What is the relationship between consciousness and the objects we are aware of?

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of consciousness and its objects, specifically the idea that we are conscious of ideas acquired through thought. The question of whether these ideas are subjective or objective is raised, with the conclusion that all ideas are subjective and never identical or common to two individuals. The conversation then delves into the difference between "by which" and "that which" and the idea that we experience perceived things, but never the percepts that allow us to perceive them. The conversation ends with a discussion on the distinction between "objects of apprehension" and "cognitive ideas", with the understanding that cognitive ideas cannot be both the direct apprehension and the means by which we apprehend something else.
  • #1
dekoi
Having recently read a chapter of a book entitled "Consciousness and Its Objects", i have run into some confusion.
The article in its most basic form questions what we are conscious of when we are, well, conscious. It continues to state that we are conscious of ideas which we acquire through thought. Whether ideas are subjective or objective is questioned, and in conclusion, it is stated that, "All ideas are subjective. I have mine; you have yours; and they are never identical or common to us both" Therefore, ideas are in a sense "objects", but have no "objectivity" since they are never shared by two people at the same instant.

Then i run into a roadblock. I then read about the difference between "by which" and "that which". It is stated that ideas are that by which we apprehend everything when concious, not by which we apprehend objects (which is the philosophical mistake in philosophy). It explains:
It means that we experience perceived things, but never the percepts whereby we perceive them. We remember past events or happenings, but we are never aware of the memories by which we remember them.
I don't seem to understand this; if anyone is able to help, thank you.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Anyone ?
------
 
  • #3
Here are some posts I wrote today trying to explain what he was saying. I still have not figured it out, but maybe you or someone else can see where I keep messing up.

I started to answer yesterday, [but I ran into problems and gave up] but it's difficult to tell what he's saying as he seems to use terms inconsistently. Of course, that may just be because I haven't read everything up to that point. I can tell you what I think he's trying to say, but I can't guarantee it will be accurate.

Think of the situation in terms of (X) inputs, (Y) mechanisms, and (Z) outputs. As the first example (1), consider seeing an apple. The input is the apple, the mechanism is your visual system, and the output is your visual image of the apple.
As the second example (2), consider remembering your visual image of the apple. The input is your visual image of the apple, the mechanism is your memory system, and the output is your memory of your visual image of the apple.
So 1X would be "the apple", 2Y would be "your memory system", and so on.

Now, 1Z and 2X are the same thing- your visual image of the apple- but they are in different examples. Try to put them in the same example, (3), as both the input and output: 3X is your visual image of the apple, 3Z is your visual image of the apple, but what is 3Y? He is saying that no 3Y will work in that example- the example is impossible. He is led to that conclusion because he assumes that every one of your experiences is the output of some mechanism that was given some input; It always works the same way: input -> mechanism -> output, X -> Y -> Z. He also assumes that the input and output are never equal in the same example (E); EX never equals EZ. Imagine that EX and EZ are as similar as possible. EZ is EX after EX has passed through EY. So, with another assumption (that passing through the mechanism takes time), EX and EZ are at least separated by time. I don't know how he justifies these assumptions though.

Anyway, it is rather easy to see in situations like the first example, where we are perceiving something "outside" of our brain, that there is some intervening mechanism between the (external) input and the (internal) output. It is rather easy to see that 1X and 1Z cannot be the same thing- there is some intervening mechanism, 1Y. It is this intervening mechanism that makes all ideas subjective.
It may not be so easy to see that the same is true- that there is some intervening mechanism- when both the input and output are internal. But he is saying that such is the case. See the paragraph on the next page that starts, "The answer to that question..."
A cognitive idea (including here percepts, memories, images, and concepts) cannot, at one and the same time, be both that which we directly apprehend and that by which we apprehend something else- some object that is not an idea in our own minds, but unlike our subjective ideas is rather something that can be an object of consideration or conversation for two or more individuals.
Now, "something else- some object..." is EX. "that which we directly apprehend" is EZ, "that by which we apprehend something else" is EZ, and [I ran into problems and started over]

