A An argument against Bohmian mechanics?

  • #51
A. Neumaier said:
But arbitrarily many, which makes the number of degrees of freedom infinite. An ##N##-particle system has ##3N## degrees of freedom. Already a free quantum field theory has an indeterminate number of particles. The number of degrees of freedom therefore exceeds ##3N## for any ##N##. Thus there are infinitely many degrees of freedom.

Well, I'm uncertain about the terminology, but the distinction that I'm making is between:
  1. An unbounded number of particles, and
  2. an infinite number of particles.
The distinction is that in the case of an unbounded number of particles, if |\psi\rangle is a state with an unbounded number of particles, then there is at least one nonnegative number n and a state |\psi_n\rangle with exactly n particles such that \langle \psi|\psi_n \rangle is nonzero.

With a truly infinite number of particles, there would be no overlap with any state with just finitely many particles.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
stevendaryl said:
Well, I'm uncertain about the terminology, but the distinction that I'm making is between:
  1. An unbounded number of particles, and
  2. an infinite number of particles.
This distinction is valid, but doesn't affect the fact that - in contrast to the claim of Rubi above - QFT has infinitely many degrees of freedom while QM has only finitely many. This differences is extremely important.
 
  • #53
A. Neumaier said:
This distinction is valid, but doesn't affect the fact that - in contrast to the claim of Rubi above - QFT has infinitely many degrees of freedom while QM has only finitely many. This differences is extremely important.
Well, that's not what I said. I explained in my post, what I meant by d.o.f., i.e. a state in QFT contains as much information as a state in QM. Of course, in the case of QFT, you need to embed a field algebra into the algebra of operators on the separable Hilbert space, instead of a particle algebra. However, this is not what is problematic. You can easily write down a Fock space and field operators on it and you can also write down well-defined interacting Hamiltonians in that Hilbert space. However, you won't be able to write down an interacting Hamiltonian that satisfies the Poincare algebra relations, i.e. produces a Lorentz-invariant theory. Writing down interacting theories that satisfy the Wightman axioms is of course very difficult.
 
  • #54
rubi said:
a state in QFT contains as much information as a state in QM.
But this is wrong. In QM, one cannot represent the information that a system is in a superposition of arbitrarily many particles!
 
  • #55
A. Neumaier said:
But this is wrong. In QM, one cannot represent the information that a system is in a superposition of arbitrarily many particles!
That is not relevant to measuring how much information can be encoded into a state. Of course, different theories encode different information in the state, but the amount of information is exactly the same. I can store either Pulp Fiction or Full Metal Jacket on my hard drive, but if I choose to store Full Metal Jacket, the information about what a quarter pounder with cheese is called in France won't be represented.
 
  • #56
rubi said:
That is not relevant to measuring how much information can be encoded into a state. Of course, different theories encode different information in the state, but the amount of information is exactly the same. I can store either Pulp Fiction or Full Metal Jacket on my hard drive, but if I choose to store Full Metal Jacket, the information about what a quarter pounder with cheese is called in France won't be represented.
But measuring information in this way is completely irrelevant. Every real number contains in your sense more information than all the physics books in the world. A classical field theory contains in your sense as much information as a quantum field theory.

In any case, it is highly misleading to equate this strange measure of information with degrees of freedom, as you did in your post #47 (without being precise enough there).
 
  • Like
Likes RockyMarciano
  • #57
A. Neumaier said:
But measuring information in this way is completely irrelevant. Every real number contains in your sense more information than all the physics books in the world. A classical field theory contains in your sense as much information as a quantum field theory.

In any case, it is highly misleading to equate this strange measure of information with degrees of freedom, as you did in your post #47 (without being precise enough there).
I stated precisely what I meant by it in my post #47, so all of this is just a semantic discussion. Of course, the dimension of the Hilbert space is relevant to what quantum theories can be formulated on it. You cannot formulate QFT in ##\mathbb C^2##, but you can (in principle) formulate it in the usual ##L^2(\mathbb R^3)## space of ordinary quantum mechanics. As I explained, the fact that you are working with a field algebra instead of a particle algebra is not a priori problematic.
 
