double slit which is illuminated by light with different wave vectors (imagine plane waves not traveling orthogonal to the plane of the double slit) and you will see how the pattern changes.

By doing coincidence counting which defines the wave vector on the other side you single out one of the many interference patterns. If you do not single out one, you get the superposition of many which add up to no pattern at all.
 
  • #25
Cthugha said:
There is no "the" interference pattern. .

hmmm...let me understand this better...lets say we pass a billion photons (one by one) through the slits/setup...

we get an interference pattern...we mark the bands...lets say its like below:

dark band is when x between 0 and 1

space (between fringes) is between 1 and 2

next dark band is x values between 3 and 4

next space (between fringes) is between 4 and 5

and so on...

now once we have run the billion photons...we wipe the screen...and then run another billion photons ...this time again one by one


wont we get the same...i.e.

dark band is when x between 0 and 1

space (between fringes) is between 1 and 2

next dark band is x values between 3 and 4

next space (between fringes) is between 4 and 5


[/QUOTE]There are many of them depending on the actual wavevector involved. You can also try that out on a simple double slit which is illuminated by light with different wave vectors (imagine plane waves not traveling orthogonal to the plane of the double slit) and you will see how the pattern changes.

By doing coincidence counting which defines the wave vector on the other side you single out one of the many interference patterns. If you do not single out one, you get the superposition of many which add up to no pattern at all.[/QUOTE]
 
  • #26
I do not get your problem. Are you talking about DCQE or a simple double slit?

Entanglement means that the total wave vector of the photon pair is fixed, but the wave vector of each one of the pair is fairly undefined. Each subset having the same wave vector will produce the same interference pattern. Each subset having another wave vector will show a different pattern. If you run the billion photons twice and take the same subset of wave vectors you will get the same pattern. If you pick a different subset, you will get a different pattern. If you do not filter at all, you will get no pattern at all.

You can easily try that with a simple double slit. Illuminate it with plane waves arriving at the double slit at an angle (angle is proportional to the wave vector) and see how the pattern changes.
 
  • #27
Cthugha said:
I do not get your problem. Are you talking about DCQE or a simple double slit?

Entanglement means that the total wave vector of the photon pair is fixed, but the wave vector of each one of the pair is fairly undefined. Each subset having the same wave vector will produce the same interference pattern. Each subset having another wave vector will show a different pattern. If you run the billion photons twice and take the same subset of wave vectors you will get the same pattern. If you pick a different subset, you will get a different pattern. If you do not filter at all, you will get no pattern at all.

You can easily try that with a simple double slit. Illuminate it with plane waves arriving at the double slit at an angle (angle is proportional to the wave vector) and see how the pattern changes.

I am talking about the DCQE with detectors (and patterns) on both detectors being studied.

I think the main point I am not able to fully understand is:

- i thought there were only two specific patterns, just like shown in the kim yoon paper
- both of them are shifted by a phase from each other and cancel out
- the two patterns are fixed in location (the x co-ordinates of ---> the fringes, the width, the empty space etc, all are fixed)

so i don't understand when you say there are many (interference) patterns...

so I am trying to understand what you mean

or here is my confusion/question:

- when s strikes detector Ds, the quantum is registered (though we don't know which one is the right photon)
- if the quantum is registered its position is registered,
- now this position either falls on the interference pattern or does not, but I feel you are hinting that even thought the position is fixed (yet unknown to us) the same position could fall or not fall on the interference pattern based on what we do with p?
 
Last edited:
  • #28
I see. I was thinking more about a setup like the one used by Walborn et al.

The Scully and Kim version is slightly differnet as the double slit appears before the BBO crystal. However, it is not a big difference. The selection in k-space is automatically performed by using small detectors. If you moved them around instead of D0, you would also notice a changing interference pattern.
In the Kim paper you now find two patterns due to the geometry of the experiment, which causes the photons to arrive at the respective detectors with a phase shift of a half cycle. This of course also means that the patterns are shifted and out of phase. You could get other patterns if you moved D1-D4, too. This is basically mentioned along the lines of eq. 4 as moving them around slightly changes the distance between BBO and detector and will therefore change the joint detection rate.
 
  • #29
Cthugha said:
I see. I was thinking more about a setup like the one used by Walborn et al.