Think of the situation in terms of (X) inputs, (Y) mechanisms, and (Z) outputs. The outputs are what he calls "ideas". He is saying there need to be two levels of ideas- level 1 and 2.
As an example of a level 1 idea, consider seeing an apple. The input is the apple, the mechanism is your visual system, and the output is your visual image of the apple.
As an example of level 2, consider remembering your visual image of the apple. The input is your visual image of the apple, the mechanism is your memory system, and the output is your memory of your visual image of the apple.
So 1X would be "the apple", 2Y would be "your memory system", and so on. Again, 1Zs and 2Zs are both what he calls "ideas". 1Zs are what he calls "objects of apprehension", 2Zs are what he calls "cognitive ideas". The distinction is made by looking at 1Xs and 2Xs. 1Xs are not ideas. 2Xs are ideas.

(I'll use page numbers of the edition on Amazon.) The paragraph on page that starts, "The answer to that question...":
A cognitive idea (including here percepts, memories, images, and concepts) cannot, at one and the same time, be both that which we directly apprehend and that by which we apprehend something else- some object that is not an idea in our own minds, but unlike our subjective ideas is rather something that can be an object of consideration or conversation for two or more individuals.
What we already know, translated:
"A cognitive idea"= a 2Z.
"something else"= a 1X.
"that by which we apprehend something else"= ?
"that which we directly apprehend"= ?
From pages 13-14:
All these [1Zs] are objects of immediate experience. They do not serve as means for apprehending anything else. They themselves are the objects of our apprehension.
With these exceptions noted, all our other ideas can be characterized as cognitive [2Zs]- as instruments of cognition. Instead of being themselves objects of apprehension, they are the means by which we apprehend objects that are not ideas.
So it seems "that by which we apprehend something else"= a 2Z.
"that which we directly apprehend"= a 1Z.
To check this [ran into problems and started over, ran into problems with that one and started over]


Think of the situation in terms of strings of inputs (X), mechanisms (Y), and outputs (Z). Call "X -> Y -> Z" a string. The Zs are what he calls "ideas". He is saying there need to be two levels of ideas: levels 1Z and 2Z. We can accomplish this by defining two levels of strings: "1X -> 1Y -> 1Z" and "2X -> 2Y -> 2Z".
As an example of a level 1 string, consider seeing an apple. The input is the apple, the mechanism is your visual system, and the output is your visual image of the apple.
As an example of a level 2 string, consider remembering your visual image of the apple. The input is your visual image of the apple, the mechanism is your memory system, and the output is your memory of your visual image of the apple.
So 1X would be "the apple", 2Y would be "your memory system", and so on.

Again, 1Zs and 2Zs are both what he calls "ideas", but he makes a distinction between them. 1Zs are what he calls "objects of apprehension". 2Zs are what he calls "cognitive ideas". The distinction is made by looking at 1Xs and 2Xs. 1Xs are not ideas. 2Xs are ideas. (You can also consider the Ys, but I won't go into it here.)

Using the page numbers of the edition on Amazon, from the paragraph on page 15 which starts, "The answer to that question...":
A cognitive idea (including here percepts, memories, images, and concepts) cannot, at one and the same time, be both that which we directly apprehend and that by which we apprehend something else- some object that is not an idea in our own minds, but unlike our subjective ideas is rather something that can be an object of consideration or conversation for two or more individuals.
So what we already know, translated:
"A cognitive idea"= a 2Z.
"something else"= a 1X.

From pages 13-14:
All these [1Zs] are objects of immediate experience. They do not serve as means for apprehending anything else. They themselves are the objects of our apprehension.
With these exceptions noted, all our other ideas can be characterized as cognitive [2Zs]- as instruments of cognition. Instead of being themselves objects of apprehension, they are the means by which we apprehend objects that are not ideas.
and on page
So it seems "that by which we apprehend something else"= a 2Z.
"that which we directly apprehend"= a 1Z.