  • #58
rubi said:
You cannot formulate QFT in C2C2\mathbb C^2, but you can (in principle) formulate it in the usual ##L^2(\mathbb R^3)## space of ordinary quantum mechanics.
No, you cannot in any sensible way since there is no natural isomorphism between a Fock space for QFT and ##L^2(\mathbb R^3)##. The structure imposed on the Hilbert space makes all the difference for its information content! Quantum mechanics does not happen in arbitrary Hilbert spaces but in Hilbert spaces with distinguished group actions!
 
  • Like
Likes RockyMarciano
  • #59
At this point, it seems like you just don't want to admit that you didn't read my post carefully. As a mathematician, you certainly know that I can pull back any structure between isomorphic objects, so of course I can pull back the group action from a Fock space onto ##L^2##. I don't need a natural isomorphism for that. (Moreover, it's exactly the other way around. The irreducible representations of the Poincare group that you obtain from Wigner's analysis are naturally defined on ##L^2## spaces. Fock spaces are built from these ##L^2## spaces and only inherit this group action.)
 
  • #60
stevendaryl said:
Well, I'm uncertain about the terminology, but the distinction that I'm making is between:
  1. An unbounded number of particles, and
  2. an infinite number of particles.
The distinction is that in the case of an unbounded number of particles, if |\psi\rangle is a state with an unbounded number of particles, then there is at least one nonnegative number n and a state |\psi_n\rangle with exactly n particles such that \langle \psi|\psi_n \rangle is nonzero.

With a truly infinite number of particles, there would be no overlap with any state with just finitely many particles.
There's no state with infinitely many particles in the sense that the expectation value of the number of particles should be finite for the state to make sense. However, you are right in saying that there are states which have a non-zero overlap with any Fock state of a definite finite particle number. An example are the coherent states of the electromagnetic field, which are as close to classical em. waves as you can get. The photon-number probabilities are given by the Poisson statistics.
 
  • #61
rubi said:
As a mathematician, you certainly know that I can pull back any structure between isomorphic objects
Yes, but ##L^2(R^3)## doesn't have this structure but must be equipped with it in order to have it. Quantum physics is always about Hilbert spaces already equipped with the right group action.

Ignoring that is like saying I can do functional analysis in the set ##R_+## of positive real numbers, since I can equip any set with continuum cardinality with the structure of ##L^2(R^3)##. No mathematician in his right mind would talk like this.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #62
vanhees71 said:
There's no state with infinitely many particles in the sense that the expectation value of the number of particles should be finite for the state to make sense.
But a state must only be square integrable. Therefore there are valid states (such as ##\sum_{N>0} N^{-1}|N\rangle##) where the expected number of particles is infinite. Nevertheless, upon each Born-style measurement, the number of particles would come out finite.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #63
Hm, good point. This would be a state without a vacuum contribution. Interesting. I'm a bit in doubt, whether it can be prepared for any type of particles.
 
  • #64
vanhees71 said:
I'm a bit in doubt, whether it can be prepared for any type of particles.
It would take an infinite amount of energy to create it, I believe.
vanhees71 said:
This would be a state without a vacuum contribution.
The state ##\sum_{N\ge 0} (N+1)^{-1}|N\rangle## has the same properties but with a vacuum contribution. Thus that's not the source of the difficulties to create such a state. You can add as much vacuum as you like without changing the infinite expected particle number.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #65
A. Neumaier said:
Yes, but ##L^2(R^3)## doesn't have this structure but must be equipped with it in order to have it. Quantum physics is always about Hilbert spaces already equipped with the right group action.

