Electrons travel faster than the speed of light

In summary,The "standard" interpretation of quantum superposition is that a system has all of the states within that superposition before it is measured.
  • #1
epkid08
264
1
Is it literally possible for them to be in two places at once?
Is this proven; How is this possible?

I mean, sure they travel very, very fast. Even if they travel faster than the speed of light, it would appear so that they are, but nothing can travel at a speed that literally freezes time [only apparently].

I think this hints more towards electrons traveling though another spatial dimension than traveling though time.
 
  • Like
Likes shakila
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2


An electron is described by its wave function. The wave function is used to find the probability density of the electron, that is, the probability of it being at locations within a certain space. This is because an electron is not a point in the classical sense. It doesn't have an exact location, but a probability density. This can explain why it can be in two places at once. This means that the speed the electron must travel to be in these two locations irrelevant.
 
  • #3


epkid08 said:
Is it literally possible for them to be in two places at once?

No, that is a misconceived term that originates with the sensationalism in the newspapers of the 1930s.
 
  • #4


Crosson said:
No, that is a misconceived term that originates with the sensationalism in the newspapers of the 1930s.

That is not exactly true. The "standard" interpretation for a quantum superposition is that the system has ALL of the states within that superposition before it is measured. This is the common view that has been described in QM (see Phillip Ball's article in May 1st 2008 issue of Nature).

To understand what the quantum–classical transition really means, consider that our familiar, classical world is an ‘either/or’ kind of place. A compass needle, say, can’t point both north and south at the same time. The quantum world, by contrast, is ‘both/and’: a magnetic atom, say, has no trouble at all pointing both directions at once. The same is true for other properties such as energy, location or speed; generally speaking, they can take on a range of values simultaneously, so that all you can say is that this value has that probability. When that is the case, physicists say that a quantum object is in a ‘superposition’ of states.

Thus, one of the key questions in understanding the quantum–classical transition is what happens to the superpositions as you go up that atoms-to-apples scale? Exactly when and how does ‘both/and’ become ‘either/or’?

An electron occupying several locations at once is what the wavefunction is describing in, for example, an H2 molecule, resulting in the bonding-antibonding state. Such a description is consistent with what is being interpreted in all of the Schrodinger Cat-type experiments (i.e. the Delft/Stony Brook SQUIDs experiment where they specifically describe the supercurrent flowing in both directions simultaneously).

So no, this isn't a "... sensationalism in the newspapers of the 1930s..."

Zz.
 
  • #5


Crosson said:
No, that is a misconceived term that originates with the sensationalism in the newspapers of the 1930s.

Yes.

...and I'm aware of the Uncertainty principle, but just because its location is in a designated area, specifically unknown, doesn't mean it's in all places at the same time in that area.
 
  • #6


have you read the other replies? o_O
 
  • #7


ZapperZ said:
The "standard" interpretation for a quantum superposition is that the system has ALL of the states within that superposition before it is measured.

What do you mean in terms of the formalism, 'has all the states'? The state of the system is that superposition, its state is not equal to any of the individual states.

I looked at the Philip Ball decoherence article, and I have studied Josephson junctions and SQUIDS, but I do not interpret quantum mechanics the way you do; it doesn't make sense.
 
  • #8


Crosson said:
What do you mean in terms of the formalism, 'has all the states'? The state of the system is that superposition, its state is not equal to any of the individual states.

The superposition of states where all the orthorgonal states are present in the description of the system has always been interpreted as having those states simultaneously. That's the "paradox" of the schrodinger cat system.

I looked at the Philip Ball decoherence article, and I have studied Josephson junctions and SQUIDS, but I do not interpret quantum mechanics the way you do; it doesn't make sense.

It is not my interpretation. I'm giving the prevailing view of what has been written as the description of superposition. If you look at all the papers, including the Leggett paper that I've mentioned several times, that is the standard interpretation of what superposition means. When someone who does not understand QM and ask such a question, that is what you have to provide.