The Scully and Kim version is slightly differnet as the double slit appears before the BBO crystal. However, it is not a big difference. The selection in k-space is automatically performed by using small detectors. If you moved them around instead of D0, you would also notice a changing interference pattern.
In the Kim paper you now find two patterns due to the geometry of the experiment, which causes the photons to arrive at the respective detectors with a phase shift of a half cycle. This of course also means that the patterns are shifted and out of phase. You could get other patterns if you moved D1-D4, too. This is basically mentioned along the lines of eq. 4 as moving them around slightly changes the distance between BBO and detector and will therefore change the joint detection rate.

The main issue where the challenge, in understanding, in my mind is:

the s-photon has been registered. now how do we explain the same position could either fall on an interference pattern or not?...to match with p-photon
 
Last edited:
  • #30
It is an interference pattern in the JOINED detection rate only. You can never say the the s-photon falls on an interference pattern because there are only interference patterns seen when considering the biphoton wavepacket. You only distinguish between the situations where the detection of the s-photon creates a situation with well defined phase that causes more detections at one of the two detectors than on the other (which gives the interference patterns) and those which do not give different detections at the two detectors.

You can never consider the s and p-photon as individual photons. Doing so will always result in wrong understandings and weird interpretations.
 
  • #31
Cthugha said:
It is an interference pattern in the JOINED detection rate only. You can never say the the s-photon falls on an interference pattern because there are only interference patterns seen when considering the biphoton wavepacket. You only distinguish between the situations where the detection of the s-photon creates a situation with well defined phase that causes more detections at one of the two detectors than on the other (which gives the interference patterns) and those which do not give different detections at the two detectors.

You can never consider the s and p-photon as individual photons. Doing so will always result in wrong understandings and weird interpretations.

in your opinion:

when s is registered on the detector, do they still remain as one or separate?

when p is finally registered on the detector, do they still remain as one or separate?

i mean when is the so called hypothetical "entanglement" broken?
 
  • #32
San K said:
... when is the so called hypothetical "entanglement" broken?

Well, it's not hypothetical since it is demonstrated experimentally. And those experiments do not conclusively show when or how entanglement ends. It appears to end when an irreversible measurement is made. Even this is somewhat ambiguous in the case of 3 (or more) particle entanglement (which partially collapses things).
 
  • #33
DrChinese said:
Well, it's not hypothetical since it is demonstrated experimentally. And those experiments do not conclusively show when or how entanglement ends. It appears to end when an irreversible measurement is made. Even this is somewhat ambiguous in the case of 3 (or more) particle entanglement (which partially collapses things).

ok, thanks for the info, and agreed (about entanglement being real/demonstrated)

in your opinion - an irreversible measurement is made when s or when p is detected?
 
  • #34
San K said:
in your opinion - an irreversible measurement is made when s or when p is detected?

Honestly, a reasonable opinion on this eludes me. :smile: I use first measurement as a basic reference point for ease of discussions. I think of the overall context as being what controls, but there really is no normal point in time associated with that.
 
  • #35
Cthugha said:
There is no time paradox at all.
You do not have self interference here. Delayed choice experiments are all about two-photon interference. You will never see any interference without doing coincidence counting. In fact the signal you record is a superposition of two interference patterns, which are exactly shifted out of phase so that the sum of both shows no interference pattern at all. Detecting the idler too and doing coincidence counting now allows you to pick a subset of all detected photons depending on the position of the detector at the idler side. One of these subsets is one of the interference pattern. If you move the detector at the idler side a bit, you will see the other interference pattern in coincidence counting. This is more or less a question of filtering out the right information - and this filtering can be done any time. Therefore there is no time paradox present.

I don't see how doing coincidence counting changes anything about the essence of the experimental results. Each idler photon's entangled signal photon pal still struck the D0 detector first and had its location recorded (time paradox) while the idler was still in flight, and all the signal photons that correlate with the idlers that struck at D4 or D3 do not exhibit interference, while all the signal photons that stuck at D0 that correlate with the idlers that struck at D2 and D1 do exhibit interference (which-way information paradox). I don't see how looking at the data afterwards and separating out the coincidence pairs alters or explains anything of the mystery of the experiment as you seem to suggest. Perhaps I'm just missing something here.
 

Similar threads

Replies
4
Views
814
Replies
18
Views
1K
Replies
8
Views
901
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
784
Replies
3
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
692
Replies
19
Views
954
Replies
1
Views
642
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Back
Top