Ignoring that is like saying I can do functional analysis in the set ##R_+## of positive real numbers, since I can equip any set with continuum cardinality with the structure of ##L^2(R^3)##. No mathematician in his right mind would talk like this.
An object must always be equipped with a structure in order to have it. It's just easier to write it down in some cases. I'm of course not suggesting that one should do QFT on ##L^2(\mathbb R^3)##, but that one could do it, i.e. a state vector in QM needs as much information to be fully specified as a state vector in QFT. You cannot do QFT in the Hilbert space of a spin-1/2 system. And you cannot do LQG in the Hilbert space of a QFT. The dimension of the Hilbert space is of course a measure for the information content of a quantum state.

Anyway, I have explained what I meant already in post #47 and what I said was correct, so this discussion is a bit pointless.
 
  • #66
rubi said:
The dimension of the Hilbert space is of course a measure for the information content of a quantum state.
No. The conventional, and the only reasonable measure of information applicable a quantum state is the entropy. What you talk about does not deserve the name information in the traditional, scientifically established sense.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #67
rubi said:
You cannot do QFT in the Hilbert space of a spin-1/2 system. And you cannot do LQG in the Hilbert space of a QFT. The dimension of the Hilbert space is of course a measure for the information content of a quantum state.
First I don't understand what you mean by the first quoted sentence, since a "Pauli particle" (spin-1/2 particle in non-relativistic QT) is described by the usual separable Hilbert space and usually reallized as ##\mathrm{L}^2(\mathbb{R}^3,\mathbb{C}^2)## (position-spin representation or "wave mechanics").

For curiosity, what's LQG?

I also don't know what I should make of the third sentence. The information content of a quantum state, or rather our ignorance about it, is given by the (von Neumann) entropy. For a pure state it's 0 (i.e., we have full possible knowledge about the system's preparation).
 
  • #68
A. Neumaier said:
No. The conventional, and the only reasonable measure of information applicable a quantum state is the entropy. What you talk about does not deserve the name information in the traditional, scientifically established sense.
Then please just assign whatever name you like to it, so we don't need to have this discussion about pure semantics. The dimension of the Hilbert space is a classification criterion for quantum systems.

vanhees71 said:
First I don't understand what you mean by the first quoted sentence, since a "Pauli particle" (spin-1/2 particle in non-relativistic QT) is described by the usual separable Hilbert space and usually reallized as ##\mathrm{L}^2(\mathbb{R}^3,\mathbb{C}^2)## (position-spin representation or "wave mechanics").
I said "spin-1/2 system" and not "(Pauli) particle". A spin-1/2 system is conventionally understood as ##\mathcal H=\mathbb C^2## with the standard spin-1/2 representation of ##SU(2)##. People study such quantum systems without referencing the coordinates of particles. Especially in quantum information, people rarely use infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces.

For curiosity, what's LQG?
Loop quantum gravity.

I also don't know what I should make of the third sentence. The information content of a quantum state, or rather our ignorance about it, is given by the (von Neumann) entropy. For a pure state it's 0 (i.e., we have full possible knowledge about the system's preparation).
See above.
 
  • #69
rubi said:
The dimension of the Hilbert space is a classification criterion for quantum systems.
A very, very weak one, since the vast majority of quantum systems of experimental interest (except for finite spin systems) have a separable infinite-dimensional Hilbert space, all of which are isomorphic if you don't have additional structure.
 