Whether it makes any sense or not, that is no longer physics but a matter of tastes. I find it to make perfect sense if one abandons the notion of a "classical particle" that has definite physical boundary. So what does not makes sense to you can make perfect sense to someone else. This is what I meant as simply a matter of tastes, so arguing about something based on one's sense doesn't mean anything. Besides, since when has making sense been infallible?

Zz.
 
  • #9


ZapperZ said:
The superposition of states where all the orthorgonal states are present in the description of the system has always been interpreted as having those states simultaneously. That's the "paradox" of the schrodinger cat system.

No, that is the popularization of the paradox. If you read the original paper, Schrodinger is concerned with the transition from quantum superpositions to classical mixtures. He is not talking about how to interpret the superposition state, he is pointing out that quantum mechanics paradoxically predicts superposition states instead of mixtures.

You and I, with the benefit of 70 years of physics since Schrodinger, know that superpositions become mixtures because of decoherence, and so the paradox is resolved.

It is not my interpretation. I'm giving the prevailing view of what has been written as the description of superposition. If you look at all the papers, including the Leggett paper that I've mentioned several times, that is the standard interpretation of what superposition means. When someone who does not understand QM and ask such a question, that is what you have to provide.

I agree that we should provide the standard answer. I don't see you referring to the Legget paper in this thread, so I searched google and of course your blog post on this topic came up:

http://physicsandphysicists.blogspot.com/2006/10/schrodinger-cat-type-experiments.html"

I followed the only link that leads to a freely accessible paper:

http://arxiv.org/abs/cond-mat/0004293"

I read the entire paper, but did not find any evidence to support what you are calling the 'standard interpretation.' All of the wording in this paper is consistent with what I know about quantum mechanics, e.g.

"Here we present the first experimental evidence that a superconducting quantum interference device (SQUID) can be put into a superposition of twomagnetic-flux states, one corresponding to a few micro-amperes of current flowing clockwise, the other cor-
responding to the same amount of current flowing counterclockwise."

Great, they put it in a superposition of both states, (A + B). This is very different from saying they put it in state A and state B simultaneously (again, I wouldn't even know how to interpret the latter within the formalism).

Again from the article:

"Such a superposition would manifest itself in an anticrossing, as illustrated in Figure 1b, where the energy level diagram of two levels of different flux states (labelled
|0i and |1i) is shown in the neighbourhood in which they would become degenerate without coherent interaction (dashed lines). Coherent tunnelling lifts the degeneracy
(solid lines) so that at the degeneracy point the energy eigenstates are close to 1 √2
(|0i + |1i) and 1 √2(|0i − |1i) , the symmetric and antisymmetric superpositions."

In other words, they don't measure the superposition by measuring two currents going in opposite directions, they measure it directly by its properties as a superposition.

Whether it makes any sense or not, that is no longer physics but a matter of tastes. So what does not makes sense to you can make perfect sense to someone else. This is what I meant as simply a matter of tastes, so arguing about something based on one's sense doesn't mean anything. Besides, since when has making sense been infallible?

Making sense is not always infallible, but in contrast not making sense is always fallible. If a particle is in the state:

psi = a*v1 + b*v2

then it does not make sense to say that the particle is also simultaneously in the states

psi = v1

and

psi = v2

Since all three of these states are totally distinct. We already know exactly what state the particle is in:

psi = a*v1 + b*v2

And we can measure all the properties of the particle in this state.

I find it to make perfect sense if one abandons the notion of a "classical particle" that has definite physical boundary.

That's fine, but then you must agree that it is sensationalist to say "the electron is in two places at once" since if it has no definite physical boundary then it has no definite location.

As for your abandoning the notion of a classical particle, this disagrees with the established standard interpretation in textbooks, e.g.

"In QED, the electron is point-like particle." -- Griffiths, Introduction to Elementary Particles

I also think the spread-out electron is untenable. In basic QM you could think of the electron as spread out in the form of the magnitude of its position space wave function, but what do you do in QFT?
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #10


ZapperZ said:
The superposition of states where all the orthorgonal states are present in the description of the system has always been interpreted as having those states simultaneously. That's the "paradox" of the schrodinger cat system.
Zz.

