Fastman99 said:
If they were identical quantum particles that were indistinguishable, then yes you wouldn't be able to tell Action A and B would be indistinguishable. With large objects like these balls, you could theoretically be able to tell based on studying the balls closely enough before hand, detecting subtle differences between the three balls.
Earlier you asked "What am I missing here?"
What it seems to me you are missing is the fact that in this discussion Feynman is not talking about
real balls in a
real machine. He is talking about ideal (identical) balls in an ideal machine (that operates in a perfectly uniform gravitational field, with perfect precision and repeatability, without any friction or other energy losses, etc.) There are no such machines. It's a thought experiment. Of course a
real machine could be made to work the same way, within a given precision. And in fact, there is such a real machine! It was built for this lecture, and you can see it http://www.basicfeynman.com/images/chalkboard/4_07.jpg.
Such abstractions are necessary in order to achieve a proper understanding of physics. Without them one is led to fallacies such as Aristotle's, who believed that in order to keep an object in motion, you have to constantly apply a force to it. He drew his conclusion from what he observed in the real world. And that's what people believed for almost 2 millennia before Galileo realized that it was wrong. To reach his conclusion that "A body moving on a level surface will continue in the same direction at a constant speed unless disturbed" Galileo had to make an abstraction (perfectly level surface, zero net gravitational force, no friction or other energy losses, etc.) in character similar to the abstraction Feynman makes in his argument.
You can overcome this kind of confusion by working on physics problems, because in order to solve them, you will have to make similar abstractions. Essentially, it's a matter of learning what things to pay attention to and what things to ignore in a given physical situation, in order to be able to make some analysis of it using the abstract mathematical laws of physics. In this particular case, the color of the balls or quantum mechanical differences between them are irrelevant and should be assumed not to exist, or simply ignored.
Mike Gottlieb
Editor, The Feynman Lectures on Physics
www.feynmanlectures.info
P.S. I will confess that when I first read this argument in The Feynman Lectures on Physics, something about it bothered me too; I was bothered by the statement "(a) First we roll the balls horizontally from the rack to the shelves, (b), and we suppose that this takes no energy because we do not change the height." This bothered me because, clearly, to move the balls at all we have to impart to them some kinetic energy, so how could that take no energy?! The answer is two-fold: (1) it takes no
minimal amount of energy to get the balls moving (though, of course, the less energy we impart, the slower they move), and (2) however much energy is imparted to the balls to get them moving, if we are clever in our design we can recapture that energy when they stop moving! For example, a latched compressed spring could be released to push a ball one way, and another spring could be compressed by the energy of the ball, stopping the ball and latching that spring. Then that spring could be released to push the ball back the other way, etc. Of course, this cycle could be repeated indefinitely only in an ideal machine where there are no energy losses, but that is what is being discussed.