  • #70
A. Neumaier said:
A very, very weak one, since the vast majority of quantum systems of experimental interest (except for finite spin systems) have a separable infinite-dimensional Hilbert space, all of which are isomorphic if you don't have additional structure.
I agree, but it seemed to me like Demystifier wasn't aware of it, which is why I explained it in my post. At first, it seems unintuitive that a Hilbert space of separable dimension is enough for field variables, because one might think that a field can have values at uncountably many space-time points. A separable Hilbert space suffices, because only smeared fields (smeared with Schwartz functions) are considered. If one wanted to include fields operators defined at sharp space-time points, one would need a Hilbert space of uncountable dimension.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and dextercioby
  • #71
rubi said:
If one wanted to include fields operators defined at sharp space-time points, one would need a Hilbert space of uncountable dimension.
But one then gets into trouble with locality.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #72
A. Neumaier said:
But one then gets into trouble with locality.
Possible, but why do you think so? One could require ##[\phi(x),\phi(y)]=\delta_{xy}## instead of ##[\phi(x),\phi(y)]=\delta(x-y)##.
I think the motivation for using Schwartz distributions is to have a well-defined notion of Fourier transform, while maintaining as much generality as possible.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #73
rubi said:
Possible, but why do you think so? One could require ##[\phi(x),\phi(y)]=\delta_{xy}## instead of ##[\phi(x),\phi(y)]=\delta(x-y)##.
Your suggestion plays havoc with everything important in QFT, since it essentially equips space-time with the discrete topology. Try to base a QFT on your suggestion and you'll see.
 
  • #74
A. Neumaier said:
Your suggestion plays havoc with everything important in QFT, since it essentially equips space-time with the discrete topology. Try to base a QFT on your suggestion and you'll see.
I can see many things going wrong and I agree that one shouldn't do it. It's just an example to clarify things. I was just wondering, why you were specifically thinking about locality, because that seems pretty easy to maintain.
 
  • #75
Well, our lattice-QCD colleagues are pretty successful with such an approach, however only in imaginary time ;-).
 
  • #76
vanhees71 said:
Well, our lattice-QCD colleagues are pretty successful with such an approach, however only in imaginary time ;-).
But locality isn't conventionally defined in imaginary time ;-(
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #77
Well, yes. Lattice theory is an approximation as well, but tell this the lattice guys and see their reaction (which is very interesting ;-)).
 
  • #78
vanhees71 said:
Well, yes. Lattice theory is an approximation as well, but tell this the lattice guys and see their reaction (which is very interesting ;-)).
The right question is this: Is it only an approximation in the limit ##a\rightarrow 0##?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #79
Yes, that's indeed the question, but on the other hand computers are finite, and thus also ##a## stays always finite too in practical calculations.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #80
rubi said:
Well, apparently, this theorem is not established rigorously, so finding a gap is not necessary to criticize it.
I don't understand this statement. You are right, this theorem is not a rigorous theorem; it is a FAPP (For ALL Practical Purposes) theorem*. If you like, you may even call it an argument, rather then a theorem. But to criticize an argument, you must find a gap in the argument. There is no other way.

*To explain what I mean by a FAPP theorem, let me give an example: the law of large numbers in probability theory. In the limit ##N\rightarrow\infty## it is a rigorous theorem. But as such, it is pretty useless. It is only useful for a big but finite ##N##, sometimes as small as ##N=1000##. For finite ##N##, the law of large numbers is only a FAPP theorem.
In fact, the FAPP theorem of Bohmian mechanics could also be translated into a mathematically rigorous theorem, but in such a form it would be physically irrelevant. Yes, it would probably make some mathematical physicists happy, but still it would not be much useful for practical purposes.
 
Last edited:
  • #81
vanhees71 said:
Well, our lattice-QCD colleagues are pretty successful with such an approach, however only in imaginary time ;-).
Right. You can also view LQG as lattice quantum gravity with the continuum limit taken.

A. Neumaier said:
But localityisn't conventionally defined in imaginary time ;-(
Well, locality in the Lorentzian (Wightman) setting translates to the symmetry of the Schwinger functions in the Euclidean setting.

Demystifier said:
I don't understand this statement. You are right, this theorem is not a rigorous theorem; it is a FAPP (For ALL Practical Purposes) theorem*. If you like, you may even call it an argument, rather then a theorem. But to criticize an argument, you mist find a gap in the argument. There is no other way.
A rigorous argument is an argument that doesn't have gaps. So if your argument is not rigorous, then it has gaps by definition.