Historically this is not true. See, for example, Kemble's QM text, which was very influential during the 30s. He, as do many other authors, simply uses the conventional interpretation of probability, given the probability measure W*(x)W(x) dV(x). So, interpreting, as you do, a superposition as representing a particle in many positions at once is, in fact, contrary to centuries of common practice in probability theory -- unless you are considering a statistical ensemble (sample space) in which case you can talk about two particles being at the same place at the same time.

How would you compute the probability of a particle being in two places at the same time?
Regards,
Reilly
 
  • #11
Crosson said:
No, that is the popularization of the paradox. If you read the original paper, Schrodinger is concerned with the transition from quantum superpositions to classical mixtures. He is not talking about how to interpret the superposition state, he is pointing out that quantum mechanics paradoxically predicts superposition states instead of mixtures.

You and I, with the benefit of 70 years of physics since Schrodinger, know that superpositions become mixtures because of decoherence, and so the paradox is resolved.

I still disagree that this isn't a standard view, since, again, I've read it way too many times beyond just want Phillip Ball had written. For example:

http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?id=schrdingers-squid
http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/news/2815
http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/print/525

I agree that we should provide the standard answer. I don't see you referring to the Legget paper in this thread, so I searched google and of course your blog post on this topic came up:

http://physicsandphysicists.blogspot.com/2006/10/schrodinger-cat-type-experiments.html"

I followed the only link that leads to a freely accessible paper:

http://arxiv.org/abs/cond-mat/0004293"

I read the entire paper, but did not find any evidence to support what you are calling the 'standard interpretation.' All of the wording in this paper is consistent with what I know about quantum mechanics, e.g.

"Here we present the first experimental evidence that a superconducting quantum interference device (SQUID) can be put into a superposition of twomagnetic-flux states, one corresponding to a few micro-amperes of current flowing clockwise, the other cor-
responding to the same amount of current flowing counterclockwise.
"

But to me, that is exactly saying the same current going in the opposite direction in the SQUID loop. The links I gave above (and I believe there is a News and Views article for one of the papers) interpreted it as such.

Great, they put it in a superposition of both states, (A + B). This is very different from saying they put it in state A and state B simultaneously (again, I wouldn't even know how to interpret the latter within the formalism).

Again from the article:

"Such a superposition would manifest itself in an anticrossing, as illustrated in Figure 1b, where the energy level diagram of two levels of different flux states (labelled
|0i and |1i) is shown in the neighbourhood in which they would become degenerate without coherent interaction (dashed lines). Coherent tunnelling lifts the degeneracy
(solid lines) so that at the degeneracy point the energy eigenstates are close to 1 √2
(|0i + |1i) and 1 √2(|0i − |1i) , the symmetric and antisymmetric superpositions."

In other words, they don't measure the superposition by measuring two currents going in opposite directions, they measure it directly by its properties as a superposition.

But that is the only way to detect such superposition, by either measuring the non-commuting observable, or the non-contextual observable. That's why this isn't a classical measurement where the "unknown state of our knowledge" has no physical manifestation that is measurable. This is also how we know the superposition description is valid. We don't detect an electron being localized at both H atom in the H2 molecule. We do, however, detect the effects via our measurement of the bonding-antibonding state. It's the same thing here.

Zz.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #12


reilly said:
Historically this is not true. See, for example, Kemble's QM text, which was very influential during the 30s. He, as do many other authors, simply uses the conventional interpretation of probability, given the probability measure W*(x)W(x) dV(x). So, interpreting, as you do, a superposition as representing a particle in many positions at once is, in fact, contrary to centuries of common practice in probability theory -- unless you are considering a statistical ensemble (sample space) in which case you can talk about two particles being at the same place at the same time.

But historically, an atom also looks like the Bohr atom.

How would you compute the probability of a particle being in two places at the same time?
Regards,
Reilly

I don't unless you consider the probability density of the wavefunction corresponds to such a quantity. This is no different than the smearing of the position of an electron in an atomic orbital. When 2 orbitals from two different atom hybridized, a single electron can localize itself at both locations when you have significant overlap of those orbitals. Tight-binding band structure calculations employ such a thing.