Giving us so far:
A 2Z cannot, at one and the same time, be both (a 1Z) and (a 2Z with a 1X as input)
Now it seems "at one and the same time"= in the same "X -> Y -> Z" string. In other words, there have to be two levels of strings: 1X -> 1Y -> 1Z and 2X -> 2Y -> 2Z, giving us the two levels of ideas.
[ran into problems and started over- with a different approach]

Using the page numbers of the edition on Amazon, from pages 13-14:"It is necessary to remember that the opposing view does not apply to all ideas, but only to some. Excluded are bodily sensations, feelings, emotions, and, in rare instances, sensations generates by stimulation of our external sense-organs. All these are conceded to be private experiences, in which we are directly conscious of the pain we feel, ... All these are objects of immediate experience. They do not serve as means for apprehending anything else. They themselves are the objects of our apprehension.
With these exceptions noted, all our other ideas can be characterized as cognitive- as instruments of cognition. Instead of being themselves objects of apprehension, they are the means by which we apprehend objects that are not ideas."

From the paragraph on page 15 which starts, "The answer to that question...":
A cognitive idea (including here percepts, memories, images, and concepts) cannot, at one and the same time, be both that which we directly apprehend and that by which we apprehend something else- some object that is not an idea in our own minds, but unlike our subjective ideas is rather something that can be an object of consideration or conversation for two or more individuals.

So we have cognitive ideas (CI) and noncognitive ideas (NI). NI "do not serve as a means of apprehending anything else."and "are the objects of our apprehension" CI "are the means by which we apprehend objects that are not ideas."
[This is where I am now, but I'm stopping for a while- it is driving me mad.]
 
  • #4
Thank you for sharing, but i think you are searching to deep inside a simple question.

I have thought about this more and come up with the following (parts being quotations which i picked out)

Thus, we experience perceived things, but never the percepts whereby we perceive them. We remember past events or happenings, but we are never aware of the memories by which we remember them. We can be aware of the imagined or imaginary objects, but never the images by which we imagine them. We apprehend objects of thought, but never the concepts by which we think of them.

Therefore, cognitive ideas (methods of apprehension) are tools which we are unaware of using, but use nevertheless; thus, these ideas are that by which we apprehend, not that which.

All of these ideas are the means of apprehension, not the objects; that by which, not that which we apprehend.

Those who hold the mistaken view of ideas as that which each individual directly apprehends – the immediate objects of which each individual is conscious – lock each of us up in the private world of his or her own subjective experience
our ideas are representations of real objects; therefore, to say that all ideas are completely private is to neglect the possibility of objective concepts

When ideas are made private by saying they are that which we apprehend, we lock ourselves in two worlds:
o 1.) Physical reality: bodies occupy space, but our belief in the existence of this world is a blind and irrational faith
o 2.) A completely private world. All apprehension and all experience is created by the consciousness of our own ideas
 

Related to What is the relationship between consciousness and the objects we are aware of?

1. What is consciousness?

Consciousness is the state of being aware of one's surroundings and experiences. It includes the ability to perceive and understand the world, to think, and to experience emotions. It is a complex and subjective phenomenon that is still not fully understood by scientists.

2. How is consciousness studied?

Consciousness is studied through various scientific methods such as brain imaging, behavioral experiments, and psychological assessments. Researchers also study consciousness through philosophical and theoretical approaches.

3. What are the objects of consciousness?

The objects of consciousness refer to the things or entities that we are aware of through our consciousness. These can include external stimuli such as objects, events, and people in our environment, as well as internal mental processes and thoughts.

4. Can consciousness be measured?

Consciousness cannot be directly measured, but scientists use proxies such as brain activity, behavior, and self-reporting to study and understand consciousness. There is ongoing research to develop more precise and objective measures of consciousness.

5. What is the relationship between consciousness and the brain?

The exact relationship between consciousness and the brain is still a topic of debate among scientists. Some theories suggest that consciousness arises from specific patterns of brain activity, while others propose a more integrated and holistic view of consciousness and the brain. Further research is needed to fully understand this relationship.

Similar threads

Replies
24
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
987
  • General Discussion
Replies
18
Views
984
  • General Discussion
Replies
21
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
5
Replies
143
Views
6K
Replies
212
Views
40K
Replies
14
Views
957
  • General Discussion
2
Replies
62
Views
11K
  • General Discussion
Replies
4
Views
696
Back
Top