In fact, the FAPP theorem of Bohmian mechanics could also be translated into a mathematically rigorous theorem, but in such a form it would be physically irrelevant. Yes, it would probably make some mathematical physicists happy, but still it would not be much useful for practical purposes.
Mathematical rigor is just a different name for having high standards with respect to ones arguments. This is generally a good thing. Whether Bohmian mechanics reproduces QM depends critically on a specific argument, so one ought to have high standards with respect to it. Since interpretations of QM all (claim to) make the same physical predictions, mathematical rigor is the only possible way to exclude some of them. So requiring arguments to be rigorous is the least we should expect in the interpretations business.
 
  • #82
Well, my only quibble is, what's "practical" about Bohmian mechanics. I've never been able to make sense of the claimed trajectories, which cannot be verified empirically. So what's physics wise the merit of Bohmian mechanics compared to minimally interpreted quantum theory? At best it's a nice academic mathematical exercise to calculate the unobservable trajectories, right?
 
  • #83
Demystifier said:
To explain what I mean by a FAPP theorem, let me give an example: the law of large numbers in probability theory. In the limit ##N\rightarrow\infty## it is a rigorous theorem. But as such, it is pretty useless. It is only useful for a big but finite ##N##, sometimes as small as ##N=1000##. For finite ##N##, the law of large numbers is only a FAPP theorem.
Of course, mathematicians also study, how big ##N## must be in order to have the probability of deviating from the ##N\rightarrow\infty## limit to be sufficiently small.
(See https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Large_deviations_theory )

vanhees71 said:
Well, my only quibble is, what's "practical" about Bohmian mechanics.
Well that seems to be Arnold's point also. Standard quantum mechanics makes correct predictions about the hydrogen atom even without including extra baggage and ending up with a complicated model (of which we don't even rigorously know whether it works, even if we include all the extra baggage).
 
  • #84
vanhees71 said:
So what's physics wise the merit of Bohmian mechanics compared to minimally interpreted quantum theory?
It adds to quantum theory a host of unobservable (and hence unverifiable and unfalsifiable) degrees of freedom to give its believers the illusion that particle have infinitely accurate positions at all times. This comes at the cost of lots of other counterintuitive features:
  • The nonlocal dynamical equations are one of them. (Even Newton considered the nonlocality of his gravitational forces as a defect of the theory.)
  • That in a universe consisting of a single hydrogen atom, the electron stands still is another one.
  • Worst of all, it cannot make any measurable prediction without taking the whole universe into account. Once this is done and its effect is eliminated by statistical mechanics, only ordinary quantum mechanics is left.
For those like me who believe that infinitely accurate positions are an artifact of idealization beyond the reasonable, it has no merit at all.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes rubi, vanhees71 and weirdoguy
  • #85
Hm, QT without Bohm's "extra baggage" describes in great detail how the hydrogen atom works. Its spectrum is among the most precisely described phenomena of relativistic QFT. There's no need for "extra baggage", let alone that's not clear how in the relativistic case one might define its content ;-).
 
  • #86
rubi said:
So if your argument is not rigorous, then it has gaps by definition.
Which does not mean that one does not need to criticize the specific gaps in order to criticize the final conclusion of the argument.
 
Last edited:
  • #87
vanhees71 said:
Well, my only quibble is, what's "practical" about Bohmian mechanics. I've never been able to make sense of the claimed trajectories, which cannot be verified empirically. So what's physics wise the merit of Bohmian mechanics compared to minimally interpreted quantum theory? At best it's a nice academic mathematical exercise to calculate the unobservable trajectories, right?
To paraphrase Feynman, Bohmian mechanics is like sex. Sure, it may have practical applications
https://www.amazon.com/dp/9814316393/?tag=pfamazon01-20
but that's not why we do it.