Look, I have ample problems with such interpretation and I can go on for pages on why I myself do not use such views. However, as I've mentioned in the previous post, it is THE prevailing view that when you have a "superposition of states", that ALL of those states are present simultaneously. The bell-type experiments is different from just a simple classical conservation of angular momentum case exactly because the superposition of the orthorgonal spin directions implies that the projection of the spin direction consists of all the possible spin states before measurement.

Zz.
 
  • #13
ZapperZ said:
I still disagree that this isn't a standard view, since, again, I've read it way too many times beyond just want Phillip Ball had written. For example:

http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?id=schrdingers-squid
http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/news/2815
http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/print/525

All three of these links are popularization articles. I agree that the first article supports your view, containing the following clear statement of what you call 'the standard interpretation':

In the new experiments, an electric current stood in for the cat and flowed both ways around a loop at the same time.

If you found a statement like this in a scientific article, or a graduate-level textbook, then I would be convinced. I too, however, have seen this kind of sensationalism in popularized articles, but I give infinitely more weight to the science I have learned from textbooks.

But to me, that is exactly saying the same current going in the opposite direction in the SQUID loop.
You must admit that the article does not exaclt say this, they use language more carefully to say that the particle is in a superposition, and then they describe the states that make up the superposition, exactly consistent with what I have learned from textbooks.

The links I gave above (and I believe there is a News and Views article for one of the papers) interpreted it as such.

As I said, these are popularizations. I appreciate you taking the effort to find and post them, but they are not definitive sources.

But that is the only way to detect such superposition, by either measuring the non-commuting observable, or the non-contextual observable. That's why this isn't a classical measurement where the "unknown state of our knowledge" has no physical manifestation that is measurable. This is also how we know the superposition description is valid. We don't detect an electron being localized at both H atom in the H2 molecule. We do, however, detect the effects via our measurement of the bonding-antibonding state. It's the same thing here.

I totally agree with this statement, we both know this.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #14


Crosson said:
All three of these links are popularization articles. I agree that the first article supports your view, containing the following clear statement of what you call 'the standard interpretation':

In the new experiments, an electric current stood in for the cat and flowed both ways around a loop at the same time.

If you found a statement like this in a scientific article, or a graduate-level textbook, then I would be convinced. I too, however, have seen this kind of sensationalism in popularized articles, but I give infinitely more weight to the science I have learned from textbooks.

You must admit that the article does not exaclt say this, they use language more carefully to say that the particle is in a superposition, and then they describe the states that make up the superposition, exactly consistent with what I have learned from textbooks.

As I said, these are popularizations. I appreciate you taking the effort to find and post them, but they are not definitive sources.

But textbooks don't deal with such "interpretations". As I've mentioned many times on here, QM must be understood at the level of its formalism. Most of us who are in this field couldn't care less how such a thing is interpreted. I know I don't use such a thing in my daily work. However, when we describe it, this is where we invoke such interpretation. I know for a fact that Leggett himself has used the same words that I did in his seminars to describe what "superposition" implies. I will look again at his J. of Phys - Condens. Matt. paper when I get into work tomorrow and see if he has used it there as well.

Zz.
 
  • #15


ZapperZ said:
But textbooks don't deal with such "interpretations". As I've mentioned many times on here, QM must be understood at the level of its formalism.

I totally agree, which is why I asked you in post #7 of this thread:

" What do you mean in terms of the formalism, 'has all the states'? "

Now I see that you are contrasting the formalism with the interpretation, which I hope you will agree is not something that they do a very good job in the popularizations that you linked (which only matters because that general trend is responsible for the OP asking this question).

Most of us who are in this field couldn't care less how such a thing is interpreted. I know I don't use such a thing in my daily work.

I agree that the phrase "in both states at the same time" does not have any effect on the calculations, and I am glad to hear that you (and, presumably, your colleagues) do not give much care towards what you call 'the standard interpretation.'

However, when we describe it, this is where we invoke such interpretation.

Why not just say 'is in a superposition state' ? Or do you mean when describing to someone who does not know the formalism?

I know for a fact that Leggett himself has used the same words that I did in his seminars to describe what "superposition" implies.

I believe you. It disappoints me slightly, but only in a way that someones politics, etc can detract from my admiration for their accomplishments in science.

I will look again at his J. of Phys - Condens. Matt. paper when I get into work tomorrow and see if he has used it there as well.

Zz, I really appreciate the effort you have put into show me evidence of the standard interpretation. Being familiar with some of your other threads, I know you have an accurate picture of the mainstream thinking in condensed matter physics.

In the future I will give a different response to the OP's question:

Is it literally possible for them to be in two places at once?

This is a widely held interpretation of the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics, but there is no experiment to date that can confirm or deny the claim. In my opinion, this interpretation does not convey the subtleties of quantum superposition, and is excessively sensational.
 
  • #16


In case the OP as been left confused by that debate...
In orthodox QM we don't really talk about the electron "being" in two places at once. In fact, we don't really talk about it "being" anywhere. We say that it is described by a wave function [tex]\Psi[/tex], a mathematical function that we can coerce into telling us the probability that we will find the particle in a particular place, or moving in a particular direction. There are certain kinds of functions called eigenfunctions that describe the particle being in a state that is physically allowed. Arguably the most bizarre thing about quantum mechanics is that most of the time, a particle isn't described by an eigenfunction, but by a linear combination of eigenfunctions; its wavefunction is that function you obtain by adding one eigenfunction to another, each function being multiplied by appropriate numbers so that you don't get probabilities greater than one. A particle described by such a linear combination of "allowed" states is said to be in a "superposition of states", and this is the origin of loose phrases such as "is in two places at once".
That much isn't really controversial (which you may find suprising!). What is controversial is whether or not nature really behaves in the way our maths seems to describe when we aren't looking; whether an electron really exists as some fuzzy, smeared-out field that decides to adopt definite values only when we decide to look for it. The part to which there are the most serious objections is the transition between a superposition of states and the particle we actually measure, a process known as the collapse of the wavefunction. Some people think it is physically real, but argue over what constitutes a measurement- some say it has to be carried out by a conscious observer, wheras some say any thermodynamically irreversible interaction with the environment will do. Some, however deny it, and instead claim that rather than the superposition of the particle collapsing, the observer instead is in a superposition of having measured all the possible values! This is the origin of talk you may have heard of the "many-worlds" interpretation. In one "world" the particle goes through one slit, in another it goes through the other, and the poor observer is split into two duplicates of himself, each identical in every detail except that memory corresponding to whether he believes the photon went through the left slit or the right one.
This may all seem deeply, deeply wierd. It is. Unfortunately (or interestingly, depending on your point of view) the experimental facts are so weird as to necessitate a weird explanation!
 
  • #17


epkid08 said:
Is it literally possible for them to be in two places at once?
If this were true, the electron should be detected in the two places simultaneously, for example the two slits. This doesn't happen.
Another possible interpretation is that the electron "is not" here, or there, or in both places, before detecting it: it "is" where and when you detect it.
 
  • #18


lightarrow said:
If this were true, the electron should be detected in the two places simultaneously, for example the two slits. This doesn't happen.
Another possible interpretation is that the electron "is not" here, or there, or in both places, before detecting it: it "is" where and when you detect it.

I think you missed the point of the question here. It isn't after detection, because the act of detection will produce a classical result (the collapse of the wavefunction). You'll notice that all of the discussion so far has been about "superposition", which is the situation before a measurement. The effects of such superposition are evident in what we can measure indirectly of all those states via things ranging from the bonding-antibonding state and the coherence gap.

Zz.
 
  • #19


ZapperZ said:
I think you missed the point of the question here. It isn't after detection,
I know, and it's just for this reason that I express my personal doubts on the physical meaning of the fact that an electron could be somewhere before detection.
 
  • #20


well..something should be in the place in which you detect the electron..
 
  • #21


Ciokko said:
well..something should be in the place in which you detect the electron..
But this doesn't necessarily imply that the same thing was flying from source to detector through defined positions.
 