So why do I do it? Well, for me interpreting QM is like interpreting a magic trick. When a magician pulls out a rabbit from the hat, what do the spectators do? Unfortunately, they cannot come to the stage to explore how the magician really does it. So for a poor spectator there are only a few options:
1) Watch and enjoy the show. (The analog of shut up and calculate for QM.)
2) Accept the minimal interpretation; the magician somehow pulls out the rabbit, and that's all what I can and need to know. (The analog of minimal interpretation for QM.)
3) Interpret it as a true magic. The rabbit was not there from the beginning, but in some moment it was created from nothing. (The analog of true collapse interpretation for QM.)
4) Accept that the magician is really a hypnotist who used hypnosis to make spectators believe they see a rabbit. The rabbit doesn't exist objectively, but only as a spectator's observation. (The analog of qubism for QM.)
5) Try to devise a rational mechanism which could explain it. For instance, perhaps the rabbit was hidden inside the table from the beginning, and perhaps the table on which the hat was sitting has a removable cover from which a rabbit can pass, and perhaps the top of the hat can be removed to allow passing of the rabbit from the table to the hat. Yes, this interpretation involves a lot if hidden variables neither of which can be proved by the spectator. Nevertheless, for a person with scientific instinct who seeks rational explanations, such an interpretation makes much more sense than the other four. (The analog of the Bohmian interpretation for QM.)

The question for everybody: What do you do when you see a magician trick?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes maline, bohm2, zonde and 2 others
  • #88
Demystifier said:
The question for everybody: What do you do when you see a magician trick?
Demystifier said:
for a poor spectator there are only a few options:
1) Watch and enjoy the show. (The analog of shut up and calculate for QM.)
For a poor spectator the entry fee is worth the show only under option 1.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #89
A. Neumaier said:
For a poor spectator the entry fee is worth the show only under option 1.
So you never try to figure out how did he did it?
 
  • #90
Demystifier said:
So you never try to figure out how did he did it?
I am not a poor spactator. I have the thermal interpretation. It is enough to show that particles have an approximate position whenever the state is such that the position can be observed. No hidden variables are needed for that.
 
  • #91
A. Neumaier said:
I am not a poor spactator. I have the thermal interpretation.
Fair enough. And is there an analog of thermal interpretation for the rabbit-from-the-hat phenomenon?
 
  • #92
Demystifier said:
The question for everybody: What do you do when you see a magician trick?

Accept and enjoy that the magician did a great trick and then try and figure out how he did it.
 
  • #93
Where is a abbit-from-the-hat phenomenon in QM that is not already there in classical physics? In a way it's indeed a miracle that we can describe nature quite well with mathematical tools. Someone (Einstein?) said the most incomprehensible about nature is its comprehensibility.
 
  • #94
Demystifier said:
Fair enough. And is there an analog of thermal interpretation for the rabbit-from-the-hat phenomenon?
Yes:

6) Study physics and extrapolate from what the physicists really do when they compare experiments with theory.

This is how I discovered the thermal interpretation.
 
  • #95
Spinnor said:
Accept and enjoy that the magician did a great trick and then try and figure out how he did it.
Does your attempted explanation involve some hidden variables, like those in 5) above?
 
  • #96
A. Neumaier said:
Yes:

6) Study physics and extrapolate from what the physicists really do when they compare experiments with theory.

This is how I discovered the thermal interpretation.
I still don't understand how that helps to explain the rabbit-from-the-hat phenomenon.
 
  • #97
Spinnor said:
Accept and enjoy that the magician did a great trick and then try and figure out how he did it.
Does the rabbit have a definite position before it is pulled out of the hat ? Or is that interpretation dependent ?
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #98
Demystifier said:
I still don't understand how that helps to explain the rabbit-from-the-hat phenomenon.
Without physics, how can you explain the appearance of the rabbit? Physics tells you that mass is conserved (and much more). So you know that the rabbit must have been there before.
 
  • #99
A. Neumaier said:
Without physics, how can you explain the appearance of the rabbit? Physics tells you that mass is conserved. So you know that the rabbit must have been there before.
That still doesn't explain the trick.
 
  • #100
Demystifier said:
That still doesn't explain the trick.
It also tells you that brains are not very reliable detectors and may fail when their attention is somewhere else.
 
Back
Top