  • #22


i mean that something should be there even before the detection, if not there is no reason to decect something in that place
 
  • #23


Ciokko said:
i mean that something should be there even before the detection, if not there is no reason to decect something in that place
"There" where? Can you precise the spatial coordinates?
 
  • #24


if your detector has a surface of detection, my coordinates are precisely "somewhere on that surface"
 
  • #25


Ciokko said:
if your detector has a surface of detection, my coordinates are precisely "somewhere on that surface"
But with "somewhere" you mean in a precise point that we don't know or in every point simultaneously?
 
  • #26


epkid08 said:
Is it literally possible for them to be in two places at once?
Is this proven; How is this possible?

I mean, sure they travel very, very fast. Even if they travel faster than the speed of light, it would appear so that they are, but nothing can travel at a speed that literally freezes time [only apparently].

I think this hints more towards electrons traveling though another spatial dimension than traveling though time.

Another thread hijacked over the typical CI vs. everything else argument.

The answer is you will never find the electron in two places at once. If you find it somewhere, you know with certainty it's nowhere else.

The rest of your post is nonsense (no offense). Unless you're referring to Wheeler's idea that "there is only one electron", which I don't think is what you meant.
 
  • #27


lightarrow said:
But with "somewhere" you mean in a precise point that we don't know or in every point simultaneously?
let's distinguish:
before detection, the electron is in a superposition, so its wave function is in different places simultaneously

after detection, the wave function collapses so we no longer have a superposition and the electron acts like a classical particle.

what i wanted to say in the previoulsy replies is that you can treat the electron's wave function like an abstract mathematical object:
I know, and it's just for this reason that I express my personal doubts on the physical meaning of the fact that an electron could be somewhere before detection.
but something (at least a simple information) should propagate physically, because if not there is no reason to detect the electron.
so, instead of consider the wave function and something else that propagates physically, let's treat the wave function like a physical object.
then, if you don't identify the wave function (of the electron) with the electron itself, this is just a matter of interpretation
 
  • #28


Ciokko said:
but something (at least a simple information) should propagate physically, because if not there is no reason to detect the electron.
But this is different from saying: "well..something should be in the place in which you detect the electron.."
so, instead of consider the wave function and something else that propagates physically, let's treat the wave function like a physical object.
then, if you don't identify the wave function (of the electron) with the electron itself, this is just a matter of interpretation
Which physical meaning would you suggest for the wavefunction, in case you don't identify it with the electron itself?
 
  • #29


lightarrow said:
But this is different from saying: "well..something should be in the place in which you detect the electron.."
no difference at all :approve:

lightarrow said:
Which physical meaning would you suggest for the wavefunction, in case you don't identify it with the electron itself?
actually, i identify the wave function with the electron itself...
 
  • #30


Ciokko said:
Which physical meaning would you suggest for the wavefunction, in case you don't identify it with the electron itself?
actually, i identify the wave function with the electron itself...
Ok, so the electron's mass and charge are dispersed in space according to |psi|^2 or what?
 
  • #31


so the electron, before the detection, acts like a wave...i really can't get your point...
 
  • #32


Ciokko said:
so the electron, before the detection, acts like a wave...i really can't get your point...
That's true for every particle, but it's completely different from saying that the wavefunction "is" the electron.
 
  • #33


The set of possible places you might find the electron is defined by the wave function.

That's all we can say, with certainty, about a wave function. Anything more is interpretation. We can't say the electron "acts like a wave" "is a wave" or any other such hueristic, in any scientifically meaningful way.
 
  • #34


<< That's all we can say, with certainty, about a wave function. Anything more is interpretation. We can't say the electron "acts like a wave" "is a wave" or any other such hueristic, in any scientifically meaningful way. >>

Actually we can say what the electron is or acts like before measurement, in a scientifically meaningful way.
 
  • #35


<< You and I, with the benefit of 70 years of physics since Schrodinger, know that superpositions become mixtures because of decoherence, and so the paradox is resolved. >>

This sounds like nonsense. Can you justify this statement with some physics?
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
38
Views
2K
Replies
276
Views
8K
Replies
3
Views
1K
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
46
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
9
Views
1K
Replies
57
Views
3K
Back
Top